F
^ll&*ay>y^
,:>^C /^/i^^ '^4
'//// //
7/n4V*^ </ '^oal/-
^^iton$ aij^^rtisb ^Mo\)
73mo\\)i Duii^bl. D.D.,LLD.
RicJjarJi Y2er)ryiSloddari>
Mw Rtcbii)oi)6 inarsh.M
t /s??^ pmji y^^^ Dj>lie; D.D.
C[larev)ce OCooh.. t.^rf €(6ilor
yil.ulaltfrl)unne (Jompanu
<5l?€[ aOUOO[;qL'lPR€(5^ \
FRANgOIS PIERRE GUILLAUME GUIZOT.
Photogravure from a tortrait painted by Delaroche.
■^>-^ip^b*A^.
Copyright, 1899,
By the colonial PRESS.
SPECIAL INTRODUCTION
FRANCOIS Pierre Guillaume Guizot was born at Nismes,
the fourth of October, 1787. His father was a dis-
tinguished advocate of that city, who took a prominent
part in the revolution which overthrew the throne of Louis
XVI. In the spring of 1794, having protested against the vio-
lence of the revolutionary tribunal, he died upon the scaffold.
The care of Madame Guizot provided the boy with a classical
education in the schools of the city of Geneva, and at the age
of nineteen he went to Paris to study law. But he had no taste
for the profession, and, with the help of the Minister from
Switzerland, his friend and patron, he devoted himself to lit-
erary pursuits. At the age of twenty-five he was appointed
adjunct Professor of History in the University of Paris, and
two years later accepted the position of general secretary in the
Bureau of the Ministry of the Interior. Henceforth his Hfe was
divided between history and politics, and in both he achieved
the highest distinction.
Let us briefly review his political career. Before he was
thirty he was an active agent in negotiating the terms for
re-establishing the monarchy under Louis XVIII. on the
accession of Louis Philippe in 1830, he was called to assist
in forming a Cabinet and became Minister of the Interior.
Compelled to resign in a few months, he was elected deputy,
and sustained the cause of constitutional government in the
National Assembly. Two years later he was recalled to the
royal counsels as Minister of Public Instruction. During the
few years of his administration he did much for public educa-
tion in France, and it is said that the germinal ideas of all
progress made since are to be found in his suggestions and
enterprises. He reformed the primary schools, and put new
spirit into their conduct by a law which established over ten
thousand primary schools in destitute parishes. He planned
iv GUIZOT
the creation of four universities to be centres of light and
learning for the provinces of France. He made great efforts
for the advancement of historical science and the improvement
of historical teaching. The Society of French History was
founded by him, and he began the publication by the govern-
ment of the great Collection des Documents relatifs a I'histoire
de France.
When the fall of the Cabinet compelled his retirement, he
resumed his literary labors, and in 1836 was elected a member
of the French Academy. It was during this period that he
was invited by the American Government to edit a French
edition of the " Letters of Washington." In 1839, his friends
having been recalled to power, Guizot was appointed Minister
to England. He was the first Protestant sent to England as
Minister since the time of Henry IV. He had written ably
upon EngHsh history. He had been known in politics as a
liberal conservative, a defender of constitutional monarchy
against despotism and radicalism. The reception given to
him was, therefore, very warm. But within eighteen months
he was recalled to enter a new Cabinet. He took the portfolio
of foreign affairs, and for seven years was practically the
leader of the French Government. His rule ended in disaster,
for both his foreign and his home policy were definitely re-
jected by the French people. In foreign affairs he exerted an
influence which in 1845 caused him to be hailed by a com-
petent observer as " the man to whom perhaps more than to
any other it is owing that Europe is now at peace." This
policy of concession was very unpopular in France. But it
was the home policy of Guizot, adhered to with the obstinacy
of unchangeable conviction unwilling to make any adjust-
ment to new circumstances or thoughts, which brought about
his fall from power, and dragged down with him the French
King. The ministry, although continuously supported by a
majority of the Chambers, steadily lost the confidence of the
nation, and this situation made evident the narrow basis of the
French throne.
In 1842, one-third of the members of the Chamber of Depu-
ties were salaried functionaries of the government, and the
representatives of France had been chosen by about 225,000
electors. Ten attempts to change this situation were made in
six years, and lost, in the Chamber of Deputies. Then the
SPECIAL INTRODUCTION v
Opposition organized a popular protest, which in a few months
developed into threatened insurrection. Guizot urged the king
to establish his authority by the use of the army. Louis Phi-
lippe hesitated, and when the streets of Paris were filled with
masses of people shouting " Long live Reform! " *' Down with
Guizot!" he abdicated. Guizot fled to England, whence he
returned the next year.
He retired to his country place of Val-Richer, in Normandy,
and bore his fall with the utmost dignity. Excluded from
politics, he devoted himself to literary labors, to the cause of
public education, and to the interests of the French Protestant
Church. In September, 1874, when he was eighty-six, it be-
came evident that death was at hand. " Adieu, my daughter,"
he said to his child kneeling at the foot of his bed. " Au
revoir, my father," she answered. The dying man raised him-
self on the pillows : " No one is more sure of it than I," he
said, and sank back into silence and death.
Few men who have achieved marked distinction have owed
so little to circumstances and so much to industry and native
ability as Guizot. He won by the gravity of his manners and
the evidences of sound judgment the friends to whom he owed
his early opportunities for distinction. His advancement in
the service of the public educational system of France was
more than justified by his services. His entry into political
life was made natural, and almost inevitable, by the manifest
power of his political pamphlets, and he developed by labor
and practice a dignified and sonorous eloquence which made
Rachel say she would gladly have acted in tragedy with him.
His rise to the head of the French Government was the natural
result of great public services, of unwavering fidelity to his
political principles, and the ability with which he advocated
them.
He won in letters a distinction as great as that which he
achieved in politics. And It is more enduring. Few historians
would include M. Guizot among the list of the great ministers
of France. But still fewer critics would be willing to exclude
him from the list of the great writers of France. It is doubtful
whether he anticipated this result of his labors, or whether
he would have been pleased If he had, for it has been said of
him with some justice that " his books of history were never
to him anything but a means of action, a method of spreading
vi GUIZOT
his ideas." This attitude, perhaps, imposed upon his treatment
of history something of the same narrow horizon which Um-
ited his political usefulness by limiting his political sympathies.
In the great spectacle of European history nothing really in-
terested him except in so far as it contributed to the rise of
the middle classes, and the development of the sort of govern-
ment which gave them the largest political influence. His
writing of history was Hke his political conduct, a logical de-
velopment of his political principles.
The list of his writings is a long one. It includes : " A His-
tory of Civilization in France,'* four volumes ; " Washington/*
six volumes ; " A History of the English Revolution," six vol-
umes ; " Parliamentary History of France," five volumes ;
" Memoirs," eight volumes ; " History of France," five vol-
umes ; " Meditations and Moral Studies," " Shakespeare and
His Times," " Corneille and His Times," " Love in Marriage."
The essay upon the " History of Civilization in Europe " is the
best known and most often reprinted of his works, and shows
plainly some of the marked characteristics of his historical
method. It was written as an introduction to his larger and
more valuable work, " The History of Civilization in France,"
and first delivered as a course of lectures at the Sorbonne in
Paris.
These works of Guizot were introduced to English readers
in 1845 by an article from John Stuart Mill, in the " Edinburgh
Review." He spoke of them as " speculations, which even in
this unfinished state may be ranked with the most valuable
contributions yet made to universal history," and points out
that, on such a topic as the cause of the fall of the Roman
Empire, " the difference between what we learn from Gibbon
and what we learn from Guizot is a measure of the progress
of historical inquiry between them."
If a writer with the capacity of Gibbon, or even of Guizot,
for the constructive treatment of large themes, should write
a history of European civilization now, the diflference between
his work and that here printed would undoubtedly be a meas-
ure of the progress of historical inquiry in the last fifty years.
For the increase of historical knowledge causes the master-
pieces of one generation to be republished with foot-notes for
the next. Many modern historians would question the pos-
sibility of sketching the history of European civilization ia
SPECIAL INTRODUCTION vii
an essay. The increase of knowledge, the change in historical
method, the prevailing taste in some leading schools of his-
tory, would lead many others to criticise the historical work
of Guizot in various respects. But of those qualified to criti-
cise the essay on the " History of Civilization in Europe," very
few would undertake to replace by a better one the only short
sketch of the general progress of European history which has
ever achieved any large measure of fame.
Paul van Dyke.
CONTENTS
FIRST LECTURE.
PAGE
Object of the course — History of European civilization — Part taken
by France in the civilization of Europe — Civilization a fit sub-
ject for narrative — It is the most general fact in history — ^The
ordinary and popular meaning of the word civilization — Two
leading facts constitute civilization: i. The development of
society; 2. The development of the individual — Demonstration —
These two facts are necessarily connected the one with the
other, and sooner or later the one produces the other — Is the
destiny of man limited wholly within his actual social condi-
tion? — The history of civilization may be exhibited and consid-
ered under two points of view — Remarks on the plan of the
course — The present state of men's minds, and the prospects of
civilization i
SECOND LECTURE.
Purpose of the lecture — Unity of ancient civilization — Variety of
modern civilization — Its superiority — Condition of Europe at
the fall of the Roman Empire — Preponderance of the towns —
Attempt at political reform by the emperors — Rescript of
Honorius and of Theodosius II — Power of the name of the
Empire — The Christian church — The various stages through
which it had passed at the fifth century — The clergy exercising
municipal functions — Good and evil influence of the church —
The barbarians — They introduce into the modern world the
sentiments of personal independence, and the devotion of man
to man — Summary of the different elements of civilization in
the beginning of the fifth century 18
THIRD LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — All the various systems pretend to be legiti-
mate — What is political legitimacy? — Coexistence of all sys-
tems of government in the fifth century — Instability in the
condition of persons, properties, and institutions — There were
two causes of this: one material, the continuation of the inva-
sion; the other moral, the selfish sentiment of^ individuality
peculiar to the barbarians — The germs of civilization have been
the necessity for order, the recollections of the Roman Empire,
the Christian church, and the barbarians — Attempts at organ-
ization by the barbarians, by the towns, by the church of Spain,
by Charlemagne, and Alfred — The German and Arabian inva-
sions cease— The feudal system begins 37
ix
X GUIZOT
FOURTH LECTURE.
PACB
Object of the lecture — Necessary alliance between facts and doc-
trines — Preponderance of the country over the towns — Organ-
ization of a small feudal society — Influence of feudalism upon
the character of the possessor of the fief, and upon the spirit of
family — Hatred of the people towards the feudal system — ^The
priest could do little for the serfs — Impossibility of regularly
organizing feudalism: i. No powerful authority; 2. No public
power; 3. Difficulty of the federative system — The idea of the
right of resistance inherent in feudalism — Influence of feudalism
favorable to the development of the individual, unfavorable to
social order 53
FIFTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Religion is a principle of association — Con-
straint is not of the essence of government — Conditions of the
legitimacy of a government: i. The power must be in the
hands of the most worthy; 2. The liberty of the governed must
be respected — The church being a corporation and not a caste,
fulfilled the first of these conditions — Of the various methods
of nomination and election that existed therein — It wanted the
other condition, on account of the illegitimate extension of
authority, and on account of the abusive employment of force —
Movement and liberty of spirit in the bosom of the church —
Relations of the church with princes — The independence of
spiritual power laid down as a principle — Pretensions and efforts
of the church to usurp the temporal power 70
SIXTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Separation of the governing and the gov-
erned party in the church — Indirect influence of the laity upon
the clergy — The clergy recruited from all conditions of society —
Influence of the church upon the public order and upon legis-
lation — The penitential system — The development of the
human mind is entirely theological — The church usually ranges
itself on the side of power — Not to be wondered at; the aim of
religions is to regulate human liberty — Different states of the
church, from the fifth to the twelfth century— ist. The imperial
church — 2d. The barbaric church; development of the separat-
ing principle of the two powers; the monastic order — 3d. The
feudal church; attempts at organization; want of reform;
Gregory VII — The theocratical church — Regeneration of the
spirit of inquiry; Abailard — Movement of the boroughs — No
connection between these two facts 86
SEVENTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Comparative picture of the state of the bor-
oughs at the twelfth and the eighteenth century— Double ques-
tion — 1st. The enfranchisement of the boroughs — State of the
towns from the fifth to the tenth century— Their decay and
regeneration — Communal insurrection — Charters— Social and
CONTENTS xi
PAGE
moral effects of the enfranchisement of the boroughs — 2d. In-
ternal government of the boroughs — Assemblies of the peo-
ple — Magistrates — High and low burghership — Diversity of the
state of the boroughs in the different countries of Europe 104
EIGHTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture— Glance at the general history of European
civilization — Its distinctive and fundamental character — Epoch
at which that character began to appear — State of Europe from
the twelfth to the sixteenth century — Character of the cru-
sades — Their moral and social causes — These causes no longer
existed at the end of the thirteenth century — Effects of the cru-
sades upon civilization 121
NINTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Important part taken by royalty in the his-
tory of Europe, and in the history of the world — True causes of
this importance — Two-fold point of view under which the insti-
tution of royalty should be considered — ist. Its true and perma-
nent nature — It is the personification of the sovereignty of
right — With what limits — 2d. Its flexibility and diversity —
European royalty seems to be the result of various kinds of
royalty — Of barbarian royalty — Of imperial royalty — Of re-
ligious royalty — Of feudal royalty — Of modern royalty, prop-
erly so called, and of its true character 135
TENTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Attempts to reconcile the various social ele-
ments of modern Europe, and to make them live and act in
common, in one society, and under one central power — ist.
Attempt at theocratical organization — Why it failed — Four prin-
cipal obstacles — Faults of Gregory VII — Reaction against the
domination of the church — on the part of the people — on the
part of the sovereigns — 2d. Attempt at republican organiza-
tion — Italian republics — Their defects — Towns in the south of
France — Crusade of the Albigenses — Swiss confederation —
Boroughs of Flanders and the Rhine — Hanseatic league —
Struggle between the feudal nobility and the boroughs — 3d.
Attempt at a mixed organization — States-general of France —
Cortes of Spain and Portugal — English Parliament — Peculiar
state of Germany — 111 success of all their attempts — From what
causes — General tendency of Europe 148
ELEVENTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Special character of the fifteenth century —
Progressive centralization of nations and governments — ist. Of
France — Formation of the national French spirit — Government
of Louis XI — 2d. Of Spain — 3d. of Germany — 4th. Of Eng-
land — 5th. Of Italy — Origin of the external relations of states
and of diplomacy — Movement in religious ideas — Attempt at
xii GUIZOT
PAGS
aristocratical reform — Council of Constance and Basle — At-
tempt at popular reform — ^John Huss — Regeneration of litera-
ture — Admiration for antiquity — Classical school, or free-
thinkers — General activity — Voyages, discoveries, inventions —
Conclusion 162
TWELFTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Diflficulty of distinguishing general facts in
modern history — Picture of Europe in the sixteenth century —
Danger of precipitate generalization — Various causes assigned
to the Reformation — Its dominant character was the insurrec-
tion of the human mind against absolute power in the intel-
lectual order — Evidences of this fact — Fate of the Reformation
in different countries — Weak side of the Reformation — The
Jesuits — Analogy between the revolutions of religious society
and those of civil society 176
THIRTEENTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — General character of the English revolution —
Its principal causes— It was more political than religious — The
three great parties in it: i. The party of legal reform; 2. The
party of the political revolution; 3. The party of the social
revolution — They all fail — Cromwell — The restoration of the
Stuarts — The legal ministry — The profligate ministry — The
revolution of 1688 in England and Europe 190
FOURTEENTH LECTURE.
Object of the lecture — Difference and likeness between the prog-
ress of civilization in England and on the Continent — Pre-
ponderance of France in Europe in the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries — In the seventeenth century by reason of
the French government — In the eighteenth by reason of
the country itself — Of the government of Louis XIV — Of his
wars — Of his diplomacy — Of his administration — Of his legis-
lation — Causes of his rapid decline — Of France in the eighteenth
century — Essential characteristics of the philosophical revolu-
tion — Conclusion of the course 204
ILLUSTRATIONS
FACING PAGE
FRAN9OIS Pierre GuILLAUME GuIZOT . . Frontispiece.
Photogravure from a painting
Banquet of Wallenstein's Generals .... 148
Photogravure from a painting
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE.
FIRST LECTURE.
GENTLEMEN: I am deeply affected by the reception
you give me, and which, you will permit me to say,
I accept as a pledge of the sympathy which has not
ceased to exist between us, notwithstanding so long a sepa-
ration. Alas! I speak as though you, whom I see around
me, were the same who, seven years ago, used to assemble
within these walls, to participate in my then labors; because
I myself am here again, it seems as if all my former hearers
should be here also; whereas, since that period, a change, a
mighty change, has come over all things. Seven years ago we
repaired hither, depressed with anxious doubts and fears,
weighed down with sad thoughts and anticipations; we saw
ourselves surrounded with difficulty and danger; we felt our-
selves dragged on toward an evil which we essayed to avert
by calm, grave, cautious reserve, but in vain. Now, we meet
together, full of confidence and hope, the heart at peace, thought
free. There is but one way in which we can worthily man-
ifest our gratitude for this happy change; it is bringing to
our present meetings, our new studies, the same calm tran-
quillity of mind, the same firm purpose, which guided our con-
duct when, seven years ago, we looked, from day to day, to
have our studies placed under rigorous supervision, or, indeed,
to be arbitrarily suspended. Good fortune is delicate, frail,
uncertain; we must keep measures with hope as with fear;
convalescence requires well nigh the same care, the same cau-
tion, as the approaches of illness. This care, this caution, this
moderation, I am sure you will exhibit. The same sympathy,
the same intimate conformity of opinions, of sentiments, of
ideas, which united us in times of difficulty and danger, and
which at least saved us from grave faults, will equally unite us
in more auspicious days, and enable us to gather all their fruits.
I rely with confidence upon your cooperation, and I need noth-
ing more.
The time between this our first meeting and the close of
the year is very limited; that which I myself have had,
I
}*|S : GUIZOT
wherein to meditate upon the Lectures I am about to deliver,
has been infinitely more limited still. one great point, there-
fore, was the selection of a subject, the consideration of which
might best be brought within the bounds of the few months
which remain to us of this year, within that of the few days
I have had for preparation; and it appeared to me that a
general review of the modern history of Europe, considered
with reference to the development of civilization — a general
sketch, in fact, of the history of European civilization, of its
origin, its progress, its aim, its character, might suitably oc-
cupy the time at our disposal. This, accordingly, is the subject
of which I propose to treat.
I have used the term European civilization, because it is
evident that there is an European civilization ; that a certain
unity pervades the civilization of the various European states ;
that, notwithstanding infinite diversities of time, place and cir-
cumstance, this civilization takes its first rise in facts almost
wholly similar, proceeds everywhere upon the same principles,
and tends to produce well nigh everywhere analogous results.
There is, then, an European civilization, and it is to the sub-
• ject of this aggregate civilization that I will request your
attention.
Again, it is evident that this civilization cannot be traced
back, that its history cannot be derived from the history of
any single European state. If, on the one hand, it is mani-
festly characterized by brevity, on the other, its variety is no
less prodigious ; it has not developed itself with completeness,
in any one particular country. The features of its physiog-
nomy are wide-spread; we must seek the elements of its
history, now in France, now in England, now in Germany,
now in Spain.
We of France occupy a favorable position for pursuing the
study of European civilization. Flattery of individuals, even
of our country, should be at all times avoided ; it is without
vanity, I think, we may say that France has been the center,
the focus of European civilization. I do not pretend, it were
monstrous to do so, that she has always, and in every direc-
tion, marched at the head of nations. At different epochs,
Italy has taken the lead of her, in the arts ; England, in politi-
cal institutions ; and there may be other respects under which,
at particular periods, other European nations have manifested
a superiority to her; but it is impossible to deny, that when-
ever France has seen herself thus outstripped in the career of
civilization, she has called up fresh vigor, has sprung forward
with a new impulse, and has soon found herself abreast with,
or in advance of all the rest. And not only has this been the
peculiar fortune of France, but we have seen that when the
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 3
civilizing ideas and institutions which have taken their rise
in other lands have sought to extend their sphere, to become
fertile and general, to operate for the common benefit of Euro-
pean civilization, they have been necessitated to undergo, to
a certain extent, a new preparation in France; and it has been
from France, as from a second native country, that they have
gone forth to the conquest of Europe. There is scarcely any
great idea, any great principle of civilization, which, prior to
its diffusion, has not passed in this way through France.
And for this reason : there is in the French character some-
thing sociable, something sympathetic, something which makes
its way with greater facility and effect than does the national
genius of any other people; whether from our language,
whether from the turn of our mind, of our manners, certain
it is that our ideas are more popular than those of other peo-
ple, present themselves more clearly and intelligibly to the
masses and penetrate among them more readily; in a word,
perspicuity, sociability, sympathy, are the peculiar character-
istics of France, of her civilization, and it is these qualities
which rendered her eminently fit to march at the very head
of European civilization.
In entering, therefore, upon the study of this great fact, it
is no arbitrary or conventional choice to take France as the
center of this study; we must needs do so if we would place
ourselves, as it were, in the very heart of civilization, in the very
heart of the fact we are about to consider.
I use the term fact, and I do so purposely; civilization is
a fact like any other — a fact susceptible, like any other, of
being studied, described, narrated.
For some time past, there has been much talk of the neces-
sity of limiting history to the narration of facts ; nothing can
be more just; but we must always bear in mind that there
are far more facts to narrate, and that the facts themselves
are far more various in their nature, than people are at first
disposed to believe ; there are material, visible facts, such as
wars, battles, the official acts of governments ; there are moral
facts, none the less real that they do not appear on the sur-
face ; there are individual facts which have denominations of
their own; there are general facts, without any particular
designation, to which it is impossible to assign any precise
date, which it is impossible to bring within strict limits, but
which are yet no less facts than the rest, historical facts, facts
which we cannot exclude from history without mutilating
history.
The very portion of history which we are accustomed to
call its philosophy, the relation of events to each other, the
connection which unites them, their causes and their effects, —
4 GUIZOT
these are all facts, these are all history, just as much as the
narratives of battles, and of other material and visible events.
Facts of this class it is doubtless more difficult to disentangle
and explain ; we are more liable to error in giving an account
of them, and it is no easy thing to give them life and anima-
tion, to exhibit them in clear and vivid colors; but this
difficulty in no degree changes their nature; they are none
the less an essential element of history.
Civilization is one of these facts ; general, hidden, complex
fact; very difficult, I allow, to describe, to relate, but which
none the less for that exists, which, none the less for that,
has a right to be described and related. We may raise as to
this fact a great number of questions; we may ask, it has
been asked, whether it is a good or an evil? Some bitterly
deplore it; others rejoice at it. We may ask, whether it is
an universal fact, whether there is an universal civilization of
the human species, a destiny of humanity ; whether the nations
have handed down from age to age, something which has
never been lost, which must increase, from a larger and larger
mass, and thus pass on to the end of time ? For my own part,
I am convinced that there is, in reality, a general destiny of
humanity, a transmission of the aggregate of civilization ; and,
consequently, an universal history of civilization to be written.
But without raising questions so great, so difficult to solve,
if we restrict ourselves to a definite limit of time and space,
if we confine ourselves to the history of a certain number of
centuries, of a certain people, it is evident that within these
bounds, civilization is a fact which can be described, related
— which is history. I will at once add, that this history is the
greatest of all, that it includes all.
And, indeed, does it not seem to yourselves that the fact
civilization is the fact par excellence — the general and defin-
itive fact, in which all the others terminate, into which they
all resolve themselves? Take all the facts which compose the
history of a nation, and which we are accustomed to regard
as the elements of its life; take its institutions, its commerce,
its industry, its wars, all the details of its government: when
we would consider these facts in their aggregate, in their con-
nection, when we would estimate them, judge them, we ask
in what they have contributed to the civilization of that na-
tion, what part they have taken in it, what influence they have
exercised over it. It is in this way that we not only form a
complete idea of them, but measure and appreciate their true
value; they are, as it were, rivers, of which we ask what
quantity of water it is they contribute to the ocean? For
civilization is a sort of ocean, constituting the wealth of a
people, and on whose bosom all the elements of the life of that
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 5
people, all the powers supporting its existence, assemble and
unite. This is so true, that even facts, which from their na-
ture are odious, pernicious, which weigh painfully upon
nations, despotism, for example, and anarchy, if they have
contributed in some way to civilization, if they have enabled
it to make an onward stride, up to a certain point we pardon
them, we overlook their wrongs, their evil nature ; in a word,
wherever we recognize civilization, whatever the facts which
have created it, we are tempted to forget the price it has cost.
There are, moreover, facts which, properly speaking, we
cannot call social; individual facts, which seem to interest
the human soul rather than the public life : such are religious
creeds and philosophical ideas, sciences, letters, arts. These
facts appear to address themselves to man with a view to his
moral perfection, his intellectual gratification; to have for
their object his internal amelioration, his mental pleasure,
rather than his social condition. But, here again, it is with
reference to civilization that these very facts are often con-
sidered, and claim to be considered.
At all times, in all countries, religion has assumed the glory
of having civilized the people; sciences, letters, arts, all the
intellectual and moral pleasures, have claimed a share of this
glory ; and we have deemed it a praise and an honor to them,
when we have recognized this claim on their part. Thus,
facts the most important and sublime in themselves, inde-
pendently of all external result, and simply in their relations
with the soul of man, increase in importance, rise in sublimity
from their affinity with civilization. Such is the value of this
general fact, that it gives value to everything it touches. And
not only does it give value; there are even occasions when
the facts of which we speak, religious creeds, philosophical
ideas, letters, arts, are especially considered and judged of
with reference to their influence upon civilization; an in-
fluence which becomes, up to a certain point and during a
certain time, the conclusive measure of their merit, of their
value.
What, then, I will ask, before undertaking its history, what,
considered only in itself, what is this so grave, so vast, so
precious fact, which seems the sum, the expression of the whole
life of nations?
I shall take care here not to fall into pure philosophy; not
to lay down some ratiocinative principle, and then deduce
from it the nature of civilization as a result; there would be
many chances of error in this method. And here again we
have a fact to verify and describe.
For a long period, and in many countries, the word civili-
sation has been in use; people have attached to the word
6 GUIZOT
ideas more or less clear, more or less comprehensive; but
there it is in use, and those who use it attach some meaning
or other to it. It is the general, human, popular meaning of
this word that we must study. There is almost always in
the usual acceptation of the most general terms more accu-
racy than in the definitions, apparently more strict, more
precise, of science. It is common sense which gives to words
their ordinary signification, and common sense is the character-
istic of humanity. The ordinary signification of a word is
formed by gradual progress and in the constant presence of
facts ; so that when a fact presents itself which seems to come
within the meaning of a known term, it is received into it, as
it were, naturally ; the signification of the term extends itself,
expands, and by degrees the various facts, the various ideas
which from the nature of things themselves men should in-
clude under this word, are included.
When the meaning of a word, on the other hand, is de-
termined by science, this determination, the work of one
individual, or of a small number of individuals, takes place
under the influence of some particular fact which has struck
upon the mind. Thus, scientific definitions are, in general,
much more narrow, and, hence, much less accurate, much
less true at bottom, than the popular meanings of the terms.
In studying as a fact the meaning of the word civilization, in
investigating all the ideas which are comprised within it, ac-
cording to the common sense of mankind, we shall make a
much greater progress toward a knowledge of the fact itself
than by attempting to give it ourselves a scientific definition,
however more clear and precise the latter might appear at
first.
I will commence this investigation by endeavoring to place
before you some hypotheses : I will describe a certain number
of states of society, and we will then inquire whether general
instinct would recognize in them the condition of a people civil-
izing itself ; whether we recognize in them the meaning which
mankind attaches to the word civilization?
First, suppose a people whose external life is easy, is full
of physical comfort ; they pay few taxes, they are free from
suffering; justice is well administered in their private rela-
tions — in a word, material existence is for them altogether
happy and happily regulated. But at the same time, the intel-
lectual and moral existence of this people is studiously kept
in a state of torpor and inactivity ; of, I will not say, oppression,
for they do not understand the feeling, but of compression. We
are not without instances of this state of things. There has
been a great number of small aristocratic republics in which the
people have been thus treated like flocks of sheep, well kept and
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 7
materially happy, but without moral and intellectual activity.
Is this civilization ? Is this a people civilizing itself ?
Another hypothesis: here is a people whose material ex-
istence is less easy, less comfortable, but still supportable.
on the other hand, moral and intellectual wants have not been
neglected, a certain amount of mental pasture has been served
out to them ; elevated, pure sentiments are cultivated in them ;
their religious and moral views have attained a certain degree
of development; but great care is taken to stifle in them the
principle of liberty; the intellectual and moral wants, as in
the former case the material wants, are satisfied ; each man has
meted out to him his portion of truth ; no one is permitted to
seek it for himself. Immobility is the characteristic of moral
life ; it is the state into which have fallen most of the popula-
tions of Asia ; wherever theocratic dominations keep humanity
in check; it is the state of the Hindoos, for example. I ask
the same question here as before; is this a people civilizing
itself?
I change altogether the nature of the hypothesis : here is a
people among whom is a great display of individual liberties,
but where disorder and inequality are excessive: it is the
empire of force and of chance ; every man, if he is not strong,
is oppressed, suffers, perishes; violence is the predominant
feature of the social state. No one is ignorant that Europe
has passed through this state. It this a civilized state ? It may,
doubtless, contain principles of civilization which will develop
themselves by successive degrees ; but the fact which dominates
in such a society is, assuredly, not that which the common sense
of mankind call civilization.
I take a fourth and last hypothesis: the liberty of each
individual is very great, inequality among them is rare, and
at all events, very transient. Every man does very nearly just
what he pleases, and differs little in power from his neighbor ;
but there are very few general interests, very few public ideas,
very little society, — in a word, the faculties and existence of
individuals appear and then pass away, wholly apart and with-
out acting upon each other, or leaving any trace behind them ;
the successive generations leave society at the same point at
which they found it : this is the state of savage tribes ; liberty
and equality are there, but assuredly not civilization.
I might multiply these hypotheses, but I think we have be-
fore us enough to explain what is the popular and natural
meaning of the word civilisation.
It is clear that none of the states I have sketched corre-
sponds, according to the natural good sense of mankind, to
this term. Why? It appears to me that the first fact com-
prised in the word civilization (and this results from the
S GUIZOT
different examples I have rapidly placed before you), is the
fact of progress, of development ; it presents at once the idea
of a people marching onward, not to change its place, but to
change its condition; of a people whose culture is condition
itself, and ameliorating itself. The idea of progress, of de-
velopment, appears to me the fundamental idea contained in
the word, civilii^ation. What is this progress? what this de-
velopment? Herein is the greatest difficulty of all.
The etymology of the word would seem to answer in a
clear and satisfactory manner: it says that it is the perfecting
of civil life, the development of society, properly so called,
of the relations of men among themselves.
Such is, in fact, the first idea which presents itself to the
understanding when the word civilization is pronounced ; we
at once figure forth to ourselves the extension, the greatest
activity, the best organization of the social relations: on the
one hand, an increasing production of the means of giving
strength and happiness to society ; on the other, a more equita-
ble distribution, among individuals, of the strength.
Is this all? Have we here exhausted all the natural, ordi-
nary meaning of the word civilization ? Does the fact contain
nothing more than this?
It is almost as if we asked : is the human species after all
a mere ant-hill, a society in which all that is required is order
and physical happiness, in which the greater the amount of
labor, and the more equitable the division of the fruits of
labor, the more surely is the object attained, the progress ac-
complished ?
Our instinct at once feels repugnant to so narrow a defini-
tion of human destiny. It feels at the first glance that the
word civilization comprehends something more extensive,
more complex, something superior to the simple perfeccion of
the social relations, of social power and happiness.
Fact, public opinion, the generally received meaning of the
term, are in accordance with this instinct.
Take Rome in the palmy days of the republic, after the sec-
ond Punic war, at the same time of its greatest virtues, when
it was marching to the empire of the world, when its social
state was evidently in progress. Then take Rome under Au-
gustus, at the epoch when her decline began, when, at all
events, the progressive movement of society was arrested,
when evil principles were on the eve of prevailing; yet there
is no one who does not think and say that the Rome of Au-
Eustus was more civilized than the Rome of Fabricius or of
!incinnatus.
Let us transport ourselves beyond the Alps : let us take the
France of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries: it is
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 9
evident that, in a social point of view, considering the actual
amount and distribution of happiness among individuals,
the France of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries was
inferior to some other countries of Europe, to Holland and to
England, for example. I believe that in Holland and in Eng-
land the social activity was greater, was increasing more
rapidly, distributing its fruit more fully, than in France, yet
ask general good sense, and it will say that the France of the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries was the most civilized
country in Europe. Europe has not hesitated in her affirma-
tive reply to the question : traces of this public opinion, as to
France, are found in all the monuments of European literature.
We might point out many other states in which the pros-
perity is greater, is of more rapid growth, is better distributed
among individuals than elsewhere, and in which, neverthe-
less, by the spontaneous instinct, the general good sense of
men, the civilization is judged inferior to that of countries not
so well portioned out in a purely social sense.
What does this mean; what advantages do these latter
countries possess? What is it gives them, in the character of
civilized countries, this privilege; what so largely compen-
sates in the opinion of mankind for what they so lack in other
respects ?
A development other than that of social life has been
gloriously manifested by them; the development of the indi-
vidual, internal life, the development of man himself, of his
faculties, his sentiments, his ideas. If society with them be
less perfect than elsewhere, humanity stands forth in more
grandeur and power. There remain, no doubt, many social
conquests to be made; but immense intellectual and moral
conquests are accomplished; worldly goods, social rights, are
wanting to many men ; but many great men live and shine in
the eyes of the world. Letters, sciences, the arts, display all
their splendor. Wherever mankind beholds these great signs,
these signs glorified by human nature, wherever it sees created
these treasures of sublime enjoyment, it there recognizes and
names civilization.
Two facts, then, are comprehended in this great fact; it
subsists on two conditions, and manifests itself by two symp-
toms: the development of social activity, and that of indi-
vidual activity; the progress of society and the progress of
humanity. Wherever the external condition of man extends
itself, vivifies, ameliorates itself; wherever the internal nature
of man displays itself with lustre, with grandeur; at these
two signs, and often despite the profound imperfection of the
social state, mankind with loud applause proclaims civiliza-
tion.
lo GUIZOT
Such, if I do not deceive myself, is the result of simple and
purely common-sense examination of the general opinion of
mankind. If we interrogate history, properly so-called, if we
examine what is the nature of the great crises of civilization,
of those facts which, by universal consent, have propelled it
onward, we shall constantly recognize one or other of the two
elements I have just described. They are always crises of
individual or social development, facts which have changed
the internal man, his creed, his manners, or his external con-
dition, his position in his relation with his fellows. Christianity,
for example, not merely on its first appearance, but during
the first stages of its existence, Christianity in no degree ad-
dressed itself to the social state; it announced aloud that it
would not meddle with the social state; it ordered the slave
to obey his master; it attacked none of the great evils, the
great wrongs of the society of that period. Yet who will deny
that Christianity was a great crisis of civilization? Why was
it so? Because it changed the internal man, creeds, senti-
ments ; because it regenerated the moral man, the intellectual
man.
We have seen a crisis of another nature, a crisis which ad-
dressed itself, not to the internal man, but to his external con-
dition; one which changed and regenerated society. This
also was assuredly one of the decisive crises of civilization.
Look through all history, you will find everywhere the same
result; you will meet with no important fact instrumental in
the development of civilization, which has not exercised one
or other of the two sorts of influence I have spoken of.
Such, if I mistake not, is the natural and popular meaning
of the term; you have here the fact, I will not say defined,
but described, verified almost completely, or, at all events,
in its general features. We have before us the two elements
of civilization. Now comes the question, would one of these
two suffice to constitute it ; would the development of the social
state, the development of the individual man, separately pre-
sented, be civilization? Would the human race recognize it
as such, or have the two facts so intimate and necessary a
relation between them, that if they are not simultaneously pro-
duced, they are notwithstanding inseparable, and sooner or
later one brings on the other?
We might, as it appears to me, approach this question on
three several sides. We might examine the nature itself of
the two elements of civilization, and ask ourselves whether by
that alone, they are or are not closely united with, and neces-
sary to each other. We might inquire of history whether they
had manifested themselves isolately, apart the one from the
other, or whether they had invariably produced the one the
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE ii
other. We may, lastly, consult upon this question the com-
mon opinion of mankind — common sense. I will address
myself first to common sense.
When a great change is accomplished in the state of a
country, when there is operated in it a large development of
wealth and power, a revolution in the distribution of the social
means, this new fact encounters adversaries, undergoes oppo-
sition: this is inevitable. What is the general cry of the
adversaries of the change ? They say that this progress of the
social state does not ameliorate, does not regenerate in like
manner, in a like degree, the moral, the internal state of man ;
that it is a false, delusive progress, the result of which is detri-
mental to morality, to man. The friends of social development
energetically repel this attack ; they maintain, on the contrary,
that the progress of society necessarily involves and carries
v^ith it the progress of morality; that when the external life
is better regulated, the internal life is refined and purified.
Thus stands the question between the adversaries and parti-
sans of the new state.
Reverse the hypothesis : suppose the moral development
in progress: what do the laborers in this progress generally
promise? What, in the origin of societies, have promised the
religious rulers, the sages, the poets, who have labored to
soften and to regulate men's manners ? They have promised the
amelioration of the social condition, the more equitable dis-
tribution of the social means. What, then, I ask you, is involved
in these disputes, these promises ? What do they mean ? What
do they imply?
They imply that in the spontaneous, instinctive conviction
of mankind, the two elements of civilization, the social devel-
opment and the moral development, are closely connected
together ; that at sight of the one, man at once looks forward
to the other. It is to this natural instinctive conviction that
those who are maintaining or combating one or other of the
two developments address themselves, when they affirm or
deny their union. It is well understood, that if we can per-
suade mankind that the amelioration of the social state will
be averse to the internal progress of individuals, we shall have
succeeded in decrying and enfeebling the revolution in operation
throughout society. on the other hand, when we promise man-
kind the amelioration of society by means of the amelioration
of the individual, it is well understood that the tendency is to
place faith in these promises, and it is accordingly made use of
with success. It is evidently, therefore, the instinctive belief of
humanity, that the m'ovements of civilization are connected the
one with the other, and reciprocally produce the one the other.
If we address ourselves to the history of the world, we shall
12 GUIZOT
receive the same answer. We shall find that all the great
developments of the internal man have turned to the profit
of society; all the great developments of the social state to
the profit of individual man. We find the one or other of
the two facts predominating, manifesting itself with striking
effect, and impressing upon the movement in progress a dis-
tinctive character. It is, sometimes, only after a very long
interval of time, after a thousand obstacles, a thousand trans-
formations, that the second fact, developing itself, comes to
complete the civilization which the first had commenced. But
if you examine them closely, you will soon perceive the bond
which unites them. The march of Providence is not restricted
to narrow limits ; it is not bound, and it does not trouble itself
to follow out to-day the consequences of the principle which
it laid down yesterday. The consequences will come in due
course, when the hour for them has arrived, perhaps not till
hundreds of years have passed away; though its reasoning
may appear to us slow, its logic is none the less true and
sound. To Providence, time is as nothing; it strides through
time as the gods of Homer through space; it makes but one
step, and ages have vanished behind it. How many centuries,
what infinite events passed away before the regeneration of
the moral man by Christianity exercised upon the regenera-
tion of the social state its great and legitimate influence. Yet
who will deny that it any the less succeeded?
If from history we extend our inquiries to the nature itself
of the two facts which constitute civilization, we are infallibly
led to the same result. There is no one who has not experienced
this in his own case. When a moral change is operated in
man, when he acquires an idea, or a virtue, or a faculty, more
than he had before — in a word, when he develops himself in-
dividually, what is the desire, what the want, which at the
same moment takes possession of him? It is the desire, the
want, to communicate the new sentiment to the world about
him, to give realization to his thoughts externally. As soon
as a man acquires anything, as soon as his being takes in his
own conviction a new development, assumes an additional
value, forthwith he attaches to this new development, this
fresh value, the idea of possession ; he feels himself impelled,
compelled by his instinct, by an inward voice, to extend to
others the change, the amelioration, which has been accom-
plished in his own person. We owe the great reformers solely
to this cause ; the mighty men who have changed the face of
the world, after having changed themselves, were urged on-
ward, were guided on their course, by no other want than
this. So much for the alteration which is operated in the
internal man ; now to the other. A revolution is accomplished
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 13
in the state of society ; it is better regulated, rights and prop-
erty are more equitably distributed among its members — ^that
is to say, the aspect of the world becomes purer and more
beautiful, the action of government, the conduct of men in
their mutual relations, more just, more benevolent. Do you
suppose that this improved aspect of the world, this ameliora-
tion of external facts, does not react upon the interior of man,
upon humanity? All that is said as to the authority of exam-
ples, of customs, of noble models, is founded upon this only:
that an external fact, good, well regulated, leads sooner or
later, more or less completely, to an internal fact of the same
nature, the same merit ; that a world better regulated, a world
more just, renders man himself more just ; that the inward is
reformed by the outward, as the outward by the inward ; that
the two elements of civilization are closely connected the one
with the other ; that centuries, that obstacles of all sorts, may
interpose between them; that it is possible they may have
to undergo a thousand reformations in order to regain each
other; but sooner or later they will rejoin each other: this
is the law of their nature, the general fact of history, the instinc-
tive faith of the human race.
I think I have thus — not exhausted the subject, very far
from it — but, exhibited in a well-nigh complete, though cur-
sory manner, the fact of civilization ; I think I have described
it, settled its limits, and stated the principal, the fundamental
questions to which it gives rise. I might stop here; but I
cannot help touching upon a question which meets me at this
point; one of those questions which are not historical ques-
tions, properly so called; which are questions, I will not call
them hypothetical, but conjectural; questions of which man
holds but one end, the other end being permanently beyond
his reach; questions of which he cannot make the circuit,
nor view on more than one side; and yet questions not the
less real, not the less calling upon him for thought; for they
present themselves before him, despite of himself, at every
moment.
Of those two developments of which we have spoken, and
which constitute the fact of civilization, the development of
society on the one hand and of humanity on the other, which
is the end, which is the means? Is it to perfect this social
condition, to ameliorate his existence on earth, that man de-
velops himself, his faculties, sentiments, ideas, his whole being ?
— or rather, is not the amelioration of the social condition, the
progress of society, society itself, the theatre, the occasion, the
mobile, of the development of the individual, in a word, is
society made to serve the individual, or the individual to serve
society? on the answer to this question inevitably depends
14 GUIZOT
that whether the destiny of man is purely social; whether
society drains up and exhausts the whole man ; or whether he
bears within him something intrinsic — something superior to
his existence on earth.
A man, whom I am proud to call my friend, a man who has
passed though meetings like our own to assume the first place
in the assemblies less peaceable and more powerful : a man, all
whose words are engraven on the hearts of those who hear them,
M. Royer-Collard, has solved this question according to his
own conviction, at least, in his speech on the Sacrilege Bill.
I find in that speech these two sentences : " Human societies
are born, live and die, on the earth ; it is there their destinies
are accomplished. . . . But they contain not the whole man.
After he has engaged himself to society, there remains to him
the noblest part of himself, those high faculties by which he
elevates himself to God, to a future life, to unknown felicity
in an invisible world. . . . We, persons individual and
identical, veritable beings endowed with immortality, we have
a different destiny from that of states."*
I will add nothing to this ; I will not undertake to treat the
question itself ; I content myself with stating it. It is met with
at the history of civilization: when the history of civilization
is completed, when there is nothing more to say as to our present
existence, man inevitably asks himself whether all is exhausted,
whether he has reached the end of all things? This then is
the last, the highest of all those problems to which history of
civilization can lead. It is sufficient for me to have indicated
its position and its grandeur.
From all I have said it is evident that the history of civiliza-
tion might be treated in two methods, drawn from two sources,
considered under two different aspects. The historian might
place himself in the heart of the human mind for a given period,
a series of ages, or among the determinate people; he might
study, describe, relate all the events, all the transformations,
all the revolutions which had been accomplished in the internal
man; and when he should arrive at the end he would have
a history of civilization among the people, and in the period he
had selected. He may proceed in another manner; instead of
penetrating the internal man, he may take his stand — he may
place himself in the midst of the world ; instead of describing
the vicissitudes of the ideas, the sentiments of the individual
being, he may describe external facts, the events, the changes
of the social state. These two portions, these two histories of
civilization are closely connected with each other; they are
the reflection, the image of each other. Yet, they may be sep-
* *' Opinion de M. Royer-Collard sur le Projet de Loi reUtif au Sacrilege,**
pp. 7» 17.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 15
arated; perhaps, indeed, they ought to be so, at least at the
onset, in order that both the one and the other may be treated
of in detail, and with perspicuity. For my part I do not pro-
pose to study with you the history of civilization in the interior
of the human soul ; it is the history of external events of the
visible and social world that I shall occupy myself with. I had
wished, indeed, to exhibit to you the whole fact of civiliza-
tion, such as I can conceive it in all its complexity and extent,
to set forth before you all the high questions which may arise
from it. At present I restrict myself; mark out my field of
inquiry within narrower limits; it is only the history of the
social state that I purpose investigating.
We shall begin by seeking all the elements of European civ-
ilization in its cradle at the fall of the Roman Empire ; we will
study with attention society, such as it was, in the midst of
those famous ruins. We will endeavor, not to resuscitate, but
to place its elements side by side, and when we have done so,
we will endeavor to make them move and follow them in their
developments through the fifteen centuries which have elapsed
since that epoch.
I believe that when we have got but a very little way into this
study, we shall acquire the conviction that civilization is as
yet very young; that the world has by no means as yet meas-
ured the whole of its career. Assuredly human thought is at
this time very far from being all that it is capable of becom-
ing ; we are very far from comprehending the whole future of
humanity: let each of us descend into his own mind, let him
interrogate himself as to the utmost possible good he has formed
a conception of and hopes for ; let him then compare his idea
with what actually exists in the world; he will be convinced
that society and civilization are very young ; that notwithstand-
ing the length of the road they have come, they have incom-
parably further to go. This will lessen nothing of the pleasure
that we shall take in the contemplation of our actual condi-
tion.
As I endeavor to place before you the great crises in the
history of civilization in Europe during the last fifteen cen-
turies, you will see to what a degree, even up in our own days,
the condition of man has been laborious, stormy, not only in the
outward and social state, but inwardly in the life of the soul.
During all those ages, the human mind has had to suffer as
much as the human race; you will see that in modern times,
for the first time, perhaps, the human mind has attained a state,
as yet very imperfect, but still a state in which reigns some
peace, some harmony. It is the same with society; it has
evidently made immense progress, the human condition is easy
and just, compared with what it was previously ; we may almost
i6 GUIZOT
when thinking of our ancestors apply to ourselves the verses
of Lucretius :
" Suave mari magno, turbantibus aequora ventis,
E terr^ magnum alterius spectare laborera." *
We may say of ourselves, without too much pride, as Sthenelus
in Homer : —
Hfifis To\ T \T€pup fity' kfifivovfs fvxSfifff tivai. f
Let us be careful, however, not to give ourselves up too much
to the idea of our happiness and amelioration, or we may fall
into two grave dangers, pride and indolence; we may conceive
an over-confidence in the power and success of the human
mind, in our own enlightenment, and, at the same time, suffer
ourselves to become enervated by the luxurious ease of our con-
dition. It appears to me that we are constantly fluctuating
between a tendency to complain upon light grounds, on the one
hand, and to be content without reason, on the other. We have
a susceptibility of spirit, a craving, an unlimited ambition in the
thought, in our desire, in the movement of the imagination; but
when it comes to the practical work of life, when we are called
upon to give ourselves any trouble, to make any sacrifices, to
use any efforts to attain the object, our arms fall down listlessly
by our sides, and we give the matter up in despair, with a facility
equalled only by the impatience with which we had previously
desired its attainment. We must beware how we allow ourselves
to yield to either of these defects. Let us accustom ourselves
duly to estimate beforehand the extent of our force, our capacity,
our knowledge; and let us aim at nothing which we feel we
cannot attain legitimately, justly, regularly, and with unfailing
regard to the principles upon which our civilization itself rests.
We seem at times tempted to adopt the principles which, as a
general rule, we assail and hold up to scorn — the principles, the
right of the strongest of barbarian Europe; the brute force, the
violence, the downright lying which were matters of course, of
daily occurrence, four or five hundred years ago. But when
we yield for a moment to this desire, we find in ourselves neither
the perseverance nor the savage energy of the men of that
period, who, suffering greatly from their condition, were natu-
rally anxious, and incessantly essaying, to emancipate them-
selves from it. We, of the present day, are content with our
condition; let us not expose it to danger by indulging in vague
• ** *Tis pleasant, in a great storm, to contemplate, from a safe position on
shore, the perils of some ships tossed about by the furious winds and the
stormy ocean."
t "Thank Heaven, we are infinitely better than those who went before us."
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 17
desires, the time for realizing which has not come. Much has
been given to us, much will be required of us; we must render
to posterity a strict account of our conduct; the public, the
government, all are now subjected to discussion, examination,
responsibility. Let us attach ourselves firmly, faithfully, undevi-
atingly, to the principles of our civilization — ^justice, legality,
publicity, Hberty; and let us never forget, that while we ourselves
require, and with reason, that all things shall be open to our
inspection and inquiry, we ourselves are under the eye of the
world, and shall, in our turn, be discussed, be judged.
SECOND LECTURE.
IN meditating the plan of the course with which I propose to
present you, I am fearful lest my lectures should possess
the double inconvenience of being very long, by reason of
the necessity of condensing much matter into little space, and,
at the same time, of being too concise.
I dread yet another difficulty, originating in the same cause;
the necessity, namely, of sometimes making affirmations with-
out proving them. This is also the result of the narrow space
to which I find myself confined. There will occur ideas and
assertions of which the confirmation must be postponed. I hope
you will pardon me for sometimes placing you under the
necessity of believing me upon my bare word. I come even
now to an occasion of imposing upon you this necessity.
I have endeavored, in the preceding lecture, to explain the
fact of civilization in general, without speaking of any particular
civilization, without regarding circumstances of time and place,
considering the fact in itself, and under a purely philosophical
point of view. I come to-day to the history of European civil-
ization; but before entering upon the narrative itself, I wish to
make you acquainted, in a general manner, with the particular
physiognomy of this civilization; I desire to characterize it so
clearly to you, that it may appear to you perfectly distinct from
all other civilizations which have developed themselves in the
world. This I am going to attempt, more than which I dare not
say; but I can only affirm it, unless I could succeed in depicting
European society with such faithfulness that you should
instantly recognize it as a portrait. But of this I dare not flatter
myself.
When we regard the civilizations which have preceded that
of modern Europe, whether in Asia or elsewhere, including even
Greek and Roman civilization, it is impossible to help being
struck with the unity which pervades them. They seem to have
emanated from a single fact, from a single idea; one might say
that society has attached itself to a solitary dominant principle,
which has determined its institutions, its customs, its creeds, in
one word, all its developments.
In Egypt, for instance, it was the theocratic principle which
pervaded the entire community; it reproduced itself in the
x8
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 19
customs, in the monuments, and in all that remains to us of
Egyptian civilization. In India, you will discover the same fact;
there is still the almost exclusive dominion of the theocratic
principle. Elsewhere you will meet with another organizing
principle — the domination of a victorious caste; the principle
of force will here alone possess society, imposing thereupon its
laws and its character. Elsewhere society will be the expression
of the democratic principle; it has been thus with the commercial
republics which have covered the coasts of Asia Minor and of
Syria, in Ionia, in Phenicia. In short, when we contemplate
ancient civilizations, we find them stamped with a singular
character of unity in their institutions, their ideas and their
manners; a sole, or at least, a strongly preponderating force
governs and determines all.
I do not mean to say this unity of principle and form in the
civilization of these states has always prevailed therein. When
we go back to their earlier history, we find that the various
powers which may develop themselves in the heart of a society,
have often contended for empire. Among the Egyptians, the
Etruscans, the Greeks themselves, etc., the order of warriors,
for example, has struggled against that of the priests ; else-
where, the spirit of clanship has struggled against that of free
association ; the aristocratic against the popular system, etc. But
it has generally been in ante-historical times that such struggles
have occurred; and thus only a vague recollection has remained
of them.
The struggle has sometimes reproduced itself in the course of
the existence of nations; but, almost invariably, it has soon been
terminated; one of the powers that disputed for empire has soon
gained it, and taken sole possession of the society. The war has
always terminated by the, if not exclusive, at least largely pre-
ponderating, domination of some particular principle. The co-
existence and the combat of different principles have never, in
the history of these peoples, been more than a transitory crisis,
and accident.
The result of this has been a remarkable simplicity in the
majority of ancient civilizations. This simplicity has produced
different consequences. Sometimes, as in Greece, the simplicity
of the social principle has led to a wonderfully rapid develop-
ment; never has any people unfolded itself in so short a period
with such brilliant effect. But after this astonishing flight,
Greece seemed suddenly exhausted; its decay, if it was not so
rapid as its rise, was nevertheless strangely prompt. It seems
that the creative force of the principle of Greek civilization was
exhausted ; no other has come to renew it.
Elsewhere, in Egypt and in India, for instance, the unity of
the principle of civilization has had a different effect ; society has
20 GUIZOT
fallen into a stationary condition. Simplicity has brought
monotony ; the country has not been destroyed, society has con-
tinued to exist, but motionless, and as if frozen.
It is to the same cause that we must attribute the character of
tyranny which appeared in the name of principle and under the
most various forms, among all the ancient civilizations. Society
belonged to an exclusive power, which would allow of the exist-
ence of none other. Every differing tendency was proscribed
and hunted down. Never has the ruling principle chosen to
admit beside it the manifestation and action of a different
principle.
This character of unity of civilization is equally stamped upon
literature and the works of the mind. Who is unacquainted with
the monuments of Indian literature, which have lately been dis-
tributed over Europe? It is impossible not to see that they are
all cast in the same mold; they seem all to be the result of the
same fact, the expression of the same idea ; works of religion or
morals, historical traditions, dramatic and epic poetry, every-
where the same character is stamped; the productions of the
mind bear the same character of simplicity and of monotony
which appears in events and institutions. Even in Greece, in the
centre of all the riches of the human intellect, a singular uni-
formity reigns in literature and in the arts.
It has been wholly otherwise with the civilization of modem
Europe. Without entering into details, look upon it, gather
together your recollections; it will immediately appear to you
varied, confused, stormy ; all forms, all principles of social organ-
ization co-exist therein ; powers spiritual and temporal ; elements
theocratic, monarchical, aristocratic, democratic; all orders, all
social arrangements mingle and press upon one another; there
are infinite degrees of liberty, wealth, and influence. These
various forces are in a state of continual struggle among them-
selves, yet no one succeeds in stifling the others, and taking
possession of society. In ancient times, at every great epoch, all
societies seemed cast in the same mold; it is sometimes pure
monarchy, sometimes theocracy or democracy, that prevails;
but each, in its turn, prevails completely. Modern Europe pre-
sents us with examples of all systems, of all experiments of social
organization ; pure or mixed monarchies, theocracies, republics,
more or less aristocratic, have thus thrived simultaneously, one
beside the other; and, notwithstanding their diversity, they have
all a certain resemblance, a certain family likeness, which it is
impossible to mistake.
In the ideas and sentiments of Europe there is the same
variety, the same struggle. The theocratic, monarchic, aristo-
cratic, and popular creeds, cross, combat, limit, and modify each
other. Open the boldest writings of the middle ages; never
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 21
there is an idea followed out to its last consequences. The part-
isans of absolute power recoil suddenly and unconsciously
before the results of their own doctrine ; they perceive around
them ideas and influences which arrest them, and prevent them
from going to extremities. The democrats obey the same law.
on neither part exists that imperturbable audacity, that blind
determination of logic, which show themselves in ancient civil-
izations. The sentiments offer the same contrasts, the same
variety; an energetic love of independence, side by side with a
great facility of submission; a singular faithfulness of man to
man, and, at the same time, an uncontrollable wish to exert free
will, to shake off every yoke, and to live for one's self, without
caring for any other. The souls of men are as different, as
agitated, as society.
The same character discovers itself in modern literature.
We cannot but agree that, as regards artistic form and beauty,
they are very much inferior to ancient literature; but, as re-
gards depth of sentiment and of ideas, they are far more rich
and vigorous. We see that the human soul has been moved
upon a greater number of points, and to a greater depth. Im-
perfection of form results from this very cause. The richer and
more numerous the materials, the more difficult it is to reduce
them to a pure and simple form. That which constitutes the
beauty of a composition, of that which we call form in works
of art, is clearness, simplicity, and a symbolic unity of work-
manship. With the prodigious diversity of the ideas and senti-
ments of European civilization, it has been much more diffi-
cult to arrive at this simplicity, this clearness.
on all sides then this predominant character of modern
civilization discovers itself. It has no doubt had this disad-
vantage, that, when we consider separately such or such a
particular development of the human mind in letters, in the
arts, in all directions in which it can advance, we usually find
it inferior to the corresponding development in ancient civiliza-
tions; but, on the other hand, when we regard it in the ag-
gregate, European civilization shows itself incomparably richer
than any other; it has displayed at one and the same time
many more different developments. Consequently you find
that it has existed fifteen centuries, and yet is still in a state of
continuous progression ; it has not advanced nearly so rapidly
as the Greek civilization, but its progress has never ceased to
grow. It catches a glimpse of the vast career which lies before
it, and day after day it shoots forward more rapidly, because
more and more of freedom attends its movements. While in
other civilizations the exclusive, or at least the excessively
preponderating dominion of a single principle, of a single form,
has been the cause of tyranny, in modern Europe the diversity
11 GUIZOT
of elements which constitute the social order, the impossibility
under which they have been placed of excluding each other,
have given birth to the freedom which prevails in the present
day. Not having been able to exterminate each other, it has
become necessary that various principles should exist together
— that they should make between them a sort of compact. Each
has agreed to undertake that portion of the development which
may fall to its share; and while elsewhere the predominance
of a principle produced tyrapny, in Europe liberty has been
the result of the variety of the elements of civilization and of
the state of struggle in which they have constantly existed.
This constitutes a real and an immense superiority; and if
we investigate yet further, if we penetrate beyond external
facts into the nature of things, we shall discover that this
superiority is legitimate, and acknowledged by reason as well
as proclaimed by facts. Forgetting for a moment European
civilization, let us turn our attention to the world in general,
on the general course of terrestrial things. What character
do we find? How goes the world? It moves precisely with
this diversity and variety of elements, a prey to this constant
struggle which we have remarked in European civilization.
Evidently it has not been permitted to any single principle, to
any particular organization, to any single idea, or to any special
force, that it should possess itself of the world, molding it once
for all, destroying all other influences to reign therein itself
exclusively.
Various powers, principles and systems mingle, limit each
other, and struggle without ceasing, in turn predominating or
predominated over, never entirely conquered or conquering.
A variety of forms, of ideas, and of principles, then, struggles,
their efforts after a certain unity, a certain ideal which perhaps
can never be attained, but to which the human race tends by
freedom and work; these constitute the general condition of
the world. European civilization is, therefore, the faithful
image of the world: like the course of things in the world,
it is neither narrow, exclusive, nor stationary. For the first
time, I believe, the character of specialty has vanished from
civilization ; for the first time it is developed as variously, as
richly, as laboriously, as the great drama of the universe.
European civilization has entered, if we may so speak, into
the eternal truth, into the plan of Providence; it progresses
according to the intentions of God. This is the rational ac-
count of its superiority.
I am desirous that this fundamental and distinguishing char-
acter of European civilization should continue present to your
minds during the course of our labors. At present I can only
make the affirmation: the development of facts must furnish
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 23
the proof. It will, nevertheless, you will agree, be a strong con-
firmation of my assertion, if we find, even in the cradle of our
civilization, the causes and the elements of the character which
I have just attributed to it: if, at the moment of its birth, at
the moment of the fall of the Roman Empire, we recognize
in the state of the world, in the facts that, from the earliest
times, have concurred to form European civilization, the prin-
ciple of this agitated but fruitful diversity which distinguishes
it. I am about to attempt this investigation. I shall examine
the condition of Europe at the fall of the Roman Empire, and
seek to discover, from institutions, creeds, ideas, and senti-
ments, what were the elements bequeathed by the ancient to
the modern world. If, in these elements, we shall already
find impressed the character which I have just described, it
will have acquired with you, from this time forth, a high degree
of probability.
First of all, we must clearly represent to ourselves the nature
of the Roman Empire, and how it was formed.
Rome was, in its origin, only a municipality, a corporation.
The government of Rome was merely the aggregate of the
institutions which were suited to a population confined within
the walls of a city: these were municipal institutions, that is
their distinguishing character.
This was not the case with Rome only. If we turn our atten-
tion to Italy, at this period, we find around Rome nothing but
towns. That which was then called a people was simply a
confederation of towns. The Latin people was a confederation
of Latin towns. The Etruscans, the Samnites, the Sabines, the
people of Graecia Magna, may all be described in the same
terms.
There was, at this time, no coimtry — that is to say, the coun-
try was wholly unlike that which at present exists ; it was cul-
tivated, as was necessary, but it was uninhabited. The pro-
prietors of lands were the inhabitants of the towns. They
went forth to superintend their country properties, and often
took with them a certain number of slaves ; but that which
we at present call the country, that thin population — sometimes
in isolated habitations, sometimes in villages — which every-
where covers the soil, was a fact almost unknown in ancient
Italy.
When Rome extended itself, what did she do? Follow
history, and you will see that she conquered or founded towns ;
it was against towns that she fought, with towns that she con-
tracted alliances ; it was also into towns that she sent
colonies. The history of the conquest of the world by Rome
is the history of the conquest and foundation of a great number
of towns. In the East, the extension of Roman dominion does
24 GUIZOT
not carry altogether this aspect: the population there was
otherwise distributed than in the West — it was much less con-
centrated in towns. But as we have to do here with the Euro-
pean population, what occurred in the East is of little interest
to us.
Confining ourselves to the West, we everywhere discover
the fact to which I have directed your attention. In Gaul, in
Spain, you meet with nothing but towns. At a distance from
the towns, the territory is covered with marshes and forests.
Examine the character of the Roman monuments, of the Roman
roads. You have great roads, which reach from one city to an-
other; the multiplicity of minor roads, which now cross the
country in all directions, was then unknown ; you have nothing
resembling that countless number of villages, country seats
and churches, which have been scattered over the country
since the middle ages. Rome has left us nothing but im-
mense monuments, stamped with the municipal character, and
destined for a numerous population collected upon one spot.
Under whatever point of view you consider the Roman world,
you will find this almost exclusive preponderance of towns,
and the social non-existence of the country.
This municipal character of the Roman world evidently
rendered unity, the social bond of a great state, extremely
difficult to establish and maintain. A municipality like Rome
had been able to conquer the world, but it was much less easy
to govern and organize it. Thus, when the work appeared
completed, when all the West, and a great part of the East,
had fallen under Roman dominion, you behold this prodigious
number of cities, of little states, made for isolation and in-
dependence, disunite, detach themselves, and escape, so to speak,
in all directions. This was one of the causes which rendered
necessary the Empire, a form of government more concen-
trated, more capable of holding together elements so slightly
coherent. The Empire endeavored to introduce unity and
combination into this scattered society. It succeeded up to a
certain point. It was between the reigns of Augustus and Dio-
cletian that, at the same time that civil legislation developed
itself, there became established the vast system of administra-
tive despotism which spread over the Roman world a net-
work of functionaries, hierarchically distributed, well linked
together, both among themselves and with the imperial court,
and solely applied to rendering eflFective in society the will of
power, and in transferring to power the tributes and energies
of society.
And not only did this system succeed in rallying and in hold-
ing together the elements of the Roman world, but the idea of
despotism, of central power, penetrated minds with a singular
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 25
facility. We are astonished to behold rapidly prevailing through-
out this ill-united assemblage of petty republics, this association
of municipalities, a reverence for the imperial majesty alone,
august and sacred. The necessity of establishing some bond
between all these portions of the Roman world must have been
very pressing, to insure so easy an access to the mind for the
faith and almost the sentiments of despotism.
It was with these creeds, with this administrative organization,
and with the military organization which was combined with it,
that the Roman Empire struggled against the dissolution at
work inwardly, and against the invasion of the barbarians from
without. It struggled for a long time, in a continual state of
decay, but always defending itself. At last a moment came in
which dissolution prevailed; neither the skill of despotism nor
the indifference of servitude sufficed to support this huge body.
In the fourth century it everywhere disunited and dismembered
itself; the barbarians entered on all sides; the provinces no
longer resisted, no longer troubled themselves concerning the
general destiny. At this time a singular idea suggested itself
to some of the emperors; they desired to try whether hopes of
general liberty, a confederation — a system analogous to that
which, in the present day, we call representative government —
would not better defend the unity of the Roman Empire than
despotic administration. Here is a rescript of Honorius and
Theodosius, the younger, addressed, in the year 418, to the pre-
fect of Gaul, the only purpose of which was to attempt to estab-
lish in the south of Gaul a sort of representative government,
and, with its aid, to maintain the unity of the Empire.
" Rescript of the emperors Honorius and Theodosius the
younger, addressed, in the year 418, to the prefect of the
Gauls, sitting in the town of Aries.
" Honorius and Theodosius, Augusti, to Agricola, prefect of
the Gauls:
" Upon the satisfactory statement that your Magnificence has
made to us, among other information palpably advantageous to
the state, we decree the force of the law in perpetuity to the
following ordinances, to which the inhabitants of our seven
provinces will owe obedience, they being such that they them-
selves might have desired and demanded them. Seeing that
persons in office, or special deputies from motives of public or
private utility, not only from each of the provinces, but also from
every town, often present themselves before your Magnificence,
either to render accounts or to treat of things relative to the
interest of proprietors, we have judged that it would be a season-
able and profitable thing that, from the date of the present year,
26 GUIZOT
there should be annually, at a fixed time, an assemblage held in
the metropolis — that is, in the town of Aries, for the inhabitants
of the seven provinces. By this institution we have in view to
provide equally for general and particular interests. In the first
place, by the meeting of the most notable of the inhabitants in
the illustrious presence of the prefect, if motives of public order
have not called him elsewhere, the best possible information may
be gained upon every subject under deliberation. Nothing of
that which will have been treated of and decided upon, after a
ripe consideration, will escape the knowledge of any of the
provinces, and those who shall not have been present at the
assembly will be bound to follow the same rules of justice and
equity. Moreover, in ordaining that an annual assembly be held
in the city of Constantine.* we believe that we are doing a thing
not only advantageous to the public good, but also adapted to
multiply social relations. Indeed, the city is so advantageously
situated, strangers come there in such numbers, and it enjoys
such an extensive commerce, that everything finds its way there
which grows or is manufactured in other places. All admirable
things that the rich East, perfumed Arabia, delicate Assyria,
fertile Africa, beautiful Spain, valiant Gaul produce, abound in
this place with such profusion, that whatever is esteemed
magnificent in the various parts of the world seems there the
produce of the soil. Besides, the junction of the Rhone with
the Tuscan sea approximates and renders almost neighbors
those countries which the first traverses, and the second bathes
in its windings. Thus, since the entire earth places at the
service of this city all that it has most worthy — since the peculiar
productions of all countries are transported hither by land, by
sea, and by the course of rivers, by help of sails, of oars, and of
wagons — how can our Gaul do otherwise than behold a benefit
in the command which we give to convoke a public assembly in
a city, wherein are united, as it were, by the gift of God, all the
enjoyments of life, and all the facilities of commerce ?
" The illustrious prefect Petronius,t through a laudable and
reasonable motive, formerly commanded that this custom should
be observed ; but as the practice thereof was interrupted by the
confusion of the times, and by the reign of usupers, we have
resolved to revive it in vigor by the authority of our wisdom.
Thus, then, dear and beloved cousin Agricola, your illustrious
Magnificence, conforming yourself to our present ordinance,
and to the custom established by your predecessors, will cause
to be observed throughout the provinces the following rules:
* Constantine the Great had a smgular liking for the town of Aries. It was
he who established there the seat of the Gaulish prefecture ; he desired also that
it should bear his name, but custom prevailed ajjainst his wish.
f Petronius was prefect of the Gauls between the years 402 and 408.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 27
" * Let all persons who are honored with public functions, or
who are proprietors of domains, and all judges of provinces, be
informed that, each year, they are to assemble in council in the
city of Aries, between the ides of August and those of September,
the days of convocation and of sitting being determined at their
pleasure.
" ' Novem Populinia and the second Aquitaine, being the most
distant provinces, should their judges be detained by indispen-
sable occupations, may send deputies in their place, according
to custom.
" ' Those who shall neglect to appear at the place assigned and
at the time appointed, shall pay a fine, which for the judges,
shall be five pounds of gold, and three pounds for the members
of the curicB'^ and other dignitaries.'
'* We propose, by this means, to confer great advantages and
favor on the inhabitants of our provinces. We feel, also, assured
of adding to the ornaments of the city of Aries, to the fidehty of
which we are so much indebted, according to our brother and
patrician, f
" Given on the 15th of the calends of May; received at Aries
on the loth of the calends of June."
The provinces and the towns refused the benefit; no one would
nominate the deputies, no one would go to Aries. Central-
ization and unity were contrary to the primitive character of
that society; the local and munificent spirit reappeared every-
where, and the impossibility of reconstituting a general society
or country became evident. The towns confined themselves,
each to its own walls and its own affairs, and the empire fell
because none wished to be of the empire, because citizens
desired to be only of their own city. Thus we again discover,
at the fall of the Roman Empire, the same fact which we have
detected in the cradle of Rome, namely, the predominance of the
municipal form and spirit. The Roman world had returned to
its first condition; towns had constituted it; it dissolved; and
towns remained.
In the municipal system we see what ancient Roman civili-
zation has bequeathed to modern Europe ; that system was very
irregular, much weakened and far inferior, no doubt, to what
it had been in earlier times; but, nevertheless, the only real, the
only constituted system which had outlived all the elements of
the Roman world.
When I say alone I make a mistake. Another fact, another
idea equally survived; the idea of the empire, the name of em-
* The municipal bodies of Roman towns were called curicB, and the members
of those bodies, who were very numerous, were called curiales.
t Constantine, the second husband of Placidius, whom Honorius had chosen
for colleague in 421.
28 GUIZOT
peror, the idea of imperial majesty, of an absolute and sacred
power attached to the name of emperor. These are the elements
which Rome has transmitted to European civilization ; upon one
hand, the municipal system, its habits, rules, precedents, the
principle of freedom; on the other, a general and uniform civil
legislation, the idea of absolute power, of sacred majesty, of the
emperor, the principle of order and subjection.
But there was formed at the same time, in the heart of the
Roman society, a society of a very diflferent nature, founded
upon totally diflferent principles, animated by diflferent senti-
ments, a society which was about to infuse into modern Euro-
pean society elements of a character wholly diflferent ; I speak of
the Christian Church. I say the Christian church, and not
Christianity. At the end of the fourth and at the beginning of
the fifth century Christianity was no longer merely an individual
belief, it was an institution ; it was constituted ; it had its govern-
ment, a clergy, an hierarchy calculated for the diflferent functions
of the clergy, revenues, means of independent action, rallying
points suited for a great society, provincial, national and general
councils, and the custom of debating in common upon the
afifairs of the society. In a word, Christianity, at this epoch, was
v/ not only a religion, it was also a church.
Had it not been a church I cannot say what might have
happened to it amid the fall of the Roman Empire. I confine
myself to simply human considerations; I put aside every ele-
ment which is foreign to the natural consequences of natural
facts; had Christianity been, as in the earlier times, no more than
a belief, a sentiment, an individual conviction, we may believe
that it would have sunk amidst the dissolution of the empire and
the invasion of the barbarians. In later times, in Asia and in all
the north of Africa, it sunk under an invasion of the same nature,
under the invasion of the Moslem barbarians; it sunk then,
although it subsisted in the form of an institution, or constituted
church. With much more reason might the same thing have
happened at the moment of the fall of the Roman Empire. There
existed, at that time, none of those means by which, in the
present day, moral influences establish themselves or oflfer resist-
ance, independently of institutions; none of those means whereby
a pure truth, a pure idea obtains a great empire over minds,
governs actions and determines events. Nothing of the kind
existed in the fourth century to give a like authority to ideas and
to personal sentiments. It is clear that a society strongly organ-
ized and strongly governed was indispensable to struggle against
such a disaster, and to issue victorious from such a storm. I do
not think that I say more than the truth in aflfirming that at the
end of the fourth and the commencement of the fifth centuries
it was the Christian church that saved Christianity; it was the
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE
29
church with its institutions, its magistrates and its power, that
vigorously resisted the internal dissolution of the empire and
barbarism ; that conquered the barbarians and became the bond,
the medium and the principle of civilization between the Roman
and barbarian worlds. It is, then, the condition of the church
rather than that of religion, properly so called, that we must look
to in order to discover what Christianity has, since then, added
to modern civilization, and what new elements it has introduced
therein. What was the Christian church at that period?
When we consider, always under a purely human point of
view, the various revolutions which have accomplished them-
selves during the development of Christianity, from the time of
its origin up to the fifth century; if, I repeat, we consider it
simply as a community and not as a religious creed, we find that
It passed through three essentially different states.
In the very earliest period, the Christian society presents itself
as a simple association of a common creed and common senti-
ments; the first Christians united to enjoy together the same
emotions, and the same religious convictions. We find among
them no system of determinate doctrines, no rules, no discipline,
no body of magistrates.
Of course, no society, however newly born, however weakly
constituted it may be, exists without a moral power which
animates and directs it. In the various Christian congregations
there were men who preached, taught and morally governed the
congregation, but there was no formal magistrate, no recognized
discipline; a simple association caused by a community of creed
and sentiments was the primitive condition of the Christian
society.
In proportion as it advanced — and very speedily, since traces
are visible in the earliest monuments — a body of doctrines, of
rules, of discipline, and of magistrates, began to appear; one
kind of magistrates were called Trpecr/Svrepoiy or ancients, who
became the priests; another, CTria-fjiO'iroi, or inspectors, or
superintendents, who became bishops ; a third Btafiovoi, or
deacons, who were charged with the care of the poor, and with
the distribution of alms.
It is scarcely possible to determine what were the precise
functions of these various magistrates ; the line of demarcation
was probably very vague and variable, but what is clear is that
an establishment was organized. Still, a peculiar character pre-
vails in this second period : the preponderance and rule belonged
to the body of the faithful. It was the body of the faithful which
prevailed, both as to the choice of functionaries, and as to the
adoption of discipline, and even doctrine. The church govern-
ment and the Christian people were not as yet separated. They
did not exist apart from, and independently of, one another;
30
GUIZOT
and the Christian people exercised the principal influence in the
society.
In the third period all was different. A clergy existed who
were distinct from the people ; a body of priests who had their
own riches, jurisdiction, and peculiar constitution ; in a word, an
entire government, which in itself was a complete society, a
society provided with all the means of existence, independently
of the society to which it had reference, and over which it ex-
tended its influence. Such was the third stage of the constitu-
tion of the Christian church ; such was the form in which it ap-
peared at the beginning of the fifth century. The government
was not completely separated from the people ; there has never
been a parallel kind of government, and less in religious matters
than in any others ; but in the relations of the clergy to the faith-
ful, the clergy ruled almost without control.
The Christian clergy had moreover another and very different
source of influence. The bishops and the priests became the
principal municipal magistrates. You have seen, that of the
Roman Empire there remained, properly speaking, nothing but
the municipal system. It had happened, from the vexations of
despotism and the ruin of the towns, that the curiales, or mem-
bers of the municipal bodies, had become discouraged and
apathetic; on the contrary, the bishops, and the body of priests,
full of life and zeal, offered themselves naturally for the super-
intendence and direction of all matters. We should be wrong
to reproach them for this, to tax them with usurpation; it was
all in the natural course of things; the clergy alone were morally
strong and animated ; they became everywhere powerful. Such
is the law of the universe.
The marks of this revolution are visible in all the legislation
of the emperors at this period. If you open the code, either of
Theodosius or of Justinian, you will find numerous regulations
which remit municipal affairs to the clergy and the bishops.
Here are some of them :
''Cod. Just. I. I, tit. IV., de episcopali audientid. § 26. —
With respect to the yearly affairs of cities, whether they concern
the ordinary revenues of the city, either from funds arising from
the property of the city, or from private gifts or legacies, or from
any other source; whether public works, or depots of provisions,
or aqueducts, or the maintenance of baths, or ports, or the con-
struction of walls or towers, or the repairing of bridges or roads,
or trials in which the city may be engaged in reference to public
or private interests, we ordain as follows : The very pious bishop
and three notables chosen from among the first men of the city,
shall meet together; they shall, each year, examine the works
done; they shall take care that those who conduct them, or who
have conducted them, shall regulate them, with precision, render
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 31
their accounts, and show that they have duly performed their
engagements in the administration, whether of the pubUc monu-
ments, or of the sums appointed for provisions or baths, or of
expenses in the maintenance of roads, aqueducts, or any other
work.
''Ibid. § 30. — With regard to the guardianship of young
persons of the first or second age, and of all those for whom the
law appoints guardians, if their fortune does not exceed 500
aurei, we ordain that the nomination of the president of the
province shall not be waited for, as this gives rise to great
expenses, particularly if the said president do not reside in the
city in which it is necessary to provide the guardianship. The
nomination of guardians shall in such case be made by the
magistrate of the city ... in concert with the very pious
bishop and other person or persons invested with public offices,
if there be more than one.
" Ibid I. I, tit. LV., de defensoribus. § 8. — We desire that
the defenders of the cities, being well instructed in the holy
mysteries of the orthodox faith, be chosen and instituted by the
venerable bishops, the priests, the notables, the proprietors, and
the curiales. As regards their installation, it shall be referred to
the glorious power of the pretorian prefect, in order that their
authority may have infused into it more solidity and vigor from
the letters of admission of his Magnificence."
I might cite a great number of other laws, and you would
everywhere meet with the fact which I have mentioned; between
the municipal system of the Romans, and that of the middle
ages, the municipal-ecclesiastic system interposed; the prepon-
derance of the clergy in the affairs of the city succeeded that of
the ancient municipal magistrates, and preceded the organi-
zation of the modern municipal corporations.
You perceive what prodigious power was thus obtained by
the Christian church, as well by its own constitution as by its
influence upon the Christian people, and by the part which it
took in civil affairs. Thus, from that epoch, it powerfully
assisted in forming the character and furthering the develop-
ment of modern civilization. Let us endeavor to sum up the
elements which it from that time introduced into it.
And first of all there was an immense advantage in the
presence of a moral influence, of a moral power, of a power
which reposed solely upon convictions and upon moral creeds
and sentiments, amidst the deluge of material power which at
this time inundated society. Had the Christian church not
existed, the whole world must have been abandoned to purely
material force. The church alone exercised a moral power. It
did more; it sustained, it spread abroad the idea of a rule, of a
law superior to all human laws. It proposed for the salvation
32 GUIZOT
of humanity the fundamental belief that there exists, above all
human laws, a law which is denominated, according to periods
and customs, sometimes reason, sometimes the divine law, but
which, everywhere and always, is the same law under different
names.
In short, with the church originated a great fact, the separation
of spiritual and temporal power. This separation is the source
of liberty of conscience; it is founded upon no other principle
but that which is the foundation of the most perfect and extended
freedom of conscience. The separation of temporal and spirit-
ual power is based upon the idea that physical force has neither
right nor influence over souls, over conviction, over truth. It
flows from the distinction established between the world of
thought and the world of action, between the world of internal
and that of external facts. Thus this principle of liberty of con-
science for which Europe has struggled so much, and suflfered
so much, this principle which prevailed so late, and often, in its
progress, against the inclination of the clergy, was enunciated,
under the name of the separation of temporal and spiritual
power, in the very cradle of European civilization; and it was
the Christian church which, from the necessity imposed by its
situation of defending itself against barbarism, introduced and
maintained it.
' The presence, then, of a moral influence, the maintenance of
a divine law, and the separation of the temporal and spiritual
powers, are the three grand benefits which the Christian church
in the fifth century conferred upon the European world.
Even at that time, however, all its influences were not equally
salutary. Already, in the fifth century, there appeared in the
church certain unwholesome principles, which have played a
great part in the development of our civilization. Thus, at this
period, there prevailed within it the separation of governors and
the governed, the attempt to establish the independence of
*--^overnors as regards the governed, to impose laws upon the
governed, to possess their mind, their life, without the free con-
sent of their reason and of their will. The church, moreover,
endeavored to render the theocratic principle predominant in
society, to usurp the temporal power, to reign exclusively. And
when it could not succeed in obtaining temporal dominion, in
inducing the prevalence of the theocratic principle, it allied itself
with temporal princes, and, in order to share, supported their
absolute power at the expense of the liberty of the people.
Such were the principles of civilization which Europe, in the
fifth century, derived from the church and from the Empire. It
was in this condition that the barbarians found the Roman
world, and came to take possession of it. In order to fully
understand all the elements which met and mixed in the cradle
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 33
of our civilization, it only remains for us to study the barba-
rians.
When I speak of the barbarians, you understand that we have
nothing to do here with their history; narrative is not our
present business. You know that at this period the conquerors
of the Empire were nearly all of the same race; they were all
Germans, except some Sclavonic tribes, the Alani, for example.
We know also that they were all in pretty nearly the same stage
of civilization. Some difference, indeed, might have existed
between them in this respect, according to the greater or less
degree of connection which the different tribes had had with the
Roman world. Thus, no doubt the Goths were more advanced,
possessed milder manners than the Franks. But in considering
matters under a general point of view, and in their results as
regards ourselves, this original difference of civilization among
the barbarous people is of no importance.
It is the general condition of society among the barbarians
that we need to understand. But this is a subject with which, at
the present day, it is very difficult to make ourselves acquainted.
We obtain, without much difficulty, a comprehension of the
Roman municipal system, of the Christian church; their influ-
ence has been continued up to our own days. We find traces of
it in numerous institutions and actual facts ; we have a thousand
means of recognizing and explaining them. But the customs
and social condition of the barbarians have completely perished.
We are compelled to make them out either from the earliest
historical monuments, or by an effort of the imagination.
There is a sentiment, a fact which, before all things, it is
necessary that we should well understand in order to represent
faithfully to one's self the barbaric character: the pleasure of
individual independence; the pleasure of enjoying one's self
with vigor and liberty, amidst the chances of the world and of
life; the delights of activity without labor; the taste for an
adventurous career, full of uncertainty, inequality and peril.
Such was the predominating sentiment of the barbarous state,
the moral want which put in motion these masses of human
beings. In the present day, locked up as we are in so regular a
society, it is difficult to realize this sentiment to one's self with
all the power which it exercised over the barbarians of the fourth
and fifth centuries. There is only one work which, in my
opinion, contains this characteristic of barbarism stamped in
all its energy — " The History of the Conquest of England by the
Normans," of M. Thierry, the only book wherein the motives,
tendencies and impulses which actuate men in a social con-
dition, bordering on barbarism, are felt and reproduced with
a really Homeric faithfulness. Nowhere else do we see so well
the nature of a barbarian and of the life of a barbarian. Some-
3
34 GUIZOT
thing of this sort is also found, though, in my opinion, in a
much lower degree, with much less simplicity, much less truth,
in Cooper's romances upon the savages of America. There is
something in the life of the American savages, in the relations
and the sentiments they bear with them in the middle of the
woods, that recalls, up to a certain point, the manners of the
ancient Germans. No doubt these pictures are somewhat ideal-
ized, somewhat poetic; the dark side of the barbaric manners
and life is not presented to us in all its grossness. I speak not
only of the evils induced by these manners upon the social state,
but of the internal and individual condition of the barbarian
himself. There was within this passionate want of personal
independence something more gross and more material than
one would be led to conceive from the work of M. Thierry;
there was a degree of brutality and of apathy which is not always
exactly conveyed by his recitals. Nevertheless, when we look
to the bottom of the question, notwithstanding this alloy of
brutality, of materialism, of dull, stupid selfishness, the love of
independence is a noble and a moral sentiment, which draws its
power from the moral nature of man; it is the pleasure of feeling
one's self a man, the sentiment of personality, of human spon-
taneity, in its free development.
It was through the German barbarians that this sentiment
was introduced into European civilization; it was unknown in
the Roman world, unknown in the Christian church, and
unknown in almost all the ancient civilizations. When you find
liberty in ancient civilizations, it is political liberty, the liberty
of the citizen : man strove not for his personal liberty, but for his
liberty as a citizen: he belonged to an association, he was
devoted to an association, he was ready to sacrifice himself to
an association. It was the same with the Christian church: a
sentiment of strong attachment to the Christian corporation, of
devotion to its laws, and a lively desire to extend its empire; or
rather, the religious sentiment induced a reaction of man upon
himself, upon his soul, an internal effort to subdue his own
liberty, and to submit himself to the will of his faith. But the
sentiment of personal independence, a love of liberty displaying
itself at all risks, without any other motive but that of satisfying
itself; this sentiment, I repeat, was unknown to the Roman and
to the Christian society. It was by the barbarians that it was
brought in and deposited in the cradle of modem civilization,
wherein it has played so conspicuous a part, has produced such
worthy results, that it is impossible to help reckoning it as one
of its fundamental elements.
There is a second fact, a second element of civilization, for
which we are equally indebted to the barbarians: this is military
clicntship; the bond which established itself between individuals,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 35
between warriors, and which, without destroying the liberty of
each, without even in the beginning destroying, beyond a certain
point, the equahty which almost completely existed between
them, nevertheless founded an hierarchial subordination, and
gave birth to that aristocratical organization which afterward
became feudalism. The foundation of this relation was the
attachment of man to man, the fidelity of individual to indi-
vidual, without external necessity, and without obligation based
upon the general principles of society. In the ancient republics
you see no man attached freely and especially to any other man;
they were all attached to the city. Among the barbarians it was
between individuals that the social bond was formed; first by
the relation of the chief to his companion, when they lived in
the condition of a band of wandering over Europe; and later,
by the relation of suzerain to vassal. This second principle,
which has played so great a part in the history of modern civili-
zation, this devotion of man to man, came to us from the barba-
rians ; it is from their manners that it has passed into ours.
I ask you, was I wrong in saying at the beginning that
modern civilization, even in its cradle, had been as varied, as
agitated and as confused as I have endeavored to describe it to
you in the general picture I have given you of it? Is it not true
that we have now discovered, at the fall of the Roman Empire,
almost all the elements which unite in the progressive develop-
ment of our civilization? We have found, at that time, three.
wholly different societies: the municipal society, the last L
remains of the Roman Empire, the Christian society, and the '
barbaric society. We find these societies very variously organ-
ized, founded upon totally different principles, inspiring
men with wholly different sentiments ; we find the craving after
the most absolute independence side by side with the most
complete submission; military patronage side by side with
ecclesiastical dominion ; the spiritual and temporal powers every-
where present; the canons of the church, the learned legislation
of the Romans, the almost unwritten customs of the barbarians;
everywhere the mixture, or rather the co-existence of the most
diverse races, languages, social situations, manners, ideas and
impressions. Herein I think we have a sufficient proof of the
faithfulness of the general character under which I have endeav-
ored to present our civilization to you.
No doubt this confusion, this diversity, this struggle, have
cost us very dear; these have been the cause of the slow progress
of Europe, of the storms and sufferings to which she has been
a prey. Nevertheless, I do not think we need regret them. To
people, as well as to individuals, the chance of the most complete
and varied development, the chance of an almost unlimited prog-
ress in all directions, compensates of itself alone for all that it
36 GUIZOt
may cost to obtain the right of casting for it. And all things
considered, this state, so agitated, so toilsome, so violent, has
availed much more than the simplicity with which other civili-
zations present themselves; the human race has gained thereby
more than it has suffered.
We are now acquainted with the general features of the con-
dition in which the fall of the Roman Empire left the world; we
are acquainted with the different elements which were agitated
and became mingled, in order to give birth to European civili-
zation. Henceforth we shall see them advancing and acting
under our eyes. In the next lecture I shall endeavor to show
what they became, and what they effected in the epoch which we
are accustomed to call the times of barbarism; that is to say,
while the chaos of invasion yet existed.
THIRD LECTURE.
I HAVE placed before you the fundamental elements of
European civilization, tracing them to its very cradle, at
the moment of the fall of the Roman Empire. I have
endeavored to give you a glimpse beforehand of their diversity,
and their constant struggle, and to show you that no one of
them succeeded in reigning over our society, or at least in
reigning over it so completely as to enslave or expel the others.
We have seen that this was the distinguishing character of
European civilization. We now come to its history at its
commencement, in the ages which it is customary to call the
barbarous.
At the first glance we cast upon this epoch it is impossible
not to be struck with a fact which seems to contradict what
we have lately said. When you examine certain notions which
are accredited concerning the antiquities of modern Europe,
you will perceive that the various elements of our civiliza-
tion, the monarchical, theocratical, aristocratical, and demo-
cratical principles, all pretend that European society originally
belonged to them, and that they have only lost the sole dominion
by the usurpation of contrary principles. Question all that has
been written, ,all that has been said upon this subject, and you
will see that all the systems whereby our beginnings are sought
to be represented or explained maintain the exclusive predom-
inance of one or other of the elements of European civilization.
Thus there is a school of feudal publicists, of whom the
most celebrated is M. de Boulainvilliers, who pretend that,
after the fall of the Roman Empire, it was the conquering
nation, subsequently become the nobility, which possessed all
powers and rights; that society was its domain; that kings
and peoples have despoiled it of this domain ; that aristocratic
organization was the primitive and true form of Europe.
Beside this school you will find that of the monarchists, the
Abbe Dubois, for instance, who maintain, on the contrary,
that it was to royalty European society belonged. The Ger-
man kings, say they, inherited all the rights of the Roman
emperors ; they had even been called in by the ancient nations ;
the Gauls among others; they alone ruled legitimately; all
the acquisitions of the aristocracy were only encroachments
upon monarchy.
37
3$ GUIZOT
A third party presents itself, that of the liberal publicists,
republicans, democrats, or whatever you like to call them. Con-
sult the Abbe de Mably ; according to him, it is to the system
of free institutions, to the association of free men, to the
people properly so called, that the government of society de-
volved from the period of the fifth century : nobles and kings
enriched themselves with the spoils of primitive freedom; it
sunk beneath their attacks indeed, but it reigned before them.
And above all these monarchical, aristocratical and popular
pretensions rises the theocratical pretension of the church, who
affirms that in virtue of her very mission, of her divine title,
society belonged to her ; that she alone had the right to govern
it; that she alone was the legitimate queen of the European
world., won over by her labors to civilization and to truth.
See then the position in which we are placed ! We fancied
we had shown that no one of the elements of European civiliza-
tion had exclusively ruled in the course of its history; that
those elements had existed in a constant state of vicinity, of
amalgamation, of combat, and of compromise; and yet, at
our very first step, we meet with the directly contrary opinion,
that, even in its cradle, in the bosom of barbaric Europe, it
was such or such a one of their elements which alone possessed
society. And it is not only in a single country, but in all the
countries of Europe, that, beneath slightly different forms, at
different periods, the various principles of our civilization have
manifested these irreconcilable pretensions. The historical
schools we have just characterized are to be met with every-
where.
This is an important fact — important not in itself, but be-
cause it reveals other facts which hold a conspicuous place in
our history. From this simultaneous setting forth of the most
opposite pretensions to the exclusive possession of power in
the first age of modern Europe two remarkable facts become
apparent. The first, the principle, the idea of political legiti-
macy; an idea which has played a great part in the course of
European civilization. The second, the veritable and peculiar
character of the condition of barbaric Europe, of that epoch
with which we are at present especially concerned.
I shall endeavor to demonstrate these two facts, to deduce
them successively from this combat of primitive pretensions
which I have just described.
What do the various elements of European civilization, the
theocratical, monarchical, aristocratical and popular elements
pretend to, when they wish to appear the first who possessed
society in Europe? Do they not thus pretend to have been
alone legitimate? Political legitimacy is evidently a right
founded upon antiquity, upon duration ; priority in time is ap-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE
39
pealed to as the source of the right, as the proof of the legiti-
macy of power. And observe, I pray you, that this pretension
is not peculiar to any one system, to any one element of our
civilization ; it extends to all. In modern times we are accus-
tomed to consider the idea of legitimacy as existing in only
one system, the monarchical. In this we are mistaken; it is
discoverable in all. You have already seen that all the elements
of our civilization have equally desired to appropriate it. If
we enter into the subsequent history of Europe, we shall find
the most different social forms and governments equally in
possession of their character and legitimacy. The Italian and
Swiss aristocracies and democracies, the republic of San
Marino, as well as the greatest monarchies of Europe, have
called themselves, and have been regarded as legitimate; the
former, like the latter, have founded their pretensions to
legitimacy upon the antiquity of their institutions and upon
the historical priority and perpetuity of their system of gov-
ernment.
If you leave Europe and direct your attention to other times
and other countries, you everywhere meet with this idea of
political legitimacy; you find it attaching itself everywhere to
some portion of the government, to some institution, form, or
maxim. There has been no country and no time, in which there
has not existed a certain portion of the social system, public
powers; which has not attributed to itself, and in which has
not been recognized this character of legitimacy, derived from
antiquity and long duration.
What is this principle? what are its elements? how has it
introduced itself into European civilization?
At the origin of all powers, I say of all without any distinc-
tion, we meet with physical force. I do not mean to state
that force alone has founded them all, or that if, in their
origin, they had not had other titles than that of force, they
would have been established. Other titles are manifestly neces-
sary ; powers have become established in consequence of certain
social expediences, of certain references to the state of society,
manners, and opinions. But it is impossible to avoid perceiving
that physical force has stained the origin of all the powers of
the world, whatever may have been their character and form.
Yet none will have anything to say to this origin ; all powers,
whatever they may be, reject it; none will admit themselves
the offspring of force. An unconquerable instinct warns gov-
ernments that force does not found right, and that if force
was their origin, their right could never be established. This,
then, is the reason why, when we go back to early times, and
there find the various systems and powers a prey to violence,
all exclaim, " I was anterior to all this, I existed previously,
40 GUIZOt
in virtue of other titles; society belonged to me before this
state of violence and struggle in which you meet with me ; I was
legitimate, but others contested and seized my rights."
This fact alone proves that the idea of force is not the
foundation of political legitimacy, but that it reposes upon a
totally different basis. What, indeed, is done by all these
systems in thus formally disavowing force? They themselves
proclaim that there is another kind of legitimacy, the true
foundation of all others, the legitimacy of reason, justice, and
right; and this is the origin with which they desire to con-
nect themselves. It is because they wish it not to be sup-
posed that they are the offspring of force, that they pretend
to be invested in the name of their antiquity with a different
title. The first characteristic then, of political legitimacy, is
to reject physical force as a source of power, and to connect
it with a moral idea, with a moral force, with the idea of right,
of justice, and of reason. This is the fundamental element from
which the principle of political legitimacy has issued. It has
issued thence by the help of antiquity and long duration. And
in this manner :
After physical force has presided at the birth of all govern-
ments, of all societies, time progresses; it alters the works
of force, it corrects them, corrects them by the very fact that
a society endures, and is composed of men. Man carries
within himself certain notions of order, justice and reason, a
certain desire to induce their prevalence, to introduce them
into the circumstances among which he lives; he labors un-
ceasingly at this task ; and if the social condition in which he
is placed continues, he labors always with a certain effect.
Man places reason, morality and legitimacy in the world in
which he lives.
Independently of the work of man, by a law of Providence
which it is impossible to mistake, a law analogous to that which
regulates the material world, there is a certain measure of
order, reason and justice, which is absolutely necessary to the
duration of a society. From the single fact of its duration,
we may conclude that a society is not wholly absurd, insensate
and iniquitous ; that it is not utterly deprived of that element
of reason, truth and justice which alone gives life to societies.
If, moreover, the society develops itself, if it becomes more
vigorous and more powerful, if the social condition from day
to day is accepted by a greater number of men, it is because
it gathers by the action of time more reason, justice and right;
because circumstances regulate themselves, step by step, accord-
ing to true legitimacy.
Thus the idea of political legitimacy penetrates the world,
and men's minds, from the world. It has for its foundation
CIVILISATION IN EUROPE 41
and first origin, in a certain measure at least, moral legitimacy,
justice, reason, and truth, and afterward the sanction of time,
which gives cause for believing that reason has won entrance
into facts, and that true legitimacy has been introduced into
the external world. At the epoch which we are about to study,
we shall find force and falsehood hovering over the cradle of
royalty, of aristocracy, of democracy, and of the church her-
self ; you will everywhere behold force and falsehood reform-
ing themselves, little by little, under the hand of time, right
and truth taking their places in civilization. It is this intro-
duction of right and truth into the social state, which has
developed, step by step, the idea of political legitimacy; it is
thus that it has been established in modern civilization.
When, therefore, attempts have at different times been
made to raise this idea as the banner of absolute power, it has
been perverted from its true origin. So far is it from being
the banner of absolute power, that it is only in the name of
right and justice that it has penetrated and taken root in the
world. It is not exclusive ; it belongs to no one in particular,
but springs up wherever right develops itself. Political legiti-
macy attaches itself to liberty as well as to power ; to individual
rights as well as to the forms according to which public func-
tions are exercised. We shall meet with it, in our way, in
the most contrary systems ; in the feudal system, in the munici-
palities of Flanders and Germany, in the Italian republics,
no less than in the monarchy. It is a character spread over
the various elements of modern civilization, and which it is
necessary to understand thoroughly on entering upon its his-
tory.
The second fact which clearly reveals itself in the simul-
taneous pretensions of which I spoke in the beginning, is
the true character of the so-called barbarian epoch. All the
elements of European civilization pretend at this time to have
possessed Europe; it follows that neither of them predomi-
nated. When a social form predominates in the world, it is
not so difficult to recognize it. on coming to the tenth cent-
ury we shall recognize, without hesitation, the predominance
of the feudal system ; in the seventeenth century we shall not
hesitate to affirm that the monarchical system prevails ; if we
look to the municipalities of Flanders, to the Italian republics,
we shall immediately declare the empire of the democratic
principle. When there is really any predominating principle
in society, it is impossible to mistake it.
The dispute which has arisen between the various systems
that have had a share in European civilization, upon the ques-
tion, which predominated at its origin, proves, then, that they
all co-existed, without any one of them prevailing generally
42 GUIZOT
enough, or certainly enough to give to society its form and its
name.
Such, then, is the character of the barbarian epoch ; it was
the chaos of all elements, the infancy of all systems, an uni-
versal turmoil, in which even strife was not permanent or sys-
tematic. By examining all the aspects of the social state at
this period, I might show you that it is impossible anywhere
to discover a single fact, or a single principle, which was any-
thing like general or established. I shall confine myself to two
essential points: the condition of individuals, and the con-
dition of institutions. That will be enough to paint the entire
society.
At this period we meet with four classes of persons. — i. The
free men ; that is to say, those who depended upon no superior,
upon no patron, and who possessed their property and rege-
lated their life in complete liberty, without any bond of obliga-
tion to any other man. 2. The leudes, Udeles, anstrustions,
etc., bound at first by the relation of companion to chief, and
afterward by that of vassal to suzerain, to another man, to-
ward whom, on account of a grant of lands, or other gifts,
they had contracted the obligation of service. 3. The freedman.
4. The slaves.
But were these various classes fixed? Did men, when once
they were inclosed in their limits, remain there? Had the
relations of the various classes anything of regularity and
permanence? By no means. You constantly behold freemen
who leave their position to place themselves in the service of
some one, receiving from him some gift or other, and passing
into the class of leudes; others you see who fall into the class
of slaves. Elsewhere leudes are seen struggling to separate
themselves from their patrons, to again become independent,
to re-enter the class of freemen. Everywhere you behold a
movement, a continual passage of one class into another; an
uncertainty, a general instability in the relations of the classes ;
no man remaining in his position, no position remaining the
same.
Landed properties were in the same condition. You know
that these were distinguished as allodial, or wholly free, and
beneficiary, or subject to certain obligations with regard to a
superior: you know how an attempt has been made to estab-
lish, in this last class of properties, a precise and defined sys-
tem ; it has been said that the benefices were at first given
for a certain determinate number of years, afterward for life,
and that finally they became hereditary. A vain attempt I All
these kinds of tenure existed without order and simultaneously ;
we meet, at the same moment, with benefices for a fixed time,
for life, and heredity; the same lands, indeed, passed in a
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 43
few years through these different states. There was nothing
more stable in the condition of lands than in that of individuals.
on all sides was felt the laborious transition of the wandering
to the sedentary life, of personal relations to the combined
relations of men and properties, or to real relations. During
this transition all is confused, local and disordered.
In the institutions we find the, same instability, the same
chaos. Three systems of institutions co-existed: royalty;
aristocratic institutions, or the dependence of men and lands
one upon another; and free institutions, that is to say, the
assemblies of free men deliberating in common. Neither of
these systems was in possession of society; neither of them
prevailed over the others. Free institutions existed, but the
men who should have taken part in the assemblies rarely at-
tended them. The signorial jurisdiction was not more regu-
larly exercised. Royalty, which is the simplest of institutions
and the easiest to determine, had no fixed character; it was
partly elective, partly hereditary. Sometimes the son succeeded
the father; sometimes a selection was made from the family;
sometime? it was a simple election of a distant relation, or
of a stranger. In no system will you find anything fixed ; all
institutions, as well as all social situations, existed together,
became confounded, and were continually changing.
In states the same fluctuation prevailed: they were erected
and suppressed, united and divided ; there were no boundaries,
no governments, no distant people; but a general confusion
of situations, principles, facts, races and languages; such was
barbarous Europe.
Within what limits is this strange period bounded? Its
origin is well marked, it begins with the fall of the Roman
Empire. But when did it conclude? In order to answer this
question, we must learn to what this condition of society is
to be attributed, what were the causes of this barbarism.
I think I can perceive two principal causes ; the one material,
arising from without, in the course of events ; the other moral,
originating from within, from man himself.
The material cause was the continuation of the invasion.
We must not fancy that the invasion of the barbarians ceased
in the fifth century; we must not think that, because Rome
was fallen, we shall immediately find the barbaric king-
doms founded upon its ruins, or that the movement was at
an end. This movement lasted long after the fall of the empire ;
the proofs of this are manifest.
See the Frank kings, even of the first race, called continually
to make war beyond the Rhine ; Clotaire, Dagobert constantly
engaged in expeditions- into Germany, fighting against the
Thuringians, Danes and Saxons, who occupied the right bank
44 GUIZOT
of the Rhine. Wherefore? Because these nations wished to
cross the river, to come and take their share of the spoils of
the empire. When, about the same time, those great invasions
of Italy by the Franks established in Gaul, and principally by
the Eastern or Austrasian Franks ? They attacked Switzerland ;
passed the Alps; entered Italy. Why? Because they were
pressed, on the northeast, by new populations ; their expeditions
were not merely forays for pillage, they were matters of neces-
sity; they were disturbed in their settlements, and went else-
where to seek their fortune. A new Germanic nation appeared
upon the stage, and founded in Italy the kingdom of Lombardy.
In Gaul, the Frank dynasty changed; the Carlovingians suc-
ceeded the Merovingians. It was now acknowledged that this
change of dynasty was, to say the truth, a fresh invasion of
Gaul by the Franks, a movement of nations which substituted
the eastern for the western Franks. The change was com-
pleted; the second race now governed. Charlemagne com-
menced against the Saxons what the Merovingians had done
against the Thuringians; he was incessantly engaged in war
against the nations beyond the Rhine. Who urged these on ?
The Obotrites, the Wiltzes, the Sorabes, the Bohemians, the
entire Sclavonic race which pressed upon the Germanic, and
from the sixth to the ninth century compelled it to advance
toward the west. Everywhere to the northeast the movement
of invasion continued and determined events.
In the south a movement of the same nature exhibited itself:
the Moslem Arabs appeared. While the Germanic and Scla-
vonic people pressed on along the Rhine and Danube, the
Arabs begun their expeditions and conquests upon all the
coasts of the Mediterranean.
The invasion of the Arabs had a peculiar character. The
spirit of conquest and the spirit of proselytism were united.
The invasion was to conquer a territory and disseminate a
faith. There was a great difference between this movement
and that of the Germans. In the Christian world, the spiritual
and temporal powers were distinct. The desire of propagating
a creed and making a conquest did not co-exist in the same
men.
The Germans, when they became converted, preserved
their manners, sentiments and tastes ; terrestrial passions and
interests continued to rule them ; they became Christians, but
not missionaries. The Arabs, on the contrary, were both con-
querors and missionaries ; the power of the sword and that
of the word, with them, were in the same hands. At a later
period, this character determined the unfortunate turn taken
by Mussulman civilization; it is in the combination of the
spiritual and temporal powers, in the confusion of moral and
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 45
material authority, that the tyranny which seems adherent in
that civilization originated. This I conceive to be the cause
of the stationary condition into which that civilization is every-
where fallen. But the fact did not make its appearance at
first; on the contrary, it added prodigious force to the Arab
invasion. Undertaken with moral passions and ideas, it im-
mediately obtained a splendor and a greatness which was want-
ing to the German invasion ; it exhibited far more energy and
enthusiasm, and far differently influenced the minds of men.
Such was the state of Europe from the fifth to the ninth
century; pressed on the south by the Mahometans, on the
north by the Germans and the Sclavonic tribes, it was scarcely
possible that the reaction of this double invasion should do
other than hold the interior of Europe in continual disorder.
The populations were constantly being displaced, and forced
one upon the other; nothing of a fixed character could be
established ; the wandering life recommenced on all sides.
There was, no doubt, some difference in this respect in the
different states : the chaos was greater in Germany than in the
rest of Europe, Germany being the focus of the movement;
France was more agitated than Italy. But in no place could
society settle or regulate itself; barbarism continued on all
sides from the same cause that had originated it.
So much for the material cause, that which arose from the
course of events. I now come to the moral cause, which
sprang from the internal condition of man, and which was
no less powerful.
After all, whatever external events may be, it is man him-
self who makes the world; it is in proportion to the ideas,
sentiments and dispositions, moral and intellectual, of man,
that the world becomes regulated and progressive; it is upon k
the internal condition of man that the visible condition of /
society depends.
What is required to enable men to found a society with /
any thing of durability and regularity? It is evidently neces-
sary that they should have a certain number of ideas sufficiently
extended to suit that society, to apply to its wants, to its rela-
tions. It is necessary, moreover, that these ideas should be
common to the greater number of the members of the society ;
finally, that they should exercise a certain empire over their
wills and actions.
It is clear, that if men have no ideas extending beyond
their own existence, if their intellectual horizon is confined
to themselves, if they are abandoned to the tempest of their
passions and their wills, if they have not among them a cer-
tain number of notions and sentiments in common around
which to rally, it is clear, I say, that between them no society
46 GUIZOT
IS possible, and that each individual must be a principle of
disturbance and dissolution to any association which he may
enter.
Wherever individuality predominates almost exclusively,
wherever man considers no one but himself, and his ideas do
not extend beyond himself, and he obeys nothing but his own
passions, society (I mean a society somewhat extended and
permanent) becames for him almost impossible. Such, how-
ever, was the moral condition of the conquerors of Europe,
at the time upon which we are now occupied.
I remarked in my last lecture that we are indebted to the Ger-
mans for an energetic sentiment of individual liberty, of human
individuality. But in a state of extreme barbarism and igno-
rance this sentiment becomes selfishness in all its brutality, and
in all its insociability. From the fifth to the eigth century it was
at this point among the Germans. They cared only for their
own interests, their own passions, their own will : how could
they be reconciled to a condition even approximating to the
social ? Attempts were made to prevail upon them to enter it ;
they attempted to do so themselves. But they immediately
abandoned it by some act of carelessness, some burst of passion,
some want of intelligence. Constantly did society attempt to
form itself; constantly was it destroyed by the act of man,
by the absence of the moral conditions under which alone it
can exist.
Such were the two determining causes of the barbarous
state. So long as these were prolonged, barbarism endured.
Let us see how and when they at last termin^ited.
Europe labored to escape from this condition. It is in the
nature of man, even when he has been plunged into such a
condition by his own fault, not to desire to remain in it. How-
ever rude, however ignorant, however devoted to his own in-
terests and to his own passions he may be, there is within
him a voice and an instinct which tells him that he was made
for better things, that he has other powers, another destiny.
In the midst of disorder, the love of order and of progress
pursues and harasses him. The need of justice, foresight, de-
velopment, agitates him even under the yoke of the most brutal
selfishness. He feels himself impelled to reform the material
world, and society, and himself; and he labors to do this,
though unaware of the nature of the want which urges him.
The barbarians aspired after civilization, while totally in-
capable of it, nay more, detesting it from the instant that they
became acquainted with its law.
There remained, moreover, considerable wrecks of the Roman
civilization. The name of the Empire, the recollection of that
great and glorious society, disturbed the memories of men,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 47
particularly of the senators of towns, of bishops, priests, and
all those who had their origin in the Roman world.
Among the barbarians themselves, or their barbaric ances-
tors, many had been witnesses of the grandeur of the Empire ;
they had served in its armies, they had conquered it. The
image and name of Roman civilization had an imposing in-
fluence upon them, and they experienced the desire of imitat-
ing, of reproducing, of preserving something of it. This was
another cause which urged them to quit the condition of bar-
barism I have described.
There was a third cause which suggests itself to every mind ;
I mean the Christian church. The church was a society regu-
larly constituted, having its principles, its rules, and its dis-
cipline, and experiencing an ardent desire to extend its in-
fluence and conquer its conquerors. Among the Christians of
this period, among the Christian clergy there were men who
had thought upon all moral and political questions, who had
decided opinions and energetic sentiments upon all subjects,
and a vivid desire to propagate and give them empire. Never
has any other society made such efforts to influence the sur-
rounding world, and to stamp thereon its own likeness, as
were made by the Christian church between the fifth and the
tenth centuries. When we come to study its particular his-
tory, we shall see all that it has done. It attacked barbarism,
as it were, at every point, in order to civilize by ruling over it.
Finally, there was a fourth cause of civilization, a cause
which it is impossible fitly to appreciate, but which is not
therefore the less real, and this is the appearance of great
men. No one can say why a great man appears at a certain
epoch, and what he adds to the development of the world ;
that is a secret of Providence: but the fact is not therefore
less certain. There are men whom the spectacle of anarchy
and social stagnation, strikes and revolts, who are intellectually
shocked therewith as with a fact which ought not to exist,
and are possessed with an unconquerable desire of changing
it, a desire of giving some rule, somewhat of the general,
regular and permanent to the world before them. A terrible
and often tyrannical power, which commits a thousand crimes,
a thousand errors, for human weakness attends it; a power,
nevertheless, glorious and salutary, for it gives to humanity,
and with the hand of man, a vigorous impulse forward, a
mighty movement.
These different causes and forces led, between the fifth and
ninth century, to various attempts at extricating European so-
ciety from barbarism.
The first attempt, which, although but slightly effective,
must not be overlooked, since it emanated from the barbarians
48 GUIZOT
themselves, was the drawing up of the barbaric laws : between
the sixth and eighth centuries the laws of almost all the bar-
barous people were written. Before this they had not been
written; the barbarians had been governed simply by cus-
toms, until they established themselves upon the ruins of the
Roman empire. We may reckon the laws of the Burgundians,
of the Salian and Ripuarian Franks, of the Visigoths, of the
Lombards, the Saxons, the Prisons, the Bavarians, the Alemanni,
etc. Here was manifestly a beginning of civilization ; an en-
deavor to bring society under general and regular principles.
The success of this attempt could not be great ; it was writing
the laws of a society which no longer existed, the laws of the
social state of the barbarians before their establishment upon
the Roman territory, before they had exchanged the wander-
ing for the sedentary life, the condition of nomad warriors for
that of proprietors. We find, indeed, here and there, some
articles concerning the lands which the barbarians had con-
quered, and concerning their relations with the ancient in-
habitants of the country; but the foundation of the greater
part of their laws is the ancient mode of life, the ancient Ger-
man condition ; they were inapplicable to the new society, and
occupied only a trifling place in its development.
At the same time, another kind of an attempt was made in
Italy and the south of Gaul. Roman society had not so com-
pletely perished there as elsewhere ; a little more order and life
remained in the cities. There civilization attempted to lift again
its head. If, for example, we look to the kingdom of the
Ostrogoths in Italy under Theodoric, we see even under the
dominion of a barbarous king and nation the municipal sys-
tem, taking breath, so to speak, and influencing the general
course of events. Roman society had acted upon the Goths,
and had to a certain degree impressed them with its likeness.
The same fact is visible in the south of Gaul. It was at the
commencement of the sixth century that a Visigoth king of
Toulouse, Alaric, caused the Roman laws to be collected, and
published a code for his Roman subjects under the name of
the Breviarmm Aniani.
In Spain it was another power — namely, that of the church,
which tried to revive civilization. In place of the ancient
German assemblies, the assemblies of warriors, it was the
council of Toledo which prevailed in Spain ; and although dis-
tinguished laymen attended this council, the bishops had domin-
ion there. Look at the law of the Visigoths, you will see that
it is not a barbarous law ; it was evidently compiled by the
philosophers of the time, the clergy. It abounds in general
ideas, in theories, theories wholly foreign to barbarous man-
ners. Thus, you know that the legislation of the barbarians
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 49
was a personal legislation — that is to say, that the same law
applied only to men of the same race. The Roman law gov-
erned the Romans, the Frank law governed the Franks ; each
people had its law, although they were united under the same
government and inhabited the same territory. This is what
is called the system of personal legislation, in opposition to that
of real legislation fixed upon the territory. Well, the legisla-
tion of the Visigoths was not personal, but fixed upon the terri-
tory. All the inhabitants of Spain, Visigoths and Romans,
were subject to the same law. Continue your investigation, and
you will find yet more evident traces of philosophy. Among
the barbarians, men had, according to their relative situations,
a determinate value; the barbarian, the Roman, the freeman,
the vassal, etc., were not held at the same price, there was a
tariff of their lives. The principle of the equal value of men
in the eye of the law was established in the law of the Visi-
goths. Look to the system of procedure, and you find in place
of the oath of compur gator es, or the judicial combat, the proof
by witnesses, and a rational investigation of the matter in
question, such as might be prosecuted in a civilized society.
In short, the whole Visigoth law bears a wise, systematic and
social character. We may perceive herein the work of the same
clergy who prevailed in the councils of Toledo, and so power-
fully influenced the government of the country.
In Spain, then, up to the great invasion of the Arabs, it was
the theocratic principle which attempted the revival of civili-
zation.
In France the same endeavor was the work of a different
power ; it came from the great men, above all from Charlemagne.
Examine his reign under its various aspects ; you will see that
his predominating idea was the design of civilizing his people.
First, let us consider his wars. He was constantly in the field,
from the south to the northeast, from the Ebro to the Elbe
or the Weser. Can you believe that these were mere wilful
expeditions, arising simply from the desire of conquest? By
no means. I do not mean to say that all that he did is to be
fully explained, or that there existed much diplomacy or strate-
gic skill in his plans; but he obeyed a great necessity — a
strong desire of suppressing barbarism. He was engaged dur-
ing the whole of his reign in arresting the double invasion —
the Mussulman invasion on the south and the German and
Sclavonic invasion on the north. This is the military character
of the reign of Charlemagne ; his expedition against the Saxons
had no other origin and no other purpose.
If you turn from his wars to his internal government
you will there meet with a fact of the same nature — the at-
tempt to introduce order and unity into the administration of
50 GUIZOT
all the countries which he possessed. I do not wish to employ
the word kingdom nor the word state; for these expressions
convey too regular a notion, and suggest ideas which are little
in harmony with the society over which Charlemagne pre-
sided. But this is certain, that being master of an immense
territory, he felt indignant at seeing all things incoherent, an-
archical and rude, and desired to alter their hideous condition.
First of all he wrought by means of his missi dotninici, whom
he despatched into the various parts of his territory, in order
that tney might observe circumstances and reform them, or
give an account of them to him. He afterward worked by
means of general assemblies, which he held with much more
regularity than his predecessors had done. At these assem-
blies he caused all the most considerable persons of the territory
to be present. They were not free assemblies, nor did they at
all resemble the kind of deliberations with which we are ac-
quainted; they were merely a means taken by Charlemagne
of being well informed of facts, and of introducing some order
and unity among his disorderly populations.
Under whatever point of view you consider the reign of
Charlemagne, you will always find in it the same character,
namely, warfare against the barbarous state, the spirit of civili-
zation; this is what appears in his eagerness to establish
schools, in his taste for learned men, in the favor with which
he regarded ecclesiastical influence, and in all that he thought
proper to do, whether as regarded the entire society or indi-
vidual man.
An attempt of the same kind was made somewhat later in
England by King Alfred.
Thus the different causes to which I have directed attention,
as tending to put an end to barbarism, were in action in some
part or other of Europe from the fifth to the ninth century.
None succeeded. Charlemagne was unable to found his
great empire, and the system of government which he desired
to establish therein. In Spain the church succeeded no better
in establishing the theocratic principle. In Italy and in the
south of Gaul, although Roman civilization often attempted to
rise again, it was not till afterward, toward the end of the
tenth century, that it really reacquired any vigor. Up to that
time all efforts to terminate barbarism proved abortive; they
supposed that men were more advanced than they truly were ;
they all desired, under various forms, a society more extended
or more regular than was compatible with the distribution of
power and the condition of men's minds. Nevertheless, they
had not been wholly useless. At the beginning of the tenth
century, neither the great empire of Charlemagne nor the
glorious councils of Toledo were any longer spoken of; but
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 51
barbarism had not the less arrived at its extreme term — two
great results had been obtained. .
I. The movement of the invasions on the north and south f-"^
had been arrested: after the dismemberment of the empire
of Charlemagne the states established on the right bank of the
Rhine opposed a powerful barrier to the tribes who continued
to urge their way westward. The Normans prove this incon-
testably; up to this period, if we except the tribes which cast
themselves upon England, the movement of maritime invasions
had not been very considerable. It was during the ninth cen-
tury that it became constant and general. And this was be-
cause invasions by land were become very difficult, society
having, on this side, acquired more fixed and certain frontiers.
That portion of the wandering population which could not be
driven back was constrained to turn aside and carry on its
roving life upon the sea. Whatever evils were done in the
west by Norman expeditions, they were far less fatal than in-
vasions by land; they disturbed dawning society far less
generally.
In the south the same fact declared itself. The Arabs were
quartered in Spain; warfare continued between them and the
Christians, but it no longer entailed the displacement of the
population. Saracenic bands still, from time to time, infested
the coasts of the Mediterranean; but the grand progress of
Islamism had evidently ceased.
II. At this period we see the wandering life ceasing, in its
turn, throughout the interior of Europe; populations estab-
lished themselves; property became fixed; and the relations
of men no longer varied from day to day, at the will of vio-
lence or chance. The internal and moral condition of man
himself began to change; his ideas and sentiments, like his
life, acquired fixedness; he attached himself to the places
which he inhabited, to the relations which he had contracted
there, to those domains which he began to promise himself
that he would bequeath to his children, to that dwelling which
one day he will call his castle, to that miserable collection of
colonists and slaves which will one day become a village.
Everywhere little societies, little states, cut, so to speak, to
the measure of the ideas and the wisdom of man, formed them-
selves. Between these societies was gradually introduced the
bond, of which the customs of barbarism contained the germ,
the bond of a confederation which did not annihilate individual
independence. on the one hand, every considerable person
established himself in his domains, along with his family and
servitors; on the other hand, a certain hierarchy of services
and rights became established between these warlike proprie-
tors scattered over the land. What was this? The feudal
-H
52 GUIZOT
system rising definitively from the bosom of barbarism. Of
the various elements of our civilization, it was natural that the
Germanic element should first prevail; it had strength on its
side, it had conquered Europe ; from it Europe was to receive
its earliest social form and organization. This is what hap-
pened. Feudalism, its character, and the part played by it in
the history of European civilization, will be the subject-matter
of my next lecture ; and in the bosom of that victorious feudal
system we shall meet at every step, with the other elements of
our civilization — royalty, the church, municipal corporations;
and we shall foresee without difficulty that they are not destined
to sink beneath this feudal form, to which they become assimi-
lated, while struggling against it, and while waiting the hour
when victory shall visit them in their turn.
FOURTH LECTURE.
WE have studied the condition of Europe after the fall of
the Roman Empire, in the first period of modern
history, the barbarous. We have seen that, at the
end of this epoch, and at the commencement of the tenth century,
the first principle, the first system that developed itself and took
possession of European society, was the feudal system ; we have
seen that feudalism was the first-born of barbarism. It is then
the feudal system which must now be the object of our study.
I scarcely think it necessary to remind you that it is not the
history of events, properly speaking, which we are considering.
It is not my business to recount to you the destinies of feudalism.
That which occupies us in the history of civilization; this is the
general and hidden fact which we seek under all the external
facts which envelop it.
Thus events, social crises, the various states through which
society has passed, interest us only in their relations to the
development of civilization ; we inquire of them solely in what
respects they have opposed or assisted it, what they have given
to it, and what they have refused it. It is only under this point
of view that we are to consider the feudal system.
In the commencement of these lectures we defined the nature
of civilization; we attempted to investigate its elements; we saw
that it consisted, on the one hand, in the development of man
himself, of the individual, of humanity; on the other hand, in that
of his external condition, in the development of society. When-
ever we find ourselves in the presence of an event, of a system,
or of a general condition of the world, we have this double
question to ask of it, what has it done for or against the develop-
ment of man, for or against the development of society?
You understand beforehand that, during our investigations,
it is impossible that we should not meet upon our way most
important questions of moral philosophy. When we desire to
know in what an event or a system has contributed to the
development of man and of society, it is absolutely needful that
we should be acquainted with the nature of the true develop-
ment of society and of man; that we should know what
developments are false and illegitimate, perverting instead of
ameliorating, causing a retrogressive instead of a progressive
movement.
53
54 GUIZOT
We shall not seek to escape from this necessity. Not only
should we thereby mutilate and lower our ideas and the facts,
but the actual state of the world imposes upon us the necessity
of freely accepting this inevitable alliance of philosophy and
history. This is precisely one of the characteristics, perhaps the
essential characteristic of our epoch. We are called upon to
consider, to cause to progress together, science and reality,
theory and practice, right and fact. Up to our times, these two
powers have existed separately; the world has been accustomed
to behold science and practice following different roads, without
recognizing each other, or at least without meeting. And when
doctrines and general ideas have desired to amalgamate with
events and influence the world they have only succeeded under
the form and by means of the arm of fanaticism. The empire
of human societies, and the direction of their affairs, have
hitherto been shared between two kinds of influences; upon one
hand, the believers, the men of general ideas and principles, the
fanatics; on the other, men strangers to all rational principles,
who govern themselves merely according to circumstances, prac-
ticians, free-thinkers, as the seventeenth century called them.
This condition of things is now ceasing; neither fanatics nor
free-thinkers will any longer have dominion. In order now to
govern and prevail with men, it is necessary to be acquainted
with general ideas and circumstances; it is necessary to know
how to value principles and facts, to respect virtue and necessity,
to preserve one's self from the pride of fanatics, and the not less
blind scorn of free-thinkers. To this point have we been con-
ducted by the development of the human mind and the social
state; upon one hand, the human mind, exalted and freed, better
comprehends the connection of things, knows how to look
around on all sides, and makes use of all things in its combi-
nations ; on the other hand, society has perfected itself to that
degree that it can be compared with the truth ; that facts can
be brought into juxtaposition with principles, and yet, in spite
of their still great imperfections, not inspire by the comparison
invincible discouragement or distaste. I shall thus obey the
natural tendency, convenience, and the necessity of our times,
in constantly passing from the examination of circumstances
to that of ideas, from an exposition of facts to a question of
doctrines. Perhaps, even, there is in the actual disposition of
men's minds another reason in favor of this method. For
some time past a confirmed taste, I might say a sort of predi-
lection, has manifested itself among us, for facts, for practical
views, for the positive aspect of human affairs. We have been
to such an extent a prey to the despotism of general ideas, of
theories ; they have, in some respects, cost us so dear that they
are become the objects of a certain degree of distrust. We
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 55
like better to carry ourselves back to facts, to special circum-
stances, to applications. This is not to be regretted ; it is a new
progress, a great step in knowledge, and toward the empire of
truth; provided always that we do not allow ourselves to be
prejudiced and carried away by this disposition; that we do
not torget that truth alone has a right to reign in the world ;
that facts have no value except as they tend to explain, and
to assimilate themselves more and more to the truth; that all
true greatness is of thought ; and that all fruitfulness belongs
to it. The civilization of our country has this peculiar charac-
ter, that it has never wanted intellectual greatness; it has
always been rich in ideas; the power of the human mind has
always been great in French society; greater, perhaps, than
in any other. We must not lose this high privilege ; we must
not fall into the somewhat subordinate and material state which
characterizes other societies. Intelligence and doctrines must
occupy in the France of the present day at least the place which
they have occupied there hitherto.
We shall, then, by no means avoid general and philosophical
questions; we shall not wander in search of them, but where
facts lead us to them we shall meet them without hesitation
or embarrassment. An occasion of doing so will more than
once present itself during the consideration of the feudal sys-
tem in its relations to the history of European civilization.
A good proof that in the tenth century the feudal system
was necessary, was the only possible social state, is the uni-
versality of its establishment. Wherever barbarism ceased,
everything took the feudal form. At the first moment, men
saw in it only the triumph of chaos; all unity, all general
civilization vanished; on all sides they beheld society dis-
membering itself; and, in its stead, they beheld a number of
minor, obscure, isolated, and incoherent societies erect them-
selves. To contemporaries, this appeared the dissolution of
all things, universal anarchy. Consult the poets and the
chroniclers of the time ; they all believed themselves at the end
of the world. It was, nevertheless, the beginning of a new
and real society, the feudal, so necessary, so inevitable, so
truly the only possible consequence of the anterior state, that
all things entered into it and assumed its form. Elements,
the most foreign to this system, the church, municipalities,
royalty, were compelled to accommodate themselves to it ; the
churches became suzerains and vassals, cities had lords and
vassals, royalty disguised itself under the form of suzerainship.
All things were given in fief, not only lands, but certain rights,
the right, for instance, of felling in forests, and of fishing,
the churches gave in fief their perquisites, from their revenues
from baptisms, the churchings of women. Water and money
56 GUIZOT
were given in fief. Just as all the general elements of society
entered into the feudal frame, so the smallest details, and the
most trifling facts of common life, became a part of feudalism.
In beholding the feudal form thus taking possession of all
things, we are tempted to believe, at first, that the essential
and vital principle of feudalism everywhere prevailed. But
this is a mistake. In borrowing the feudal form, the elements
and institutions of society which were not analogous to the
feudal system, did not renounce their own nature or
peculiar principles. The feudal church did not cease to be
animated and governed, at bottom, by the theocratic principle ;
and it labored unceasingly, sometimes in concert with the royal
power, sometimes with the pope, and sometimes with the peo-
ple, to destroy this system, of which, so to speak, it wore the
livery. It was the same with royalty and with the corpora-
tions ; in the one the monarchical, in the other the democratical
principle, continued, at bottom, to predominate. Notwith-
standing their feudal livery, these various elements of Euro-
pean society constantly labored to deliver themselves from a
form which was foreign to their true nature, and to assume
that which corresponded to their peculiar and vital principle.
Having shown the universality of the feudal form, it be-
comes very necessary to be on our guard against concluding
from this the universality of the feudal principle, and against
studying feudalism indifferently, whenever we meet with its
physiognomy. In order to know and comprehend this system
thoroughly, to unravel and judge of its effects in reference to
modern civilization, we must examine it where the form and
principle are in harmony; we must study it in the hierarchy
of lay possessors of fiefs, in the association of the conquerors
of the European territory. There truly resided feudal society ;
thereupon we are now to enter.
I spoke just now of the importance of moral questions, and
of the necessity of not avoiding them. But there is a totally
opposite kind of considerations, which has generally been too
much neglected ; I mean the material condition of society, the
material changes introduced into mankind's method of exist-
ing, by a new fact, by a revolution, by a new social state. We
have not always sufficiently considered these things; we have
not always sufficiently inquired into the modifications intro-
duced by these great crises of the world, into the material ex-
istence of men, into the material aspect of their relations.
These modifications have more influence upon the entire so-
ciety than is supposed. Who does not know how much the
influence of climates has been studied, and how much im-
portance was attached to it by Montesquieu. If we regard the
immediate influence of climate upon men, perhaps it is not so
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 57
extensive as has been supposed ; it is, at all events, very vague
and difficult to be appreciated. But the indirect influence of
climate, that which, for example, results from the fact that,
in a warm country men live in the open air, while in a cold
country they shut themselves up in their houses; that in one
case they nourish themselves in one manner, in the other in
another. These are facts of great importance, facts which,
by the simply difference of material life, act powerfully upon
civilization. All great revolutions lead to modifications of
this sort in the social state, and these are very necessary to be
considered.
The establishment of the feudal system produced one of
these modifications, of unmistakable importance ; it altered the
distribution of the population over the face of the land.
Hitherto the masters of the soil, the sovereign population,
had lived united in more or less numerous masses of men,
whether sedentarily in cities, or wandering in bands through
the country. In consequence of the feudal system, these same
men lived isolated, each in his own habitation and at great dis-
tances from one another. You will immediately perceive how
much influence this change was calculated to exercise upon the
character and course of civilization. The social preponderance,
the government of society, passed suddenly from the towns to
the country; private property became of more importance
than public property, private life than public life. Such was
the first and purely material effect of the triumph of feudal
society. The further we examine into it, the more will the
consequence of this single fact be unfolded to our eyes.
Let us investigate this society in itself and see what part
it has played in the history of civilization. First of all let us
take feudalism in its most simple, primitive, and fundamental
element; let us consider a single possessor of a fief in his do-
main, and let us see what will become of all those who form
the little society around him.
He establishes himself upon an isolated and elevated spot,
which he takes care to render safe and strong; there he con-
structs what he will call his castle. With whom does he es-
tablish himself? With his wife and children; perhaps some
freemen, who have not become proprietors, attach themselves
to his person, and continue to live with him, at his table.
These are the inhabitants of the interior of the castle. Around
and at his foot a little population of colonists and serfs gather
together, who cultivate the domains of the possessor of the
fief. In the center of this lower population religion plants a
church; it brings hither a priest. In the early period of the
feudal system this priest was commonly at the same time the
chaplain of the castle and pastor of the village; by and by
1—
58 GUIZOT
these two characters separated ; the village had its own pastor,
who Hved there beside his church. This, then, was the ele-
mentary feudal society, the feudal molecule, so to speak. It
is this element that we have first of all to examine. We will
demand of it the double question which should be asked of
all our facts: What has resulted from it in favor of the de-
velopment — (i) of man himself, (2) of society?
We are perfectly justified in addressing this double question
to the little society which I have just described, and in placing
faith in its replies; for it was the type and faithful image of
the entire feudal society. The lord, the people on his domains,
and the priest; such is feudalism upon the great as well as
the small scale, when we have taken from it royalty and the
towns, which are distinct and foreign elements.
The first fact that strikes us in contemplating this little so-
ciety, is the prodigious importance which the possessor of the
fief must have had, both in his own eyes, and in the eyes of
those who surround him. The sentiment of personality, of
individual liberty, predominated in the barbaric life. But
here it was wholly different ; it was no longer only the liberty
of the man, of the warrior ; it was the importance of the pro-
prietor, of the head of the family, of the master, that came to
be considered. From this situation an impression of immense
superiority must have resulted ; a superiority quite peculiar,
and very different from everything that we meet with in the
career of other civilizations. I will give the proof of this. I
take in the ancient world some great aristocratical position,
a Roman patrician, for instance: like the feudal lord, the
Roman patrician was head of a family, master, superior. He
was, moreover, the religious magistrate, the pontiff in the in-
terior of his family. Now, his importance as a religious magis-
trate came to him from without ; it was not a purely personal
and individual importance; he received it from on high; he
was the delegate of the Divinity ; the interpreter of the religious
creed. The Roman patrician was, besides, the member of a
corporation which lived united on the same spot, a member
of the senate; this again was an importance which came to
him from without, from his corporation, a received, a bor-
rowed importance. The greatness of the ancient aristocrats,
associated as it was with a religious and political character,
belonged to the situation, to the corporation in general, rather
than to the individual. That of the possessor of the fief was
purely individual ; it was not derived from any one ; all his
rights, all his power, came to him from himself. He was not
a religious magistrate; he took no part in the senate; it was
in his person that all his importance resided ; all that he was,
he was of himself, and in his own name. What a mighty
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 59
influence must such a situation have exerted on its occupant!
What individual haughtiness, what prodigious pride — let us
say the word — what insolence, must have arisen in his soul !
Above himself there was no superior of whom he was the
representative or interpreter; there was no equal near him;
no powerful and general law which weighed upon him; no
external rule which influenced his will; he knew no curb but
the limits of his strength and the presence of danger. Such
was the necessary moral result of this situation upon the char-
acter of man.
I now proceed to a second consequence, mighty also, and
too little noticed, namely, the particular turn taken by the
feudal family spirit.
Let us cast a glance over the various family systems. Take
first of all the patriarchal system of which the Bible and
oriental records offer the model. The family was very numer-
ous ; it was a tribe. The chief, the patriarch, lived therein in
common with his children, his near relations, the various gen-
erations which united themselves around him, all his kindred,
all his servants ; and not only did he live with them all, but he
had the same interests, the same occupations, and he led the
same life. Was not this the condition of Abraham, of the
patriarchs, and of the chiefs of the Arab tribes, who still repro-
duce the image of the patriarchal life?
Another family system presents itself, namely, the clan,
a petty society, whose type we must seek for in Scotland or
Ireland. Through this system, very probably, a large portion
of the European family has passed. This is no longer the
patriarchal family. There is here a great difference between
the situation of the chief and that of the rest of the popula-
tion. They did not lead the same life: the greater portion
tilled and served; the chief was idle and warlike. But they
had a common origin ; they all bore the same name ; and their
relations of kindred, ancient traditions, the same recollections,
the same affections, established a moral tie, a sort of equality
between all the members of the clan.
These are the two principal types of the family society pre-
sented by history. But have we here the feudal family ? Obvi-
ously not. It seems, at first, that the feudal family bears some
relation to the clan; but the difference is much greater than
the resemblance. The population which surrounded the pos-
sessor of the fief were totally unconnected with him ; they did
not bear his name ; between them and him there was no kin-
dred, no bond, moral or historical. Neither did it resemble
the patriarchal family. The possessor of the fief led not the
same life, nor did he engage in the same occupations with
those who surrounded him; he was an idler and a warrior,
6o GUIZOT
while the others were laborers. The feudal family was not
numerous; it was not a tribe; it reduced itself to the family,
properly so called, namely, to the wife and children; it lived
separated from the rest of the population, shut up in the castle.
The colonists and serfs made no part of it; the origin of the
members of this society was different, the inequality of their
situation immense. Five or six individuals, in a situation at
once superior to and estranged from the rest of the society,
that was the feudal family. It was of course invested with a
peculiar character. It was narrow, concentrated, and con-
stantly called upon to defend itself against, to distrust, and,
at least, to isolate itself from even its retainers. The interior
life, domestic manners, were sure to become predominant in
such a system. I am aware that the brutality of the passions
of a chief, his habit of spending his time in warfare or the
chase, were a great obstacle to the development of domestic
manners. But this would be conquered ; the chief necessarily
returned home habitually ; he always found there his wife and
children, and these well nigh only; these would alone consti-
tute his permanent society — they would alone share his inter-
ests, his destiny. Domestic life necessarily, therefore, acquired
great sway. Proofs of this abound. Was it not within the
bosom of the feudal family that the importance of women de-
veloped itself? In all the ancient societies, I do not speak of
those where the family spirit did not exist, but of those wherein
it was very powerful in the patriarchal life, for instance, women
did not hold at all so considerable a place as they acquired in
Europe under the feudal system. It was to the development
and necessary preponderance of domestic manners in feudal-
ism, that they chiefly owed this change, this progress in their
condition. Some have desired to trace the cause to the peculiar
manners of the ancient Germans; to a national aspect which,
it is said, they bore toward women amid their forests. Upon
a sentence of Tacitus, German patriotism has built I know not
what superiority, what primitive and uneradicable purity of
German manners, as regards the relations of the two sexes.
Mere fancies ! Phrases similar to that of Tacitus, concerning
sentiments and usages analogous to those of the ancient Ger-
mans, are to be found in the recitals of a crowd of observers
of savage or barbarous people. There is nothing primitive
therein, nothing peculiar in any particular race. It was in
the effects of a strongly marked social position, in the progress
and preponderance of domestic manners, that the importance
of women in Europe originated ; and the preponderance of
domestic manners became, very early, an essential character-
istic of the feudal system.
A second fact, another proof of the empire of domestic life,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 6l
equally characterizes the feudal family: I mean the heredi-
tary spirit, the spirit of perpetuation, which evidently predomi-
nated therein. The hereditary spirit is inherent in the family
spirit ; but nowhere has it so strongly developed itself as under
the feudal system. This resulted from the nature of the prop-
erty with which the family was incorporated. The fief was
unlike other properties; it constantly demanded a possessor
to defend it, serve it, acquit himself of the obligations inherent
in the domain, and thus maintain it in its rank amid the general
association of the masters of the soil. Thence resulted a sort of
identification between the actual possessor of the fief and the
fief itself, and all the series of its future possessors.
This circumstance greatly contributed to fortify and make
closer the family ties already so powerful by the very nature of
the feudal family.
I now issue from the seignorial dwelling, and descend amid
the petty population that surrounds it. Here all things wear a
different aspect. The nature of man is so good and fruitful
that when a social situation endures for any length of time, a
certain moral tie, sentiments of protection, benevolence and
affection, inevitably establish themselves among those who are
thus approximated to one another, whatever may be the con-
ditions of approximation. It happened thus with feudalism.
No doubt, after a certain time, some moral relations, some
habits of affection, became contracted between the colonists
and the possessor of the fief. But this happened in spite of
their relative position, and not by reason of its influence.
Considered in itself, the position was radically wrong. There
was nothing morally in common between the possessor of the
fief and the colonists; they constituted part of his domain;
they were his property; and under this name, property, were
included all the rights which, in the present day, are called
rights of public sovereignty, as well as the rights of private
property, the right of imposing laws, of taxing and punishing,
as well as that of disposing of and selHng. As far as it is possi-
ble that such should be the case where men are in presence of
men, between the lord and the cultivators of his lands there
existed no rights, no guarantees, no society.
Hence, I conceive, the truly prodigious and invincible hatred
with which the people at all times have regarded the feudal
system, its recollections, its very name. It is not a case with-
out example for men to have submitted to oppressive despot-
isms, and to have become accustomed to them; nay, to have
willingly accepted them. Theocratic and monarchical despot-
isms have more than once obtained the consent, almost the
affections, of the population subjected to them. But feudal
despotism has always been repulsive and odious; it has op-
62 GUIZOT
pressed the destinies, but never reigned over the souls of men.
The reason is, that in theocracy and monarchy, power is ex-
ercised in virtue of certain words which are common to the
master and to the subject; it is the representative, the minis-
ter of another power superior to all human power; it speaks
and acts in the name of the Divinity or of a general idea, and
not in the name of man himself, of man alone. Feudal des-
potism was altogether different ; it was the power of the indi-
vidual over the individual ; the dominion of the personal and
capricious will of a man. This is, perhaps, the only tyranny
of which, to his eternal honor, man will never willingly ac-
cept. Whenever, in his master, he beholds a mere man, from
the moment that the will which oppresses him appears a merely
human and individual will, like his own, he becomes indignant,
and supports the yoke wrathfully. Such was the true and dis-
tinguishing character of feudal power; and such was also the
origin of the antipathy which it has ever inspired.
The religious element which was associated with it was
little calculated to ease the burden. I do not conceive that the
influence of the priest, in the little society which I have just
described, was very great, nor that he succeeded much in
legitimating the relations of the inferior population with the
lord. The church has exerted a very great influence upon
European civilization, but this it has done by proceedings of
a general character, by changing, for instance, the general dis-
positions of men. When we enter closely into the petty feudal
society, properly so called, we find that the influence of the
priest, between the colonists and the lord, scarcely amounted
to anything. Most frequently he was himself rude and sub-
ordinate as a serf, and very little in condition or disposition to
combat the arrogance of the lord. No doubt, called, as he was,
to sustain and develop somewhat of moral life in the inferior
population, he was dear and useful to it on this account; he
spread through it somewhat of consolation and of life; but,
I conceive, he could and did very little to alleviate its destiny.
I have examined the elementary feudal society; I have
placed before you the principal consequences which necessarily
flowed from it, whether to the possessor of the fief himself,
or his family, or the population congregated around him. Let
us now go forth from this narrow inclosure. The population
of the fief was not alone upon the land ; there were other socie-
ties, analogous or different ; with which it bore relation.
What influence did the general society, to which that popula-
tion belonged, necessarily exercise upon civilization?
I will make a brief remark before answering this question:
It is true that the possessor of the fief and the priest belonged,
one and the other, to a general society ; they had at a distance
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 63
numerous and frequent relations. It was not the same with
the colonists, the serfs ; every time that, in order to designate
the population of the country at this period, we make use of
a general word, which seems to imply one and the same society,
the word people, for example, we do not convey the truth.
There was for this population no general society; its exist-
ence was purely local. Beyond the territory which they in-
habited the colonists had no connection with any thing or
person. For them there was no common destiny, no common
country; they did not form a people. When we speak of the
feudal association as a whole, it is only the possessors of the
fiefs that are concerned.
Let us see what were the relations of the petty feudal society
with the general society with which it was connected, and to
what consequences these relations necessarily led as regards
the development of civilization.
You are acquainted with the nature of the ties which united
the possessors of the fiefs among themselves, with the obli-
gations of service on the one hand, of protection on the other.
I shall not enter into a detail of these obligations ; it suffices
that you have a general idea of their character. From these
obligations there necessarily arose within the mind of each
possessor of a fief a certain number of moral ideas and senti-
ments, ideas of duty, sentiments of affection. The fact is
evident that the principle of fidelity, of devotion, of loyalty to
engagements, and all sentiments connected therewith, were de-
veloped and sustained by the relations of the possessors of the
fiefs between themselves.
These obligations, duties and sentiments endeavored to con-
vert themselves into rights and institutions. Every one knows
that feudalism desired legally to determine what were the ser-
vices due from the possessor of the fief toward his suzerain;
what were the services which he might expect in return; in
what cases the vassal owed pecuniary or military aid to his
suzerain ; in what forms the suzerain ought to obtain the con-
sent of his vassals, for services to which they were not com-
pelled by the simple tenure of their fiefs. Attempts were made
to place all their rights under the guarantee of institutions,
which aimed at insuring their being respected. Thus, the
seignorial jurisdictions were destined to render justice be-
tween the possessors of the fiefs upon claims carried before
their common suzerain. Thus, also, each lord who was of any
consideration assembled his vassals in a parliament, in order
to treat with them concerning matters which required their
consent or their concurrence. In short, there existed a collec-
tion of political, judicial and military means, with which at-
tempts were made to organize the feudal system, converting
H
64 GUIZOT
the relations between the possessors of fiefs into rights and
institutions.
But these rights and these institutions had no reahty, no
guarantee.
If one is asked what is meant by a guarantee, a poHtical
guarantee, one is led to perceive that its fundamental character
is the constant presence, in the midst of the society, of a will,
of a power disposed and in a condition to impose a law upon
particular wills and powers, to make them observe the common
rule and respect the general right.
There are only two systems of political guarantees possible :
it is either necessary there should be a particular will and
power so superior to all others that none should be able to
resist it, and that all should be compelled to submit to it as
soon as it interferes ; or else that there should be a public will
and power, which is the result of agreement, of the develop-
ment of particular wills, and which, once gone forth from
them, is in a condition to impose itself upon, and to make
itself respected equally by all.
Such are the two possible systems of political guarantees:
the despotism of one or of a body, or free government. When
we pass systems in review, we find that all of them come under
one or other of these heads.
Well, neither one nor the other existed, nor could exist,
under the feudal system.
No doubt the possessors of the fiefs were not all equal
among themselves ; there were many of superior power, many
powerful enough to oppress the weaker. But there was no
one, beginning from the first of the suzerains, the king, who
was in condition to impose law upon all the others and make
himself obeyed. Observe that all the permanent means of
power and action were wanting: there were no permanent
troops, no permanent taxes, no permanent tribunals. The
social powers and institutions had, after a manner, to recom-
mence and create themselves anew every time they were re-
quired. A tribunal was obliged to be constructed for every
process, an army whenever there was a war to be made, a
revenue whenever money was wanted; everything was occa-
sional, accidental and special ; there was no means of central,
permanent and independent government. It is plain that, in
such a system, no individual was in a condition to impose his
will upon others, or to cause the general rights to be resi>ected
by all.
on the other hand, resistance was as easy as repression
was difficult. Shut up in his castle, having to do only with
a small number of enemies, easily finding among vassals of
his own condition the means of coalition, and of assistance,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 65
the possessor of the fief defended himself with the greatest
facihty.
Thus, then, we see that the first system of guarantees, the
system which places them in the intervention of the strongest,
was not possible under feudalism.
The other system, that of a free government, a public power,
was equally impracticable; it could never have arisen in the
bosom of feudalism. The reason is sufficiently simple.
When we speak, in the present day, of a public power, of that
which we call the rights of sovereignty, the right of giving
laws, taxing and punishing, we all think that those rights
belong to no one, that no one has, on his own account, a right
to punish others, and to impose upon them a charge, a law.
Those are rights which belong only to society in the mass,
rights which are exercised in its name, which it holds not of
itself, but receives from the Highest., Thus, when an indi-
vidual comes before the powers invested with these rights,
the sentiment which, perhaps without his consciousness,
reigns in him is, that he is in the presence of a public and
legitimate power, which possesses a mission for commanding
him, and he is submissive beforehand and internally. But it
was wholly otherwise under feudalism. The possessor of the
fief, in his domain, was invested with all the rights of sov-
ereignty over those who inhabited it; they were inherent to
the domain, and a part of his private property. What are
at present public rights were then private rights; what is
now public power was then private power. When the pas-
sessor of a fief, after having exercised sovereignty in his own
name, as a proprietor over all the population amid which he
lived, presented himself at an assembly, a parliament held be-
fore his suzerain, a parliament not very numerous, and com-
posed in general of men who were his equals, or nearly so,
he did not bring with him, nor did he carry away the idea of
a public power. This idea was in contradiction to all his
existence, to all that he had been in the habit of doing in the
interior of his own domains. He saw there only men who
were invested with the same rights as himself, who were in
the same situation, and, like him, acted in the name of their
personal will. Nothing in the most elevated department of the
government, in what we call public institutions, conveyed to
him, or forced him to recognize this character of superiority
and generality, which is inherent to the idea that we form
to ourselves of pubHc powers. And if he was dissatisfied with
the decision, he refused to agree with it, or appealed to force
for resistance.
Under the feudal system, force was the true and habitual
guarantee of right, if, indeed, we may call force a guarantee.
5
66 GUIZOT
All rights had perpetual recourse to force to make themselves
recognized or obeyed. No institution succeeded in doing this ;
and this was so generally felt that institutions were rarely
appealed to. If the seignorial courts and parliaments of vassals
had been capable of influence, we should have met with them
in history more frequently than we do, and found them exert-
ing more activity; their rarity proves their invalidity.
At this we must not be astonished ; there is a reason for it,
more decisive and deeply seated than those which I have de-
scribed.
Of all systems of government and political guarantee, the fed-
erative system is certainly the most difficult to establish and to
render prevalent ; a system which consists in leaving in each
locality and each particular society all that portion of the govern-
ment which can remain there, and in taking from it only that
portion which is indispensable to the maintenance of the general
society, and carrying this to the center of that society, there to
constitute of it a central government. The federative system,
logically the most simple, is, in fact, the most complex. In
order to reconcile the degree of local independence and liberty
which it allows to remain, with the degree of general order and
submission which it demands and supposes in certain cases, a
very advanced degree of civilization is evidently requisite ; it ib
necessary that the will of man, that individual liberty, should
concur in the establishment and maintenance of this system,
much more than in that of any other, for its means of coercion
are far less than those of any other.
The federative system, then, is that which evidently requires
the greatest development of reason, morality and civilization in
the society to which it is applied. Well, this, nevertheless, was
the system which feudalism endeavored to establish ; the idea of
genaral feudalism, in fact, was that of a federation. It reposed
upon the same principles on which are founded, in our day, the
federation of the United States of America, for example. It
aimed at leaving in the hands of each lord all that portion of gov-
ernment and sovereignty which could remain there, and to carry
to the suzerain, or to the general assembly of barons, only the
least possible portion of power, and that only in cases of absolute
necessity. You perceive the impossibility of establishing such
a system amid ignorance, amid brutal passions — in short, in a
normal state so imperfect as that of man under feudalism. The
very nature of government was contradictory to the ideas and
manners of the very men to whom it was attempted to be applied.
Who can be astonished at the ill success of these endeavors at
organization?
We have considered feudal society, first in its most simple and
fundamental element, then in its entirety. We have examined,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 67
under these two points of view, that which it necessarily did, that
which naturally flowed from it, as to its influence upon the
course of civilization. I conceive that we have arrived at this
double result :
First, federalism has exerted a great, and, on the whole, a
salutary influence upon the internal development of the indi-
vidual ; it has awakened in men's minds ideas, energetic senti-
ments, moral requirements, fine developments of character and
passion.
Secondly, under the social point of view, it was unable to es-
tablish either legal order or political guarantees ; it was indis-
pensable to the revival in Europe of society, which had been so
entirely dissolved by barbarism that it was incapable of a more
regular and more extended form ; but the feudal form, radically
bad in itself, could neither regulate nor extend itself. The only
political right which the feudal system caused to assert itself in
European society was the right of resistance — I do not say legal
resistance, that could not have place in a society so little ad-
vanced. The progress of society consists precisely in substitut-
ing, on the one hand, public powers for particular wills ; on the
other, legal, for individual resistance. In this consists the grand
aim, the principal perfection of the social order ; much latitude
is left to personal liberty ; then, when that liberty fails, when it
becomes necessary to demand from it an account of itself, appeal
is made to public reason alone, to determine the process insti-
tuted against the liberty of the individual. Such is the system
of legal order and of legal resistance. You perceive, without
difficulty, that under feudalism there existed nothing of this sort.
The right of resistance which the feudal system maintained and
practised was the right of personal resistance — a terrible, un-
social right, since it appeals to force and to war, which is the de-
struction of society itself ; a right which, nevertheless, should
never be abolished from the heart of man, for its abolition is the
acceptation of servitude. The sentiment of the right or resist-
ance had perished in the disgrace of Roman society, and could
not rise anew from its wreck ; it could not come more naturally,
in my opinion, from the principle of the Christian society. To
feudalism we are indebted for its re-introduction into the man-
ners of Europe. It is the boast of civilization to render it always
useless and inactive ; it the boast of the feudal system to have
constantly professed and defended it.
Such, if I do not deceive myself, is the result of an examina-
tion of feudal society, considered in itself, in its general ele-
ments, and independently of historical development. If we
pass on to facts, to history, we shall see that has happened which
might have been looked for ; that the feudal system has done
what it was fitted to do ; that its destiny has been in conformity
^
6S GUIZOT
with its nature. Events may be adduced in proof of all the
conjectures and inferences which I have drawn from the very
nature of this system.
Cast a glance upon the general history of feudalism between
the tenth and thirteenth centuries ; it is impossible to mistake
the great and salutary influence exerted by it upon the develop-
ment of sentiments, characters, and ideas. We cannot look into
the history of this period without meeting with a crowd of noble
sentiments, great actions, fine displays of humanity, born evi-
dently in the bosom of feudal manners. Chivalry, it is true, does
not resemble feudalism — nevertheless, it is its daughter : from
feudalism issued this ideal of elevated, generous, loyal senti-
ments. It says much in favor of its parentage.
Turn your eyes to another quarter : the first bursts of Euro-
pean imagination, the first attempts of poetry and of literature,
the first intellectual pleasures tasted by Europe on its quitting
barbarism, under the shelter, under the wings of feudalism, in
the interior of the feudal castles, that all these were born. This
kind of development of humanity requires a movement in the
soul, in life, leisure, a thousand conditions which are not to be
met with in the laborious, melancholy, coarse, hard existence of
the common people. In France, in England, in Germany,
it is with the feudal times that the first literary recollections, the
first intellectual enjoyments of Europe connect themselves.
on the other, if we consult history upon the social influence
of feudalism, its answers will always be in harmony with our
conjectures ; it will reply that the feudal system has been as
much opposed to the establishment of general order as to the
extension of general liberty. Under whatever point of view
you consider the progress of society, you find the feudal system
acting as an obstacle. Therefore, from the earliest existence of
feudalism, the two forces which have been the grand motive
powers of the development of order and liberty — on one hand
the monarchical power, the popular power on the other ; roy-
alty, and the people — have attacked and struggled against it un-
ceasingly. Some attempts have, at different times, been made
to regulate it, and construct out of it a state somewhat legal and
general : in England, such attempts were made by William the
Conqueror and his sons ; in France, by St. Louis ; in Germany,
by many of the emperors. All attempts, all efforts have failed.
The very nature of feudal society was repugnant to order and
legality. In modern ages, some men of intellect have attempted
to re-establish feudalism as a social system ; they have desired
to discover therein a legal, regulated, and progressive state ;
they have made of it an age of gold. But ask them to assign the
age of gold to some particular place or time, and they can do no
such thing : it is an Utopia without a date, a drama for which
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 69
we find, in past times, neither theater nor actors. The cause of
this error is easy to discover, and it equally explains the mistake
of those who cannot pronounce the name of feudalism without
cursing it. Neither one party nor the other has taken the pains
to consider the double aspect under which feudalism presents it-
self ; to distinguish, on the one hand, its influence upon the in-
dividual development of man, upon sentiments, characters and
passions, and, on the other, its influence upon the social state.
The one party has not been able to persuade itself that a social
system, in which so many beautiful sentiments, so many virtues
are found — in which they behold the birth of all literatures, and
in which manners assume a certain elevation and nobility — can
have been so bad and fatal as it is pretended. The other party
has only seen the wrong done by feudalism to the mass of the
population, the obstacles opposed by it to the establishment of
order and liberty; and this party has not been able to believe that
fine characters, great virtues, and any progress, can have resulted
from it. Both have mistaken the double element of civilization ;
they have not understood that it consists of two developments,
of which the one may, in time, produce itself independently of
the other ; although, after the course of centuries, and by means
of a long series of circumstances, they must reciprocally call
forth and lead to each other.
For the rest, that which feudalism was in theory it was in fact ;
that to which theory pointed as likely to result from it, has re-
sulted from it. IndividuaHty and energy of personal existence,
such was the predominating trait among the conquerors of the
Roman world ; the development of individuality necessarily
resulted, before all things, from the social system which was
founded by and for themselves. That which man himself
brings to a social system, at the moment of his entrance, his in-
ternal and moral qualities, powerfully influence the situation in
which he establishes himself. The situation, in turn, reacts upon
these qualities, and strengthens and develops them. The indi-
vidual predominated in the German society ; it was for the bene-
fit of the development of the individual that feudal society, the
daughter of German society, exerted its influence. We shall
again find the same fact in the different elements of civilization ;
they have remained faithful to their principle; they have ad-
vanced and urged on the world in the direction which they first
entered. In our next lecture the history of the church and its
influence, from the fifth to the twelfth century, upon European
civilization, will furnish us with another and a striking illustra-
tion of this fact.
FIFTH LECTURE.
WE have examined the nature and influence of the feudal
system ; it is with the Christian church, from the fifth
to the twelfth century, that we are now to occupy
ourselves : I say, with the church ; and I have already laid this
emphasis, because it is not with Christianity properly speaking,
with Christianity as a religious system, but with the church as
an ecclesiastical society, with the Christian clergy, that I propose
to engage your attention.
In the 'fifth century this society was almost completely organ-
ized ; not that it has not since then undergone many and impor-
tant changes ; but we may say that at that time, the church, con-
sidered as a corporation, as a government of Christian people,
had attained a complete and independent existence.
one glance is enough to show us an immense difference be-
tween the state of the church and that of the other elements of
European civilization in the fifth century. I have mentioned,
as the fundamental elements of our civilization, the municipal
and feudal systems, royalty, and the church. The municipal
system, in the fifth century, was no more than the wreck of the
Roman Empire, a shadow without life or determinate form.
The feudal system had not yet issued from the chaos. Royalty
existed only in name. All the civil elements of modern society
were either in decay or infancy. The church alone was, at the
same time, young and constituted ; it alone had acquired a defi-
nite form, and preserved all the vigor of early age ; it alone
possessed, at once, movement and order, energy and regularity,
that is to say, the two great means of influence. Is it not, let me
ask you, by moral life, by internal movement, on the one hand,
and by order and discipline on the other, that institutions take
possession of society? The church, moreover, had mooted all
the great questions which interest man ; it busied itself with all
the problems of his nature, and with all the chances of his des-
tiny. Thus its influence upon modern civilization has been very
great, greater, perhaps, than even its most ardent adversaries,
or its most zealous defenders have supposed. Occupied with
rendering it services, or with combating it, they have regarded
it only in a polemical point of view, and have therefore, I con-
ceive, been unable either to judge it with equity, or to measure
it in all its extent.
70
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 71
The Christian church in the fifth century presents itself as an
independent and constituted society, interposed between the
masters of the world, the sovereigns, the possessors of the tem-
poral power on the one hand, and the people on the other, serv-
ing as a bond between them, and influencing all.
In order completely to know and comprehend its action, we
must therefore consider it under three aspects : first of all we
must regard it in itself, make an estimate of what it was, of its
internal constitution, of the principles which predominated in it,
and of its nature ; we must then examine it in its relation to the
temporal sovereignties, kings, lords, and others ; lastly, in its
relations to the people. And when from this triple examination
we shall have deduced a complete picture of the church, of its
principles, its situation, and the influence which it necessarily
exercised, we shall verify our assertions by an appeal to history ;
we shall find out whether the facts and events, properly so called,
from the fifth to the twelfth century, are in harmony with the
results to which we have been led by the study of the nature of
the church, and of its relations, both with the masters of the
world and with the people.
First of all, let us occupy ourselves with the church in itself,
with its internal condition, and its nature.
The first fact which strikes us, and perhaps the most impor-
tant, is its very existence, the existence of a religious govern-
ment, of a clergy, of an ecclesiastical corporation, of a priest-
hood, of a religion in the sacerdotal state.
With many enlightened men, these very words, a body of
priesthood, a religious government, appear to determine the
question. They think that a religion which ends in a body of
priests, a legally constituted clergy, in short, a governed relig-
ion, must be, taking all things together, more injurious than
useful. In their opinion, religion is a purely individual relation
of man to God ; and that whenever the relation loses this char-
acter, whenever an external authority comes between the indi-
vidual and the object of religious creeds — namely, God — religion
is deteriorated, and society in danger.
We cannot dispense with an examination of this question. In
order to ascertain what has been the influence of the Christian
church, we must know what ought to be, by the very nature of
the institution, the influence of a church and of a clergy. In
order to appreciate this influence, we must find out, first of all,
whether religion is, in truth, purely individual ; whether it does
not provoke and give birth to something more than merely a
private relation between each man and God ; or whether it nec-
essarily becomes a source of new relations between men, from
which a religious society and a government of that society nec-
essarily flow.
72 GUIZOT
If we reduce religion to the religious sentiment properly so
called, to that sentiment which is very real, though somewhat
vague and uncertain as to its object, and which we can scarcely
characterize otherwise than by naming it, — to this sentiment
which addresses itself sometimes to external nature, sometimes
to the innermost recesses of the soul, to-day to poetry, to-mor-
row to the mysteries of the future, which, in a word, wanders
everywhere, seeking everywhere to satisfy itself, and fixing itself
nowhere, — if we reduce religion to this sentiment, it seems evi-
dent to me that it should remain purely individual. Such a
sentiment may provoke a momentary association between men ;
it can, it even ought to take pleasure in sympathy, nourishing
and strengthening itself thereby. But by reason of its fluctuat-
ing and doubtful character it refuses to become the principle of
a permanent and extensive association, to adapt itself to any sys-
tem of precepts, practices, and forms; in short, to give birth to a
religious society and government.
But either I deceive myself strangely, or this religious senti-
ment is not the complete expression of the religious nature of
man. Religion, I conceive, is a different thing, and much more
than this.
In human nature and in human destiny there are problems of
which the solution lies beyond this world, which are connected
with a class of things foreign to the visible world, and which in-
veterately torment the soul of man, who is fixedly intent upon
solving them. The solution of these problems, creeds, dogmas,
which contain that solution, or at least flatter themselves that
they do, these constitute the first object and the first source of
religion.
Another path leads men to religion. To those among you
who have prosecuted somewhat extended philosophical studies,
it is, I conceive, sufficiently evident at present that morality ex-
ists independently of religious ideas ; that the distinction of
moral good and evil, the obligation to shun the evil, and to do
the good, are laws, which, like the laws of logic, man discovers
in his own nature, and which have their principle in himself, as
they have their application in his actual life. But these facts be-
ing decided, the independence of morality being admitted, a
question arises in the human mind — Whence comes morality?
To what does it lead? Is this obligation to do good, which sub-
sists of itself, an isolated fact, without author and aim? Does it
not conceal from, or rather does it not reveal to man a destiny
which is beyond this world? This is a spontaneous and inevita-
ble question, by which morality, in its turn, leads man to the
door of religion, and discovers to him a sphere from which he
had not borrowed morality.
Thus, in the problems of our nature, upon one hand, and in
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 73
the necessity of discovering a sanction, origin, and aim for mo-
rality, on the other, we find assured and fruitful sources of relig-
ion, which thus presents itself under aspects very different from
that of a mere instrument, as it has been described ; it presents
itself as a collection — first, of doctrines called forth by problems
which man discovers within himself ; and, of precepts which
correspond to those doctrines, and give to natural morality a
meaning and sanction; second, of promises which address them-
selves to the hopes of humanity in the future. This is what truly
constitutes religion ; this is what it is at bottom, and not a mere
form of sensibility, a flight of the imagination, a species of poetry.
Reduced in this manner to its true elements and to its essence,
religion no longer appears as a purely individual fact, but as a
powerful and fruitful principle of association. Consider it as a
system of creeds and dogmas ; truth belongs to no one ; it is
universal, absolute ; men must seek and profess it in common.
Consider the precepts that associate themselves with doctrines :
an obligatory law for one is such for all ; it must be promul-
gated, it must bring all men under its empire. It is the same
with the promises made by religion in the name of its creeds and
precepts : they must be spread abroad, and all men must be
called to gather the fruits of them. From the essential elements
of religion, then, you see that the religious society is born ; in-
deed, it flows therefrom so infallibly that the word which ex-
presses the most energetic social sentiment, the most imperious
necessity of propagating ideas and extending a society, is the
word proselytism, a word which applies above all to religious
creeds, and, indeed, seems to be almost exclusively consecrated
to them.
The religious society being once born, when a certain number
of men become united in common religious creeds, under the
law of common religious precepts, and in common religious
hopes, that society must have a government. There is no society
which can survive a week, an hour, without a government. At
the very instant in which the society forms itself, and even by
the very fact of its formation, it calls a government, which pro-
claims the common truth, the bond of the society, and promul-
gates and supports the precepts which originate in that truth.
The necessity for a power, for a government over the religious
society, as over every other, is implied in the fact of the existence
of that society. And not only is government necessary, but it
naturally forms itself. I must not pause for any time to explain
how government originates and establishes itself in society in
general. I shall confine myself to saying that, when things fol-
low their natural laws, when external force does not mix itself
up with them, power always flies to the most capable, to the best,
to those who will lead society toward its aim. In a warlike ex-
74 GUIZOT
pedition the bravest obtain the power. If research or skilful
enterprise is the object of an association, the most capable will
be at the head of it. In all things, when the world is left to its
natural course, the natural inequality of men freely displays it-
self, and each takes the place which he is capable of occupying.
Well, as regards religion, men are no more equal in talents,
faculties, and power than in the other cases ; such a one will be
better able than any other to expound religious doctrines, and to
cause them to be generally adopted ; some other bears about
him more authority to induce the observance of religious pre-
cepts ; a third will excel in sustaining and animating religious
emotions and hopes in the souls of men. The same inequality
of faculties and influence which gives rise to power in civil society
originates it equally in religious society. Missionaries arise and
declare themselves like generals. Thus, as on one hand re-
ligious government necessarily flows from the nature of relig-
ious society, so on the other it naturally develops itself therein by
the mere effect of the human faculties and their unequal parti-
tion. Therefore, from the moment at which religion is born in
man, religious society develops itself ; and from the moment at
which religious society appears it gives rise to its government.
But now a fundamental objection arises : there is nothing in
this case to ordain or impose ; nothing coercive. There is no
room for government, since unlimited liberty is required to
exist.
It is, I conceive, a very rude and petty idea of government in
general to suppose that it resides solely, or even principally, in
the force which it exerts to make itself obeyed in its coercive ele-
ment.
I leave the religious point of view ; I take civil government.
I pray you follow with me the simple course of facts. The so-
ciety exists : there is something to be done, no matter what, in
its interest and name ; there is a law to make, a measure to take,
a judgment to pronounce. Assuredly there is likewise a worthy
manner of fulfilling these social wants ; a good law to make, a
good measure to take, a good judgment to pronounce. What-
ever may be the matter in hand, whatever may be the interest in
question, there is in every case a truth that must be known, a
truth which must decide the conduct of the question.
The first business of government is to seek this truth, to dis-
cover what is just, reasonable, and adapted to society. When it
has found it, it proclaims it. It becomes then necessary that it
should impress it upon men's minds ; that the government
should make itself approved of by those upon whom it acts, that
it should persuade them of its reasonableness. Is there any-
thing coercive in this? Assuredly not. Now, suppose that the
truth which ought to decide concerning the affair, no matter
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 75
what, suppose I say, that this truth once discovered and pro-
claimed, immediately all understandings are convinced, all wills
determined, that all recognize the reasonableness of the govern-
ment, and spontaneously obey it ; there is still no coercion, there
is no room for the employment of force. Is it that the govern-
ment did not exist? Is it that, in all this, there was no govern-
ment? Evidently there was a government and it fulfilled its
task. Coercion comes then only when the resistance of indi-
vidual will occurs, when the idea, the proceeding which the gov-
ernment has adopted, does not obtain the approbation and vol-
untary submission of all. The government then employs force
to make itself obeyed ; this is the necessary result of human im-
perfection, an imperfection which resides at once in the govern-
ing power and in the society. There will never be any way of
completely avoiding it; civil governments will ever be com-
pelled to have recourse, to a certain extent, to coercion. But
governments are evidently not constituted by coercion : when-
ever they can dispense with it they do, and to the great profit of
all ; indeed, their highest perfection is to dispense with it, and to
confine themselves to methods purely moral, to the action which
they exert upon the understanding ; so that the more the gov-
ernment dispenses with coercion, the more faithful it is to its
true nature, the better it fulfills its mission. It is not thereby
reduced in power or contracted, as is vulgarly supposed ; it acts
only in another manner, and in a manner which is infinitely
more general and powerful. Those governments which make
the greatest use of coercion succeed not nearly so well as those
which employ it scarcely at all.
In addressing itself to the understanding, in determining the
will, in acting by purely intellectual means, the government, in-
stead of reducing, extends and elevates itself ; it is then that it
accomplishes the most and the greatest things. on the contrary,
when it is obliged incessantly to employ coercion, it contracts
and lessens itself, and effects very little, and that little very ill.
Thus the essence of government does not reside in coercion, in
the employment of force ; but that which above all things con-
stitutes it, is a system of means and powers, conceived with the
design of arriving at the discovery of what is applicable to each
occasion ; at the discovery of truth, which has a right to rule
society, in order that afterward the minds of men may be brought
to open themselves to it, and adopt it voluntarily and freely.
The necessity for, and the actual existence of a government are
thus perfectly conceivable, when there is no occasion for coer-
cion, when even it is absolutely interdicted.
Well, such is the government of the religious society. Un-
doubtedly, coercion is interdicted to it ; undoubtedly, the em-
ployment of force by it is illegitimate, whatever may be its aim,
76 GUIZOT
for the single reason that its exclusive territory is the human con-
science : but not less, therefore, does it subsist ; not the less
has it to accomplish all the acts I have mentioned. It must dis-
cover what are the religious doctrines which solve the problems
of the human destiny ; or, if there exists already a general sys-
tem of creeds whereby those problems are solved, it must dis-
cover and exhibit the consequences of that system, as regards
each particular case ; it must promulgate and maintain the pre-
cepts which correspond to its doctrines ; it must preach and
teach them, in order that, when the society wanders from them,
it may bring back. There must be no coercion ; the duties of
this government are, examining, preaching, and teaching re-
ligious virtues ; and, at need, admonishing or censuring. Sup-
press coercion as completely as you will, you will yet behold all
the essential questions of the organization of a government arise
and claim solutions. For example, the question whether a body
of religious magistrates is necessary, or whether it is possible to
trust to the religious inspiration of individuals (a question which
is debated between the majority of religious societies and the
Quakers), will always exist, it will always be necessary to discuss
it. In like manner, the question, whether, when it has been
agreed that a body of religious magistrates is necessary, we
should prefer a system of equality, of religious ministers equal
among themselves and deliberating in common, to an hierarchi-
cal constitution, with various degrees of power; this question
will never come to an end, because you deny all coercive power
to ecclesiastical magistrates, whosoever they may be. Instead,
then, of dissolving religious society in order that we may have
the right of destroying religious government, we must rather
recognize that the religious society forms itself naturally, that
the religious government flows as naturally from the religious
society, and that the problem to be solved is to ascertain under
what conditions this government should exist, what are its foun-
dations, principles, and conditions of legitimacy. This is the
real investigation which is imposed by the necessary existence
of a religious government as of all others.
The conditions of legitimacy are the same for the government
of a religious society as for that of any other ; they may be re-
duced to two : the first, that the power should attach itself to
and remain constantly in the hands of the best and most capable,
as far, at least, as human imperfection will allow of its doing so ;
that the truly superior people who exist dispersed among the
society should be sought for there, brought to light, and called
upon to unfold the social law, and to exercise power ; the second
that the power legitimately constituted should respect the legit-
imate liberties of those over whom it exercises itself. In these
two conditions, a good system of forming and organizing power,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 77
and a good system of guarantees of liberty, consists the worth of
government in general, whether religious or civil; all govern-
ments ought to be judged according to this criterion.
Instead, then, of taunting the church, or the government of
the Christian world, with its existence, we should find out how
it was constituted, and whether its principles corresponded with
the two essential conditions of all good government. Let us
examine the church in this twofold view.
As regards the formation and transmission of power in the
church, there is a word which is often used in speaking of the
Christian clergy, and which I wish to discard ; it is the world
caste. The body of ecclesiastical magistrates has often been
called a caste. Look around the world; take any country in
which castes have been produced, in India or Egypt ; you will see
everywhere that the caste is essentially hereditary; it is the
transmission of the same position and the same power from
father to son. Wherever there is no inheritance there is no
caste, there is a corporation ; the spirit of a corporation has its
inconveniences, but it is very different from the spirit of the
caste. The word caste cannot be applied to the Christian
church. The celibacy of the priests prevents the Christian
church from ever becoming a caste.
You already see, to a certain extent, the consequences of this
difference. To the vSystem of caste, to the fact of inheritance,
monopoly is inevitably attached. This results from the very
definition of the word caste. When the same functions and the
same powers become hereditary in the same families, it is evident
that privilege must have been attached to them, and that no one
could have acquired them independently of his origin. In fact,
this was what happened; wherever the religious government
fell into the hands of a caste it became a matter of privilege; no
one entered into it but those who belonged to the families of the
caste. Nothing resembling this is met with in the Christian
church; and not only is there no resemblance found, but the
church has continually maintained the principle of the equal
admissibility of all men to all her duties and dignities, whatever
may have been their origin. The ecclesiastical career, particu-
larly from the fifth to the twelfth century, was open to all. The
church recruited herself from all ranks, alike from the inferior,
as well as the superior; more often, indeed, from the inferior.
Around her all was disposed of under the system of privilege ;
she alone maintained the principle of equality and competition;
she alone called all who were possessed of legitimate superiority
to the possession of power. This was the first great consequence
which naturally resulted from her being a body, and not a
caste.
Again, there is an inherent spirit in castes, the spirit of immo-
78 GUIZOT
bility. This assertion needs no proof. Open any history and you
will see the spirit of immobility imprinted upon all societies,
whether political or religious, where the system of castes domin-
ated. The fear of progress, it is true, was introduced at a certain
epoch, and up to a certain point, in the Christian church. But
we cannot say that it has dominated there; we cannot say that
the Christian church has remained immovable and stationary;
for many long ages she has been in movement and progress;
sometimes provoked by the attacks of an external opposition,
sometimes impelled from within, by desires of reform and inter-
nal development. Upon the whole it is a society which has con-
tinually changed and marched onward, and which has a varied
and progressive history. There can be no doubt that the equal
admission of all men to the ecclesiastical functions, that the con-
tinued recruiting of the church according to principles of equal-
ity, has powerfully contributed to maintain, and incessantly
reanimate within it, its life and movement, to prevent the triumph
of the spirit of immobility.
How could the church, who thus admitted all men to power,
assure herself of their right to it? How could she discover and
bring to light, from the heart of society, the legitimate superior-
ities which were to share the government?
Two principles were in vigor in the church : First, the election
of the inferior by the superior — the choice, the nomination;
second, the election of the superior by the subordinates — that
is, an election properly so called, what we understand as such
in the present day.
The ordination of priests, for instance, the power of making a
man a priest, belonged to the superior alone. The choice was
exercised by the superior over the inferior. So, in the collation
of certain ecclesiastical benefices, among others, benefices
attached to the feudal concessions, it was the superior — king,
pope, or lord — who nominated the incumbent; in other cases,
the principle of election, properly so called, was in force. The
bishops had long been, and at the epoch which occupies us were
still very often, elected by the body of the clergy. Sometimes
even the congregations interfered. In the interior of monas-
teries, the abbot was elected by the monks. At Rome, the popes
were elected by the college of cardinals, and at one time even the
whole of the Roman clergy took part in the election. You thus
see the two principles — the choice of the inferior by the superior,
and the election of the superior by the subordinate — acknowl-
edged and acted upon in the church, especially at the epoch
under consideration. It was by one or other of these means
that she nominated the men called upon to exercise a portion
of the ecclesiastical power.
Not only were these two principles co-existent, but being
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 79
essentially different there was a struggle between them. After
many centuries and many vicissitudes the nomination of the
inferior by the superior gained the mastery in the Christian
church; but as a general thing, from the fifth to the twelfth
century, it was the other principle, the choice of the superior
by the subordinate, which still prevailed. And do not be sur-
prised at the co-existence of two principles so dissimilar. Re-
gard society in general, the natural course of the world, the
manner in which power is transmitted in it, you will see that this
transmission is brought into force sometimes according to one
of these principles and sometimes according to the other. The
church did not originate them; she found them in the provi-
dential government of human things, and thence she borrowed
them. There is truth and utility in each of them ; their combin-
ation will often be the best means of discovering the legitimate
power. It is a great misfortune, in my opinion, that one of these
two, the choice of the inferior by the superior, should have
gained the mastery in the church; the second, however, has
never entirely prevailed; and under various names, with more
or less success, it has been reproduced in all epochs, so as at all
events to enter protest and interrupt prescription.
The Christian church derived, at the epoch which occupies
us, immense strength from its respect for equality and legitimate
superiorities. It was the most popular society, the most access-
ible and open to all kinds of talent, to all the noble ambitions of
human nature. Thence arose its power, much more than from
its riches, or from the illegitimate means which it has too often
employed.
As regards the second condition of a good government, re-
spect for liberty, there was much to wish for in the church.
Two evil principles met in it; the one avowed, and, as it were,
incorporated in the doctrines of the church; the other intro-
duced into it by human weakness, and not as a legitimate conse-
quence of doctrine.
The first was the denial of the right of individual reason, the
pretension to transmit creeds down through the whole religious
society, without any one having the right to judge for himself.
It was easier to lay down this principle than to make it actually
prevail. A conviction does not enter into the human intellect
unless the intellect admits it; it must make itself acceptable. In
whatever form it presents itself, and whatever name it evokes,
reason weighs it; and if the creed prevail, it is from being
accepted by reason. Thus, under whatever form they may be
concealed, the action of the individual reason is always exerted
upon the ideas which are sought to be imposed upon it. It is
very true that reason may be altered; it may to a certain extent
abdicate and mutilate itself; it may be induced to make an ill
8o GUIZOT
use of its faculties, or not to put in force all the use of them to
which it has a right; such, indeed, has been the consequence
of the ill principle admitted by the church ; but as regards the
pure and complete influence of this principle, it never has been,
and never can be, put into full force.
The second evil principle is, the right of constraint which the
church arrogates to herself — a right contrary to the very nature
of religious society, to the very origin of the church, and her
primitive maxims — a right which has been disputed by many
of the most illustrious fathers, St. Ambrose, St. Hilary, St.
Martin, but which has, notwithstanding, prevailed and become a
dominant fact. The pretension of forcing to believe, if two such
words can stand in juxtaposition, or of physically punishing
belief, the persecution of heresy, contempt for the legitimate
liberty of human thought, this is an error which was introduced
into the church even before the fifth century ; and dearly has it
cost her.
If, then, we consider the church in relation to the liberty of
her members, we perceive that her principles in this respect
were less legitimate and less salutary than those which presided
at the formation of the ecclesiastical power. It must not be
supposed, however, that an evil principle radically vitiates an
institution, nor even that it is the cause of all the evil which it
carries in its breast. Nothing more falsifies history than logic :
when the human mind rests upon an idea, it draws from it every
possible consequence, makes it produce all the eflfect it is capable
of producing, and then pictures it in history with the whole
retinue. But things do not happen in this way; events are not
so prompt in their deductions as the human mind. There is in
all things a mixture of good and evil so profound and invincible
that wherever you penetrate, when you descend into the most
hidden elements of society or the soul, you find there these two
orders of existent facts developing themselves side by side, com-
bating without exterminating one another. Human nature never
goes to the extremity either of evil or good ; it passes incessantly
from one to the other, erecting itself at the moment when it
seems most likely to fall, and weakening at the moment when
its walk seems firmest. We shall find here that character of
discordance, variety and strife, which I have remarked as being
the fundamental characteristic of European civilization. There
is still another general fact which characterizes the government
of the church, and of which it is necessary to take notice.
At the present day, when the idea of government presents
itself to us, whatever it may be, we know that there is no preten-
sion of governing other than the external actions of man — the
civil relations of men among themselves; governments profess
to apply themselves to nothing more. With regard to human
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 8i
thought, human conscience, and morality, properly so called,
with regard to individual opinions and private manners, they
do not interfere ; these fall within the domain of liberty.
The Christian church did or wished to do directly the con-
trary ; she undertook to govern the liberty, private manners and
opinions of individuals. She did not make a code like ours, to
define only actions at once morally culpable and socially danger-
ous, and only punishing them in proportion as they bore this
twofold character. She made a catalogue of all actions morally
culpable, and under the name of sins she punished all with the
intention of repressing all; in a word, the government of the
church did not address itself, like modern governments, to the
external man, to the purely civil relations of men among them-
selves; it addressed itself to the internal man, to the thought and
conscience, that is to say, to all that is most private to him, most
free and rebellious against constraint. The church then from
the very nature of her enterprise, together with the nature of
some of the principles upon which she founded her government,
was in danger of becoming tyrannical and of employing illegiti-
mate force. But at the same time the force encountered a resist-
ance which it could not vanquish. However little movement
and space are left them, human thought and liberty energetically
react against all attempts to subdue them, and at every moment
compel the very despotism which they endure to abdicate. Thus
it happened in the bosom of the Christian church. You have
seen the proscription of heresy, the condemnation of the right
of inquiry, the contempt for individual reason, and the principle
of the imperative transmission of doctrines upon authority.
Well, show one society in which individual reason has been more
boldly developed than in the church! What are sects and
heresies, if they are not the fruit of individual opinions ? Sects
and heresies, all the party of opposition in the church, are the in-
contestable proof of the moral life and activity which reigned in
it ; a life tempestuous and painful, overspread with perils, errors,
crimes, but noble and powerful, and one that has given rise to the
finest developments of mind and intellect. Leave the oppo-
sition, look into the ecclesiastical government itself; you will
find it constituted and acting in a manner very different from
what some of its principles seem to indicate. It denied the right
of inquiry, and wished to deprive individual reason of its liberty;
and yet it is to reason that it incessantly appeals, and liberty is
its dominant fact. What are its institutions and means of action?
Provincial councils, national councils, general councils, a con-
tinual correspondence, the incessant publication of letters,
admonitions, and writings. Never did a government pro-
ceed to such an extent by discussion and common deliberation.
We might suppose ourselves in the heart of the Greek
6
82 GUIZOT
schools of philosophy; and yet it was no mere discussion or
seeking^ for truth that was at issue; it involved questions of
authority, of adopting measures, of promulgating decrees; in
fine, of a government. But such in the very heart of this gov-
ernment was the energy of intellectual life, that it became the
dominant and universal fact, to which all others gave way; and
what shone forth on all sides was the exercise of reason and
liberty.
I am far from inferring that these bad principles which I have
attempted to set forth, and which, in my opinion, existed in the
system of the church, remained in it without effect. At the epoch
which now occupies us, they already bore but too bitter fruit,
and were destined at a later period to bear fruit still more bitter;
but they have not accomplished all the evil of which they were
capable, they have not stifled all the good which grew in the
same soil. Such was the church, considered in itself, in its
internal construction and nature. I now pass to its relations
with the sovereigns, the masters of temporal power. This is the
second point of view under which I promised to consider it.
When the Empire fell — when, instead of the ancient Roman
system, the government, in the midst of which the church
had taken birth, with which she had arisen, and had habits in
common and ancient ties, she found herself exposed to those
barbarian kings and chiefs who wandered over the land or
remained fixed in their castles, and to whom neither traditions,
creeds nor sentiments could unite her; her danger was great,
and as great was her terror.
A single idea became dominant in the church ; this was to take
possession of the new-comers, to convert them. The relations
between the church and the barbarians had, at first, scarcely
any other aim. In influencing the barbarians it was necessary
that their senses and their imagination should be appealed to.
We therefore find at this epoch a great augmentation in the
number, pomp and variety of the ceremonies of worship. The
chronicles prove that this was the chief means by which the
church acted upon the barbarians; she converted them by
splendid spectacles. When they were established and converted,
and when there existed some ties between them and the church,
she did not cease to run many dangers on their part. The
brutality and recklessness of the barbarians were such that the
new creeds and sentiments with which they were inspired exer-
cised but little empire over them. Violence soon reassumed
the upper hand, and the church, like the rest of society,
was its victim. For her defence she proclaimed a principle for-
merely laid down under the Empire, although more vaguely —
this was the separation of the spiritual from the temporal power,
and their reciprocal independence. It was by the aid of this
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 83
principle that the church Hved freely in connection with the
barbarians; she maintained that force could not act upon the
system of creeds, hopes, and religious promises; that the spiritual
world and the temporal world were entirely distinct. You may at
once see the salutary consequences resulting from this principle.
Independently of its temporal utility to the church, it had this
inestimable effect of bringing about, on the foundation of right,
the separation of powers, and of controlling them by means of
each other. Moreover, in sustaining the independence of the
intellectual world, as a general thing, in its whole extent, the
church prepared the way for the independence of the in-
dividual intellectual world — the independence of thought.
The church said that the system of religious creeds could not
fall under the yoke of force; and each individual was led to
apply to his own case the language of the church. The prin-
ciple of free inquiry, of liberty of individual thought, is exactly
the same as that of the independence of general spiritual author-
ity with regard to temporal power.
Unhappily, it is easy to pass from the desire for liberty to the
lust for domination. I thus happened within the bosom of the
church; by the natural development of ambition and human
pride, the church attempted to establish, not only the indepen-
dence of spiritual power, but also its domination over temporal
power. But it must not be supposed that this pretension had
no other source than in the weaknesses of human nature ; there
were other more profound sources which it is of importance to
know.
When liberty reigns in the intellectual world, when thought
and human conscience are not subjected to a power which dis-
putes their right to debate and decide, or employs force against
them ; when there is no visible and constituted spiritual govern-
ment, claiming and exercising the right to dictate opinions;
then the idea of the domination of the spiritual over the temporal
order is impossible. Nearly such is the present state of the world.
But when there exists, as there did exist in the tenth century, a
government of the spiritual order; when thought and conscience
come under laws, institutions and powers which arrogate to
themselves the right of commanding and constraining them ; in
a word, when spiritual power is constituted, when it actually
takes possession of human reason and conscience in the name
of right and force, it is natural that it should be led to assume
the domination over the temporal order, that it should say:
" Now ! I have right and influence over that which is most
elevated and independent in man ; over his thought, his internal
will, and his conscience, and shall I not have right over his
exterior, material and passing interests? I am the interpreter
of justice and truth, and am I not allowed to regulate worldly
84 GUIZOT
affairs according to justice and truth?" In very virtue of this
reasoning, the spiritual order was sure to attempt the usurpation
of the temporal order. And this was the more certain from the
fact that the spiritual order embraced every development of
human thought at that time; there was but one science, and that
was theology; but one spiritual order, the theological; all other
sciences, rhetoric, arithmetic, even music, all was comprised in
theology. ^ .
The spiritual power, thus finding itself at the head of all tne
activity of human thought, naturally arrogated to itself the gov-
ernment of the world. A second cause tended as powerfully to
this end — the frightful state of the temporal order, the vi.cjence
and iniquity which prevailed in the government of temporal
societies.
We, for many centuries, have spoken at our ease of the rights
of temporal power; but at the epoch under consideration the
temporal was mere force, ungovernable brigandage. The
church, however imperfect her notions still were concerning
morality and justice, was infinitely superior to such a temporal
government as this ; the cries of the people continually pressed
her to take its place. When a pope, or the bishops, proclaimed
that a prince had forfeited his rights, and that her subjects were
absolved from their oath of fidelity, this intervention, without
doubt subject to various abuses, was often, in particular cases,
legitimate and salutary. In general, when liberty has failed
mankind, it is religion that has had the charge of replacing it.
In the tenth century the people were not in a state to defend
themselves, and so make their rights available against civil
violence : religion, in the name of Heaven, interfered. This is
one of the causes which have most contributed to the victories
of the theocratical principle.
There is a third, which I think is too seldom remarked : the
complexity of situation of the heads of the church, the variety
of aspects under which they have presented themselves in so-
ciety. on one hand they were prelates, members of the eccle-
siastical order, and part of the spiritual power, and by this title
independent ; on the other, they were vassals, and, as such, en-
gaged in the bonds of civil feudalism. This is not all ; besides
being vassals they were subjects ; some portion of the ancient
relations between the Roman emperors, and the bishops, and
the clergy, had now passed into those between the clergy and
the barbarian sovereigns. By a series of causes, which it would
be too tedious to develop, the bishops had been led to regard,
up to a certain point, the barbarian sovereigns as the successors
of the Roman emperors, and to attribute to them all their pre-
rogatives. The chiefs of the clergy, then, had a three-fold
character: an ecclesiastical character, and as such, an inde-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 85
pendent one ; a feudal character, one as such bound to certain
duties, and holding by certain services ; and, lastly, the charac-
ter of a simple subject, and as such bound to obey an absolute
sovereign. Now mark the result. The temporal sovereigns,
who were not less covetous and ambitious than the bishops,
availed themselves of their rights as lords or sovereigns to en-
croach upon the spiritual independence, and to seize upon the
collation of benefices, the nomination of bishops, etc. The
bishops, on their side, often intrenched themselves in their
spiritual independence in order to escape their obligations as
vassals or subjects ; so that, on either hand, there was an almost
inevitable tendency which led the sovereigns to destroy spirit-
ual independence, and the heads of the church to make
spiritual independence a means of universal domination.
The result has been shown in facts of which no one is ig-
norant: in the quarrels concerning investitures, and in the
struggle between the priesthood and the empire. The various
situations of the heads of the church, and the difficulty of recon-
ciling them, were the real sources of the uncertainty and con-
test of these pretensions.
Lastly, the church had a third relation with the sovereigns,
which was for her the least favorable and the most unfortunate
of them all. She laid claim to co-action, to the right of re-
straining and punishing heresy ; but she had no means of doing
this; she had not at her disposal a physical force; when she had
condemned the heretic, she had no means of executing judgment
upon him. What could she do ? She invoked the aid of what
was called the secular arm ; she borrowed the force of civil
power as a means of co-action. And she thereby placed her-
self, in regard to civil power, in a situation of dependence and
inferiority. A deplorable necessity to which she was reduced
by the adoption of the evil principle of co-action and persecu-
tion.
It remains for me to make you acquainted with the relations
of the church with the people, what principles were prevalent in
them, and what consequences have thence resulted to civiliza-
tion in general. I shall afterward attempt to verify the induc-
tions we have here drawn from the nature of its institutions and
principles, by means of history, facts, and the vicissitudes of the
destiny of the church from the fifth to the twelfth century.
SIXTH LECTURE.
WE were unable, at our last meeting, to terminate the in-
quiry into the state of the church from the fifth to the
twelfth century. After having decided that it should
be considered under three principal aspects, first, in itself alone,
in its internal constitution, and in its nature as a distinct and in-
dependent society; next, in its relations to the sovereign and
the temporal power; and lastly, in its relations with the people,
we have only accomplished the two first divisions of this task.
It now remains for me to make you acquainted with the
church in its relations with the people. I shall afterward en-
deavor to draw from this threefold inquiry a general idea of the
influence of the church upon European civilization from the
fifth to the twelfth century. And lastly, we will verify our as-
sertions by an examination of the facts, by the history of the
church itself at that epoch.
You will easily understand that, in speaking of the relations
of the church with the people, I am forced to confine myself to
very general terms. I cannot enter into a detail of the prac-
tices of the church, or of the daily relations of the clergy with the
faithful. It is the dominant principles and grand effects of the
system and of the conduct of the church toward the Christian
people, that I have to place before you.
The characteristic fact, and, it must so be called, the radical
vice of the relations of the church with the people, is the sepa-
ration of the governing and the governed, the non-influence of
the governed in their government, the independence of the
Christian clergy with regard to the faithful.
This evil must have been provoked by the state of man and
of society, for we find it introduced into the Christian church at
a very early period. The separation of the clergy and the
Christian people was not entirely consummated at the epoch
under consideration ; there was, on certain occasions, in the
election of bishops for instance, at least in some cases, a direct
intervention of the Christian people in its government. But
this intervention became by degrees more weak and of more
rare occurrence ; it was from the second century of our era that
it begun visibly and rapidly to decline. The tendency to the
isolation and independence of the clergy is, in a measure, the
history of the church itself from its very cradle. From thence,
86
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE $7
it cannot be denied, arose the greater portion of those abuses
which, at this epoch, and still more at a later period, have cost
so dear to the church. We must not, however, impute them
solely to this, nor regard this tendency to isolation as peculiar
to the Christian clergy. There is in the very nature of religious
society a strong inclination to raise the governing far above the
governed, to attribute to the former something distinct and di-
vine. This is the effect of the very mission with which they are
charged, and of the character under which they present them-
selves to the eyes of people, and such an effect is more griev-
ous in the religious society than in any other. What is it that
is at stake with the governed? Their reason, their conscience,
their future destiny — that is to say, all that is most near to them,
most individual, and most free. We can conceive, to a certain
point, that although great evil may result therefrom, a man
may abandon to an external authority the direction of his mate-
rial interests, and his temporal destiny. We can understand
the philosopher, who, when they came to tell him that his house
was on fire, answered, "Go and inform my wife; I do not
meddle in the household affairs." But, when it extends
to the conscience, the thought and the internal existence,
to the abdication of self-government, to the delivering one's
self to a foreign power, it is truly a moral suicide, a servi-
tude a hundred-fold worse than that of the body, or than
that of the soul. Such, however, was the evil which, with-
out prevailing entirely, as I shall immediately show, gradu-
ally usurped the Christian church in its relations with the
faithful. You have already seen that, for the clergy them-
selves, and in the very heart of the church, there was no
guarantee for liberty. It was far worse beyond the church and
among the laity. Among ecclesiastics, there was, at least, dis-
cussion, deliberation and a display of individual faculties ; there
the excitement of contest supplied, in some measure, the want
of liberty. There was none of this between the clergy and the
people. The laity took part in the government of the church
as mere spectators. Thus we see springing up and prevailing
at a very early period, the idea that theology and religious ques-
tions and affairs are the privileged domain of the clergy ; that
the clergy alone have the right, not only of deciding, but of
taking part tfierein at all ; that in any case the laity can have no
kind of right to interfere. At the period under consideration
this theory was already in full power; centuries and terrible
revolutions were necessary to conquer it, to bring back within
the public domain religious questions and science.
In the principle, then, as well as in fact, the legal separation
of the clergy and the Christian people was almost consum-
mated before the twelfth century.
SS GUIZOT
I would not have you suppose, however, that even at this
epoch the Christian people were entirely without influence in its
government. The legal intervention was wanting, but not in-
fluence — that is almost impossible in any government, still more
so in a government founded upon a belief common both to the
governing and the governed. Wherever this community of
ideas is developed, or wherever a similar intellectual move-
ment prevails with the government and the people, there must
necessarily exist a connection between them which no vice in
the organization can entirely destroy. To explain myself clearly
I will take an example near to us, and from the political order :
at no epoch in the history of France has the French people had
less legal influence on its government, by means of institutions,
than in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, under Louis
XIV and Louis XV.
No one is ignorant that at this period nearly all official and
direct influence of the country in the exercise of authority had
perished; yet there can be no doubt that the people and the
country then exercised upon the government far more influence
than in other times — in the times, for instance, when the states-
general were so often convoked, when the parliament took so
important a part in politics, and when the legal participation
of the people in power was much greater.
It is because there is a force which cannot be inclosed by
laws, which, when need is, can dispense with institutions: it is
the force of ideas, of the public mind and opinion. In France,
in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, there was a public
opinion which was much more powerful than at any other
epoch. Although deprived of the means of acting legally upon
the government, it acted indirectly by the empire of ideas, which
were common alike to the governing and the governed, and
by the impossibility which the governing felt of taking no note
of the opinion of the governed. A similar fact happened in the
Christian church from the fifth to the twelfth century; the Chris-
tian people, it is true, were deficient in legal action, but there
was a great movement of mind in religious matters — this move-
ment brought the laity and the ecclesiastics into conjunction,
and by this means the people influenced the clergy.
In all cases in the study of history it is necessary to hold as
highly valuable, indirect influences ; they are much more effi-
cacious, and sometimes more salutary, than is generally sup-
posed. It is natural that men should wish their actions to be
prompt and evident, should desire the pleasure of participating
in their success, power and triumph. This is not always pos-
sible, not always even useful. There are times and situations
in which indirect and unseen influences arc alone desirable and
practicable. I will take another example from the political
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 89
order. More than once, especially in 1641, the English parlia-
ment, like many other assemblies in similar crisis, has claimed
the right of nominating directly the chief officers of the crown,
the ministers, councillors of state, etc. ; it regarded this direct
action in the government as an immense and valuable guaran-
tee. It has sometimes exercised this prerogative, and always
with bad success. The selections were ill concerted, and affairs
ill governed. But how is it in England at the present day?
Is it not the influence of parliament which decides the formation
of the ministry, and the nomination of all the great officers of
the crown? Certainly; but then it is an indirect and gen-
eral influence, instead of a special intervention. The end
at which England has long aimed is gained; but by differ-
ent means ; the first means which were tried had never acted
beneficially.
There is a reason for this, concerning which I ask your per-
mission to detain you for a moment. Direct action supposes,
in those to which it is confided, far more enlightenment, reason
and prudence ; as they are to attain the end at once, and with-
out delay, it is necessary that they should be certain of not miss-
ing that end. Indirect influences, on the contrary, are only
exercised through obstacles, and after tests which restrain and
rectify them ; before prospering, they are condemned to un-
dergo discussion, and to see themselves opposed and controlled ;
they triumph but slowly, and, in a measure, conditionally. For
this reason, when minds are not sufficiently advanced and
ripened to guarantee their direct action being taken with safety,
indirect influences, although often insufficient, are still prefer-
able. It was thus that the Christian people influenced their
government, very incompletely, in much too limited an extent,
I am convinced — but still they influenced it.
There was also another cause of approximation between the
church and the people ; this was the dispersion, so to speak, of
the Christian clergy among all social conditions. Almost
everywhere, when a church has been constituted independently
of the people whom it governed, the body of priests has been
formed of men nearly in the same situation ; not that great ine-
qualities have not existed among them, but upon the whole the
government has appertained to colleges of priests living in com-
mon, and governing, from the depths of the temple, the people
under their law. The Christian church was quite differently or-
ganized. From the miserable habitation of the serf, at the foot
of the feudal castle, to the king's palace itself, everywhere there
was a priest, a member of the clergy. The clergy was associated
with all human conditions. This diversity in the situation of
the Christian priests, this participation in all fortunes, has been
a grand principle of union between the clergy and the laity, a
90
GUIZOT
principle which has been wanting in most churches invested
with power. The bishops and chiefs of the Christian clergy
were, moreover, as you have been, engaged in the feudal organ-
ization, and were members, at one and the same time, of a civil
and of an ecclesiastical hierarchy. Hence it was that the same
interests, habits and manners, became common to both the civil
and religious orders. There has been much complaint, and
with good reason, of bishops who have gone to war, of
priests who have led the life of laymen. Of a verity, it was a
great abuse, but still an abuse far less grievous than was, else-
where, the existence of those priests who never left the temple,
and whose life was totally separated from that of the community.
Bishops, in some way mixed up in civil discords, were far more
serviceable than the priests who were total strangers to the
population, to all its affairs and its manners. Under this con-
nection there was established between the clergy and the Chris-
tian people a parity of destiny and situation, which, if it did not
correct, at least lessened the evil of the separation between the
governing and the governed.
This separation being once admitted, and its limits deter-
mined (the attainment of which object I have just attempted),
let us investigate the manner in which the Christian church was
governed, and in what way it acted upon the people under its
command. on the one hand, how it tended to the develop-
ment of man, and the internal progress of the individual ; and
on the other, how it tended to the amelioration of the social
condition.
As regards the development of the individual, I do not think,
correctly speaking, that, at the epoch under consideration, the
church troubled itself much in the matter ; it endeavored to in-
spire the powerful of the world with milder sentiments, and
with more justice in their relations with the weak ; it maintained
in the weak a moral life, together with sentiments and desires
of a more elevated order than those to which their daily destiny
condemned them. Still, for the development of the individual,
properly so called, and for increasing the worth of man's per-
sonal nature, I do not think that at this period the church did
much, at all events not among the laity. What it did effect was
confined to the ecclesiastical society; it concerned itself much
with the development of the clergy, and the instruction of the
priests; it had for them schools, and all the institutions which
the deplorable state of society permitted. But they were ec-
clesiastical schools destined only for the instruction of the
clergy; beyond this, the church acted only indirectly and by
very dilatory means upon the progress of ideas and manners.
It doubtless provoked general activity of mind, by the career
which it opened to all those whom it judged capable of serving
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 91
it ; but this was all that it did at this period toward the intellec-
tual development of the laity.
It worked more, I believe, and that in a more efficacious man-
ner, toward the amelioration of social society. There can be
no doubt that it struggled resolutely against the great vices of
the social state, against slavery, for instance. It has often been
repeated, that the abolition of slavery among modern people
is entirely due to Christians. That, I think, is saying too
much ; slavery existed for a long period in the heart of Christian
society without it being particularly astonished or irritated. A
multitude of causes, and a great development in other ideas and
principles of civilization were necessary for the abolition of this
iniquity of all iniquities. It cannot be doubted, however, that the
church exerted its influence to restrain it. We have an un-
deniable proof of this. The greater part of the forms of en-
franchisement, at various epochs, were based upon religious
principles ; it is in the name of religious ideas, upon hopes of
the future, and upon the religious equality of mankind, that en-
franchisement has almost always been pronounced.
The church worked equally for the suppression of a crowd
of barbarous customs, and for the amelioration of the criminal
and civil legislation. You know how monstrous and absurd
this legislation then was, despite some principles of liberty in it ;
you also know what ridiculous proofs, such as judicial combat,
and even the simple oaths of a few men, were considered as the
only means of arriving at the truth. The church endeavored
to substitute in their stead more rational and legitimate means.
I have already spoken of the difference which may be observed
between the laws of the Visigoths, issued chiefly from the coun-
cils of Toledo, and other barbarous laws. It is impossible to
compare them without being struck by the immense superiority
of the ideas of the church in matters of legislation, justice and in
all that interests the search for truth and the destiny of man-
kind. Doubtless many of these ideas were borrowed from the
Roman legislation ; but had not the church preserved and de-
fended them, if it had not worked their propagation, they would,
doubtless, have perished. For example, as regards the em-
ployment of the oath in legal procedure, open the law of the
Visigoths and you will see with what wisdom it is used:
*• Let the judge, that he may understand the cause, first in-
terrogate the witnesses, and afterward examine the writings,
to the end that the truth may be discovered with more certainty,
and that the oath may not be needlessly administered. The
search for truth requires that the writings on either side be care-
fully examined, and that the necessity for the oath, suspended
over the heads of the parties, arrive unexpectedly. Let the
oath be administered only in those cases when the judge can
92 GUIZOT
discover no writings, proof, or other certain evidence of the
truth/' (For. Jnd. 1. ii. tit. i. 21.)
In criminal matters the relation between the punishments and
the offences is determined according to philosophical and moral
notions, which are very just. one may there recognize
the efforts of an enlightened legislator struggling against the
violence and want of reflection of barbarous manners. The
chapter, De ccede et morte hominum, compared with laws corre-
sponding thereto in other nations, is a very remarkable ex-
ample. Elsewhere it is the damage done which seems to con-
stitute the crime, and the punishment is sought in the material
reparation of pecuniary composition. Here the crime is re-
duced to its true, veritable and moral element, the intention.
The various shades of criminality, absolutely involuntary hom-
icide, homicide by inadvertency, provoked homicide, homicide
with or without premeditation, are distinguished and defined
nearly as correctly as in our codes, and the punishments vary in
just proportion. The justice of the legislator went still further.
He has attempted, if not to abolish, at least to lessen the diver-
sity of legal value established among men by the laws of bar-
barism. The only distinction which he kept up was that of the
free man and the slave. As regards free men, the punishment
varies neither according to the origin nor the rank of the de-
ceased, but solely according to the various degrees of moral cul-
pability of the murderer. With regard to slaves, although not
daring to deprive the master of all right to life and death, he at
least attempted to restrain it by subjecting it to a public and
regular procedure. The text of the law deserves citation :
"If no malefactor or accomplice in a crime should go unpun-
ished, with how much more reason should we condemn those
who have committed homicide lightly and maliciously 1 There-
fore, as masters, in their pride, often put their slaves to death,
without fault on their part, it is right that this license should be
entirely extirpated, and we ordain that the present law be per-
petually observed by all. No master or mistress can put to
death without public trial any of their male or female slaves,
nor any person dependent upon them. If a slave, or any other
servant, shall commit any crime which will render him liable to
capital punishment, his master, or accuser, shall immediately
inform the judge, or the count, or the duke, of the place where
the crime was committed. After an investigation into the
affair, if the crime be proved, let the culprit undergo, either
through the judge or his own master, the sentence of death
which he merits : provided, however, that if the judge will not
put the accused to death, he shall draw up a capital sentence
against him in writing ; and then it shall be in the power of the
master either to kill him or spare his life. At the same time,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 93
if the slave, by a fatal audacity, resisting his master, shall strike,
or attempt to strike, him with a weapon or stone, and if the
master, while defending himself, should kill the slave in his
rage, the master shall not receive the punishment due to a
homicide ; but it must be proved that this really was the fact,
and that, by the testimony or oath of the slaves, male or female,
who may have been present, and by the oath of the author of
the deed himself. Whoever, in pure malice, whether with his
own hand or by that of another, shall kill his slave without
public judgment, shall be reckoned infamous and declared in-
capable of bearing testimony, and shall pass the remainder of
his life in exile or penitence, and his goods shall fall to his near-
est heir to whom the law accords the inheritance." (For. Jud. 1.
vi. tit. V. 1. 12.)
There is one fact in the institutions of the church which is
generally not sufficiently remarked; it is the penitential system, a
system so much the more curious to study in the present day from
its being, as regards the principles and applications of the penal
law, exactly in accordance with the ideas of modern philosophy.
If you study the nature of the punishments of the church, and
the public penances which were its principal mode of chastise-
ment, you will see that the chief object is to excite repentance
in the soul of the culprit and moral terror in the beholders by
the example. There was also another idea mixed with it, that
of expiation. I know not, as a general thing, if it be possible
to separate the idea of expiation from that of punishment, and
whether there is not in all punishment, independently of the
necessity of provoking repentance in the culprit and of de-
terring those who might be tempted to become so, a secret and
imperious want to expiate the wrong committed. But, leav-
ing aside this question, it is evident that repentance and ex-
ample are the ends proposed by the church in its whole peni-
tential system. Is not this also the end of a truly philosophical
legislation? Is it not in the name of these principles that the most
enlightened jurists of this and the past century have advocated
the reform of the European penal legislation? Open their
works, those of Bentham, for instance, and you will be surprised
by all the resemblances which you will meet with between the
penal means therein proposed and those employed by the
church. They certainly did not borrow them from her, nor
could she have foreseen that one day her example would be in-
voked to aid the plans of the least devout of philosophers.
Lastly, she strove by all sorts of means to restrain violence and
continual warfare in society. Every one knows what was the
truce of God, and numerous measures of a similar kind, by which
the church struggled against the employment of force and
strove to introduce more order and gentleness into society.
94
GUIZOT
These facts arc so well known that it is needless for me to enter
into details. Such are the principal points which I have to
place before you concerning the relations between the church
and the people. We have considered it under the three aspects
which I first announced ; and have gained an inward and out-
ward knowledge of it, both in its internal constitution and its
two-fold position. It now remains for us to deduct from our
knowledge, by means of induction and conjecture, its general
influence upon European civilization. This, if I mistake not,
is a work almost completed, or at least far advanced; the simple
announcement of the dominant facts and principles in the
church show and explain its influence ; the results have, in some
measure, already passed before your eyes with the causes. If,
however, we attempt to recapitulate them, we shall, I think, be
led to two general assertions.
The first is, that the church must have exercised a very great
influence upon the moral and intellectual orders in modem
Europe, upon public ideas, sentiments and manners.
The fact is evident; the moral and intellectual development
of Europe has been essentially theological. Survey history
from the fifth to the twelfth centuries; it is theology that pos-
sessed and directed the human spirit ; all opinions are impressed
by theology; philosophical, political and historical questions
are all considered under a theological point of view. So all-
powerful is the church in the intellectual order, that even the
mathematical and physical sciences are held in submission to
its doctrines. The theological spirit is, in a manner, the blood
which ran in the veins of the European world, down to Bacon
and Descartes. For the first time, Bacon in England and
Descartes in France carried intelligence beyond the path of
theology.
The same fact is evident in all branches of literature ; theo-
logical habits, sentiments and language are manifest at every
step.
Upon the whole, this influence has been salutary; not only
has it sustained and fertilized the intellectual movement in
Europe, but the system of doctrines and precepts, under the
name of which it implanted the movement, was far superior to
anything with which the ancient world was acquainted. There
was at the same time movement and progress.
The situation of the church, moreover, gave an extent and a
variety to the development of the human mind in the modern
world which it had not possessed previously. In the east, in-
tellect is entirely religious; in Greek society, it is exclusively
human ; in the one, humanity, properly so called — that is, its
actual nature and destiny, vanishes ; in the other, it is man
himself, his actual passions, sentiments and interests which oc-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 95
cupy the whole stage. In the modern world, the religious
spirit is mixed up with everything, but it excludes nothing.
Modern intellect has at once the stamp of humanity and of
divinity. Human sentiments and interests occupy an impor-
tant place in our literature ; and yet the religious character of
man, that portion of his existence which links him to another
world, appears in every step; so that the two great sources of
man's development — humanity and religion — have flowed at
one time, and that abundantly; and despite all the evil and
abuses with which it is mixed, despite many acts of tyranny,
regarded in an intellectual point of view, the influence of the
church has tended more to develop than compress, more to ex-
tend than to confine.
Under a political point of view, it is otherwise. There can
be no doubt that in softening sentiments and manners, in crying
down and exploding numerous barbarous customs, the church
has powerfully contributed to the amelioration of the social
state; but in the political order, properly so called, as regards the
relations between the government and the subject, between
power and liberty, I do not think that, upon the whole, her in-
fluence has been beneficial. Under this relation, the church
has always presented itself as the interpreter and defender of
two systems, the theocratic or the Roman Imperial system —
that is, of despotism, sometimes under a religious, and some-
times under a civil form. Take all her institutions, and all her
legislation ; take her canons and procedure ; and you will always
find, as the dominant principle, theocracy or the empire. If
weak, the church sheltered herself under the absolute power of
the emperors ; if strong, she claimed the same absolutism on
her own account in the name of her spiritual power. We must
not confine ourselves to particular facts or special instances.
The church has, doubtless, often invoked the rights of the
people against the bad government of the sovereigns ; and often
even approved of and provoked insurrection ; has often main-
tained, in the face of the sovereign, the rights and interests of
the people. But when the question of political guarantees has
arisen between power and liberty, when the question was of es-
tablishing a system of permanent institutions, which might
truly place liberty beyond the invasions of power, the church
has generally ranged upon the side of despotism.
one need not be much astonished at this, nor charge the
clergy with too great a degree of human weakness, nor suppose
it a vice peculiar to the Christian church. There is a more
profound and powerful cause. What does a religion pretend
to ? It pretends to govern the human passions and the human
will. All religion is a restraint, a power, a government. It
comes in the name of divine law for the purpose of subduing
96 GUIZOT
human nature. It is human Hberty, then, with which it chiefly
concerns itself; it is human liberty which resists it, and which
it wishes to overcome. Such is the enterprise of religion, such
its mission and its hope.
It is true, that although human liberty is what religions con-
cern themselves with, although they aspire to the reformation
of the will of man, they have no moral means of acting upon
him but through himself, by his own will. When they act by
external means, by force, seduction, or any means, in fact, which
are foreign to the free concurrence of man, when they treat
him as they would water or wind, as a material power, they do
not attain their end, they neither reach nor govern the human
will. For religions to accomplish what they attempt, they must
make themselves acceptable to liberty itself; it is needful that
man should submit, but he must do so voluntarily and freely, and
must preserve his liberty in the very heart of his submission.
This is the double problem which religions are called upon to
solve.
This they have too often overlooked ; they have considered
liberty as an obstacle, not as a means ; they have forgotten the
nature of the force to which they address themselves, and have
treated the human soul as they would a material force. It is in
following this error that they have almost always been led to
range themselves on the side of power and despotism against
human liberty, regarding it only as an adversary, and taking
more pains to subdue than to secure it. If religions had turned
their means of action to good account, if they had not allowed
themselves to be carried away by a natural but deceitful in-
clination, they would have seen that it is necessary to guarantee
liberty in order to regulate it morally ; that religion cannot, nor
ought to act except by moral means ; they would have respected
the will of man in applying themselves to govern it. This they
have too often forgotten, and religious power has ended in itself
suffering as much as liberty.
I will go no further in the examination of the general con-
sequence of the influence of the church upon European civili-
ation. I have recapitulated them in this twofold result ; a great
and salutary influence upon the social and moral order, an in-
fluence rather unfortunate than beneficial on the political order,
properly so called. We have now to verify our assertions by
facts, to verify by history that which we have deduced from
the mere nature and situation of the ecclesiastical society. Let
us see what was the fate of the Christian church from the fifth
to the twelfth century, and whether the principles which I have
placed before you, and the results which T have attempted to
draw from them, were really developed as I have ventured to
describe.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 97
You should be careful not to suppose that these principles
and consequences have appeared at the same periods, and with
the same distinctness that I have represented them. It is a
great and too common an error, when considering the past at
the distance of many centuries, to forget the moral chronology,
to forget (singular obliviousness !) that history is essentially
successive. Take the life of a man, of Cromwell, Gustavus
Adolphus or Cardinal Richelieu. He enters upon his career,
he moves and progresses ; he influences great events, and he in
his turn is influenced by them; he arrives at the goal. We then
know him, but it is in his whole ; it is, as it were, such as he has
issued after much labor from the workshop of Providence. But
at starting he was not what he has thus become ; he has never
been complete and finished at any single period of his life ; he
has been formed progressively. Men are formed morally as
physically ; they change daily ; their being modifies itself with-
out ceasing; the Cromwell of 1650 was not the Cromwell of 1640.
There is always a groundwork of individuality ; it is always the
same man who perseveres ; but how changed are his ideas,
sentiments and will ! What things has he lost and acquired !
At whatever moment we look upon the life of man there is no
time when it has been what we shall see it when its term is at-
tained.
It is here, however, that most historians have fallen into error ;
because they have gained one complete idea of man they see
him such throughout the whole course of his career. For them,
it is the same Cromwell who enters parliament in 1628, and who
dies thirty years afterward in the palace of Whitehall. And
with regard to institutions and general influences, they inces-
santly commit the same error. Let us guard against it. I
have represented to you the principles of the church in their
entirety, and the development of the consequences. But re-
member that historically the picture is not correct ; all has been
partial and successive, cast here and there over space and time.
We must not expect to find this uniformity, this prompt and
systematic connection, in the recital of facts. Here we shall see
one principle springing up, there another; all will be incomplete,
unequal and dispersed. We must come to modern times, to
the end of the career, before we shall find the entire result. I
shall now place before you the various states through which
the church passed between the fifth and the twelfth century. We
cannot collect an entire demonstration of the assertions which
I have placed before you, but we shall see sufficient to enable us
to presume they are legitimate.
The first condition in which the church appears at the fifth
century is the imperial state, the church of the Roman Empire.
When the Roman Empire was on the decline the church
7
98 GUIZOT
thought herself at the term of her career, and that her triumph
was accompHshed. It is true she had completely vanquished
paganism. The last emperor who took the rank of sovereign
pontiff, which was a pagan dignity, was the emperor Gratian,
who died at the end of the fourth century. Gratian was called
sovereign pontiff, like Augustus and Tiberius. The church
likewise thought herself at the end of her struggle with the
heretics, especially with the Arians, the chief heretics of the
day. The Emperor Theodosius, toward the end of the fourth
century, instituted against them a complete and severe legis-
lation. The church then enjoyed the government and the
victory over its two most formidable enemies. It was at this
moment that she saw the Roman Empire fail her, and found her-
self in the presence of other pagans and heretics, in the pres-
ence of barbarians, Goths, Vandals, Burgundians and Franks.
The fall was immense. You may easily conceive the lively at-
tachment for the empire which must have been preserved in
the bosom of the church. Thus we see her strongly adhering
to what remained of it — to the municipal system and to ab-
solute power. And when she had converted the barbarians, she
attempted to resuscitate the empire; she addressed herself to
the barbarous kings, conjured them to become Roman em-
perors, to take all the rights belonging to them, and enter into
the same relations with the church as that which she had main-
tained with the Roman Empire, This was the work of the
bishops between the fifth and sixth centuries, the general state
of the church.
This attempt could not be successful; there were no means
of reforming the Roman society with barbarians. Like the
civil world, the church herself fell into barbarism. This was
its second state. When one compares the writings of the ec-
clesiastical chroniclers of the eighth century with those of pre-
ceding ages, the difference is immense. Every wreck of Ro-
man civilization had disappeared, even the language ; every-
thing felt itself, as it were, cast into barbarism. on the one
hand, barbarians entered the clerical order, and became priests
and bishops; and, on the other hand, the bishops adopted a life of
barbarism, and without quitting their bishoprics, placed them-
selves at the head of bands, overrunning the country, pillaging,
and making war, like the companions of Clovis. You will find
in Gregory of Tours mention of several bishops, among others
Salonus and Sagittarius, who thus passed their lives.
Two important facts developed themselves in the bosom of
this barbarous church. The first is the separation of the spirit-
ual and temporal power. This principle took its rise at this
epoch. Nothing could be more natural. The church not hav-
ing succeeded in resuscitating the absolute power of the Roman
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 99
Empire, and sharing it herself, was forced to seek safety in in-
dependence. It was necessary that she should defend herself
on all sides, for she was continually threatened. Each bishop
and priest saw his barbarous neighbors incessantly interfering
in the affairs of the church, to usurp her riches, lands and
power; her only means of defence was to say, "The spiritual
order is totally separate from the temporal; you have not the
right to interfere in its affairs." This principle, above all
others, became the defensive arm of the church against bar-
barism.
A second important fact belonged to this epoch, the devel-
opment of the monastic order in the west. It is known that at
the commencement of the sixth century, St. Benedict insti-
tuted his order among the monks of the west, who were then
trifling in number, but who have since prodigiously increased.
The monks at this epoch were not members of the clergy ; they
were still regarded as laymen. No doubt priests, or even
bishops, were sought for among them ; but it was only at
the end of the fifth and the beginning of the sixth cen-
tury that the monks in general were considered as forming a
part of the clergy, properly so called. We then find that
priests and bishops became monks, believing that by so
doing they made a fresh progress in religious life. Thus
the monastic order in Europe took all at once a great de-
velopment. The monks struck the fancy of the barbarians
far more than the secular clergy. Their number was as im-
posing as their singularity of life. The secular clergy, the
bishop or simple priest, were common to the imagination of
the barbarians, who were accustomed to see, maltreat and rob
them. It was a much more serious affair to attack a monastery,
where so many holy men were congregated in one holy place.
The monasteries, during the barbaric epoch, were an asylum
for the church, as the church was for the laity. Pious men
there found a refuge, as in the east they sheltered themselves
in the Thebaid, to escape a worldly life and the temptations of
Constantinople.
Such are the two great facts in the history of the church,
which belong to the barbaric epoch ; on one side the develop-
ment of the principle of separation between the spiritual and
temporal power ; on the other, the development of the mon-
astic system in the west.
Toward the end of the barbaric epoch, there was a new at-
tempt to resuscitate the Roman Empire made by Charlemagne.
The church and the civil sovereign again contracted a close
alliance. This was an epoch of great docility, and hence one
of great progress for papacy. The attempt again failed, and
the empire of Charlemagne fell ; but the advantages which the
loo GUIZOT
church had gained from his alliance still remained with her.
Papacy found herself definitely at the head of Christianity.
on the death of Charlemagne, chaos recommenced; the
church again fell into it as well as civil society, and only left
it to enter the frame of feudalism. This was its third state.
By the dissolution of the empire of Charlemagne, there hap-
pened almost the same thing in the ecclesiastical order as in
the civil order ; all unity disappeared, all became local, partial,
and individual. There then commenced in the situation of the
clergy a struggle which it had never experienced before. This
was the struggle between the sentiments and interests of the
fief-holder and the sentiments and interests of the priest. The
chiefs of the church were placed betwen these two positions,
each tended to overcome the other; the ecclesiastical spirit was
no longer so powerful or so universal ; individual interest be-
came more influential, and the desire for independence and the
habits of a feudal life, loosened the ties of the ecclesiastical
hierarchy. There was then made in the bosom of the church
an attempt to remedy the effects of this relaxation. They
sought in various quarters, by a system of federation, and by
communal assemblies and deliberations, to organize national
churches. It is at this epoch, and under the feudal system,
that we find the greatest number of councils, convocations, and
ecclesiastical assemblies, both provincial and national. It was
in France, more especially, that this attempt at unity seemed
followed with the greatest ardor. Hincmar, archbishop of
Rheims, may perhaps be considered as the representative of
this idea. His constant care was to organize the French
church; he sought and put in force all the means of corre-
spondence and union which might bring back some unity into
the feudal church. We find Hincmar maintaining on the one
side the independence of the church with regard to its temporal
power, and on the other its independence with regard to pa-
pacy; it was he who, knowing that the pope wished to come
into France, and threatened the bishops with excommunica-
tion, said. Si excommunicaturus vencrit, cxcommimicatus ahibit.
But this attempt to organize the feudal church succeeded no
better than the attempt to organize the imperial church had
done. There were no means of establishing unity in this
church. Its dissolution was always increasing. Each bishop,
prelate and abbot isolated himself more and more within his
diocese or his monastery. The disorder increased from the
same cause. This was the time of the greatest abuses of
simony, of the entirely arbitrary disposition of ecclesiastical
benefices, and of the greatest looseness of manners among
the priests. This disorder greatly shocked the people and the
better portion of the clergy. We thence see at an early time, a
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE loi
certain spririt of reform appear in the church, and the desire
to seek some authority which could rally all these elements,
and impose law upon them. Claude, bishop of Turin, and
Agobard, archbishop of Lyons, originated in their dioceses
some attempts of this nature, but they were not in a condition
to accomplish such a work. There was within the whole
church but one force adequate to it, and that was the court of
Rome, the papacy. It was, therefore, not long ere it prevailed.
The church passed during the course of the eleventh century
into its fourth state, that of the theocratical or monastical
church. The creator of this new form of church, in so far
as a man can create, was Gregory VI I.
We are accustomed to represent to ourselves Gregory VII
as a man who wished to render all things immovable, as an
adversary to intellectual development and social progress, and
as a man who strove to maintain the world in a stationary or
retrograding system. Nothing can be so false. Gregory VII
was a reformer upon the plan of despotism, as were Charle-
magne and Peter the Great. He, in the ecclesiastical order,
was almost what Charlemagne in France and Peter the Great
in Russia were in the civil order. He wished to reform the
church, and through the church to reform society, to intro-
duce therein more morality, more justice, and more law — he
wished to effect this through the holy see, and to its profit.
At the same time that he strove to subject the civil world
to the church, and the church to papacy, with an aim of re-
form and progress, and not one of immobility or retrogression,
an attempt of the same kind and a similar movement was pro-
duced in the heart of monasteries. The desire for order, dis-
cipline and moral strictness, was zealously shown. It was at
this period that Robert de Moleme introduced a severe order at
Citeaux. This was the age of St. Norbert and the reform of
the prebendaries, of the reform of Cluni, and lastly, of the
great reform of St. Bernard. A general ferment reigned in the
monasteries ; the old monks defended themselves, declared
it to be an injurious thing, said that their liberty was in dan-
ger, that the manners of the times must be complied with,
that it was impossible to return to the primitive church, and
treated all the reformers as madmen, dreamers and tyrants.
Open the history of Normandy, by Orderic Vital, and you will
continually meet with these complaints.
All therefore seemed tending to the advantage of the church,
to its unity and power. While papacy sought to seize upon the
government of the world, and while monasteries reformed
themselves in a moral point of view, some powerful though
isolated men claimed for human reason its right to be con-
sidered as something in man, and its right to interfere in his
102 GUIZOT
opinions. The greater part of them did not attack received
doctrines nor religious creeds ; they only said that reason had
a right to test them, and that it did not suffice that they should
be affirmed upon authority. John Erigena, Roscelin and
Abailard were the interpreters through whom reason once
more began to claim her inheritance; these were the first
authors of the movement of liberty which is associated with
the movement of reform of Hildebrand and St. Bernard. When
we seek the dominant character of this movement, we find that
it is not a change of opinion, or a revolt against the system
of public creeds — it is simply the right of reasoning claimed
on the behalf of reason. The pupils of Abailard asked him, as
he himself tells us in his Introduction to Theology, " for
philosophical argument calculated to satisfy the reason, sup-
plicating him to instruct them, not to repeat what he taught
them, but to understand it; because nothing can be believed
without being understood, and it is ridiculous to preach things
which neither he who professes, nor those whom he teaches,
can understand. ... To what purpose were the study of
philosophy, if not to lead to the study of God, to whom all
things should be referred? With what view are the faithful
permitted to read the writings which treat of the age and the
books of the Gentiles, unless to prepare them for understand-
ing the Holy Scriptures, and the necessary capacity for de-
fending them? In this view it is especially necessary to be
aided with all the force of reason, so as to prevent, upon
questions so difficult and complicated as are those which form
the object of the Christian faith, the subtleties of its enemies
from easily contriving to adulterate the purity of our faith."
The importance of this first attempt at liberty, this regenera-
tion of the spirit of inquiry, was soon felt. Although occupied
in reforming herself, the church did not the less take the alarm.
She immediately declared war against these new reformers,
whose methods menaced her more than their doctrines.
This is the great fact which shone forth at the end of the
eleventh and beginning of the twelfth century, at the time
when the state of the church was that of the theocratical or
monastic. At this epoch, for the first time, there arose a
struggle between the clergy and the free-thinkers. The quar-
rels of Abailard and St. Bernard, the councils of Soissons and
Sens, where Abailard was condemned, are nothing but the ex-
pression of this fact, which holds so important a position in
the history of modern civilization. It was the principal cir-
cumstance in the state of the church in the twelfth century,
at the point at which we shall now leave it.
At the same time a movement of a different nature was pro-
duced, the movement for the enfranchisement of the boroughs.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 103
Singular inconsistency of rude and ignorant manners ! If it
had been said to the citizens who conquered their Hberty with
so much passion, that there were men who claimed the rights
of human reason, the right of free inquiry — men whom the
church treated as heretics — they would have instantly stoned
or burnt them. More than once did Abailard and his friends
run this risk. on the other hand, those very writers who
claimed the rights of human reason, spoke of the efforts for
the enfranchisement of the boroughs as of an abominable dis-
order, and overthrow of society. Between the philosophical
and the communal movement, between the political and ra-
tional enfranchisement, war seemed to be declared. Centuries
were necessary to effect the reconciliation of these two great
powers, and to make them understand that their interests were
in common. At the twelfth century they had nothing in com-
mon.
SEVENTH LECTURE.
WE have conducted, down to the twelfth century, the
history of the two great elements of civilization,
the feudal system and the church. It is the third
of these fundamental elements, I mean the boroughs, which
now we have to trace likewise down to the twelfth century,
confining ourselves to the same limits which we have observed
in the other two.
We shall find ourselves differently situated with regard to
the boroughs, from what we were with regard to the church
or the feudal system. From the fifth to the twelfth century,
the feudal system and the church, although at a later period
they experienced new developments, showed themselves al-
most complete, and in a definitive state; we have watched
their birth, increase and maturity. It is not so with the bor-
oughs. It is only at the end of the epoch which now occupies
us, in the eleventh and twelfth centuries, that they take up
any position in history ; not but that before then they had a his-
tory which was deserving of study; nor is it that there were not
long before this epoch traces of their existence; but it was only
at the eleventh century that they became evidently visible
upon the great scene of the world, and as an important element
of modern civilization. Thus, in the feudal system and the
church, from the fifth to the twelfth century, we have seen
the eflfects born and developed from the causes. Whenever,
by way of induction or conjecture, we have deduced certain
principles and results, we have been able to verify them by
an inquiry into the facts themselves. As regards the bor-
oughs, this facility fails us; we are present only at their
birth. At present I must confine myself to causes and origins.
What I say concerning the eflfects of the existence of the
boroughs, and their influence in the course of Euroi>ean civili-
zation, I shall say in some measure by way of anticipation.
I cannot invoke the testimony of contemporaneous and known
facts. It is at a later period, from the twelfth to the fifteenth
century, that we shall see the boroughs taking their development,
the institution bearing all its fruit, and history proving our
assertions. I dwell upon this difiference of situation in order
to anticipate your objections against the incompleteness and
104
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 105
prematurity of the picture which I am about to offer you.
I will suppose that in 1789, at the time of the commencement
of the terrible regeneration of France, a burgher of the twelfth
century had suddenly appeared among us, and that he had
been given to read, provided he knew how, one of the pam-
phlets which so powerfully agitated mind ; for example, the
pamphlet of M. Sieyes — '' Who is the third estate ? " His
eyes fall upon this sentence, which is the foundation of the
pamphlet: "The third estate is the French nation, less the
nobility and the clergy." I ask you, what would be the effect
of such a phrase upon the mind of such a man? Do you
suppose he would understand it ? No, he could not understand
the words, the French nation, because they would represent
to him no fact with which he was acquainted, no fact of his age ;
and if he understood the phrase, if he clearly saw in it this
sovereignty attributed to the third estate above all society,
of a verity it would appear to him mad, impious, such would
be its contradiction to all that he had seen, to all his ideas
and sentiments.
Now, ask this astonished burgher to follow you: lead him
to one of the French boroughs of this epoch, to Rheims, Beau-
vais, Laon, or Noyon ; a different kind of astonishment would
seize him : he enters a town ; he sees neither towers nor ram-
parts, nor burgher militia ; no means of defence ; all is open,
all exposed to the first comer, and the first occupant. The
burgher would doubt the safety of this borough; he would
think it weak and ill-secured. He penetrates into the interior,
and inquires what is passing, in what manner it is governed,
and what are its inhabitants. They tell him that beyond the
walls there is a power which taxes them at pleasure without
their consent; which convokes their militia and sends it to
war without their voice in the matter. He speaks to them of
magistrates, of the mayor, and of the aldermen ; and he hears
that the burghers do not nominate them. He learns that the
affairs of the borough are not decided in the borough; but
that a man belonging to the king, an intendant, administers
them, alone and at a distance. Furthermore, they will tell him
that the inhabitants have not the right of assembling and de-
liberating in common upon matters which concern them ; that
they are never summoned to the public place by the bell of
their church. The burgher of the twelfth century would be
confounded. First, he was stupefied and dismayed at the
grandeur and importance that the communal nation, the third
estate, attributed to itself; and now he finds it on its own
hearthstone in a state of servitude, weakness, and nonentity,
far worse than any thing which he had experienced. He
passes from one spectacle to another utterly different, from
io6 GUIZOT
the view of a sovereign burghership to that of one entirely
powerless. How would you have him comprehend this, — rec-
oncile it, so that his mind be not overcome?
Let us burghers of the nineteenth century go back to the
twelfth and be present at an exactly corresponding double
spectacle. Whenever we regard the general affairs of a coun-
try, its state, its government, the whole society, we shall see
no burghers, hear, speak of none; they interfere in nothing,
and are quite unimportant. And not only have they no im-
portance in the state, but if we would know what they think
of their situation, and how they speak of it, and what their
position in regard to their relation with the government of
France in general is in their own eyes, we shall find in their
language an extraordinary timidity and humility. Their ancient
masters, the lords, from whom they forced their franchises,
treat them, at least in words, with a haughtiness which con-
founds us; but it neither astonishes nor irritates them.
Let us enter into the borough itself; let us see what passes
there. The scene changes; we are in a kind of fortified place
defended by armed burghers: these burghers tax themselves,
elect their magistrates, judge and punish, and assemble for
the purpose of deliberating upon their affairs. All come to
these assemblies ; they make war on their own account against
their lord; and they have a militia. In a word, they govern
themselves; they are sovereigns. This is the same contrast
which in the France of the eighteenth century so much aston-
ished the burghers of the twelfth; it is only the parts that
are changed. In the latter, the burgher nation is all, the bor-
ough nothing; in the former, the burghership is nothing, the
borough everything.
Assuredly, between the twelfth and the eighteenth century,
many things must have passed — many extraordinary events,
and many revolutions have been accomplished, to bring about,
in the existence of a social class, so enormous a change. Despite
this change, there can be no doubt but that the third estate
of 1789 was, politically speaking, the descendant and heir of
the corporations of the twelfth century. This French nation,
so haughty and ambitious, which raises its pretensions so high,
which so loudly proclaims its sovereignty, which pretends not
only to regenerate and govern itself, but to govern and regen-
erate the world, undoubtedly descends, principally at least,
from the burghers who obscurely though courageously revolted
in the twelfth century, with the sole end of escaping in some
corner of the land from the obscure tyranny of the lords.
Most assuredly it is not in the state of the boroughs in the
twelfth century that we shall find the explanation of such a
metamorphosis : it was accomplished and had its causes in the
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 107
events which succeeded it from the twelfth to the eighteenth
century; it is there that we shall meet it in its progression.
Still the origin of the third estate has played an important
part in its history ; although we shall not find there the secret
of its destiny, we shall, at least, find its germ: for what it
was at first is again found in what it has become, perhaps,
even to a greater extent than appearances would allow of our
presuming. A picture, even an incomplete one, of the state of
the boroughs in the twelfth century, will, I think, leave you
convinced of this.
The better to understand this state, it is necessary to con-
sider the boroughs from two principal points of view. There
are two great questions to resolve; the first, that of the en-
franchisement of the boroughs itself — the question how the
revolution was operated, and from what causes — what change
it brought into the situation of the burghers, what effect it has
had upon society in general, upon the other classes and upon
the state. The second question relates only to the govern-
ment of the boroughs, the internal condition of the enfranchised
towns, the relations of the burghers among themselves, and
the principles, forms and manners which dominated in the cities.
It is from these two sources, on the one hand, from the change
introduced into the social condition of the burghers, and on
the other, from their internal government and their communal
condition, that all their influence upon modern civilization origi-
nated. There are no facts produced by this influence but
which should be referred to one or other of these causes. When,
therefore, we shall have summed them up, when we thor-
oughly understand, on one side, the enfranchisement of the
boroughs, and on the other, the government of the boroughs,
we shall be in possession, so to speak, of the two keys to their
history.
Lastly, I shall say a word concerning the various state of the
boroughs throughout Europe. The facts which I am about to
place before you do not apply indifferently to all the boroughs
of the twelfth century, to the boroughs of Italy, Spain, Eng-
land, or France ; there are certainly some which belong to all,
but the differences are great and important. I shall point
them out in passing ; we shall again encounter them in a later
period of civilization, and we will then investigate them more
closely.
To understand the enfranchisement of the boroughs, it is
necessary to recall to your minds what was the state of the
towns from the fifth to the eleventh century — from the fall
of the Roman Empire down to the commencement of the com-
munal revolution. Here, I repeat, the differences were very
great ; the state of the towns varied prodigiously in the various
io8 GUIZOT
countries of Europe; still there are general facts which may
be affirmed of almost all towns ; and I shall try to confine my-
self to them. When I depart from this restriction, what I
say more especially will apply to the boroughs of France, and
particularly to the boroughs of the north of France, beyond the
Rhone and the Loire. These will be the prominent points in
the picture which I shall attempt to trace.
After the fall of the Roman Empire, from the fifth to the
tenth century, the condition of the towns was one neither of
servitude nor liberty. one runs the same risk in the employ-
ment of words that I spoke of the other day in the painting
of men and events. When a society and a language has long
existed, the words take a complete, determined and precise
sense, a legal and official sense, in a manner. Time has intro-
duced into the sense of each term a multitude of ideas which
arise the moment that it is pronounced, and which, not belong-
ing to the same date, are not applicable alike to all times. For
example, the words servitude and liberty call to our minds in the
present day ideas infinitely more precise and complete than
the corresponding facts of the eighth, ninth or tenth centuries.
If we say that, at the eighth century, the towns were in a state
of liberty, we say far too much ; in the present day we attach
a sense to the word liberty which does not represent the fact
of the eighth century. We shall fall into the same error if we
say that the towns were in a state of servitude, because the
word implies an entirely different thing from the municipal
facts of that period.
I repeat that at that time the towns were neither in a state
of servitude nor liberty; they suffered all the ills which ac-
company weakness ; they were a prey to the violence and con-
tinual depredations of the strong; but yet, despite all these
fearful disorders, despite their impoverishment and depopula-
tion, the towns had preserved ancl did still preserve a certain
importance : in most of them there was a clergy, a bishop, who
by the great exercise of power, and his influence upon the
population, served as a connecting link between them and their
conquerors, and thus maintained the town in a kind of in-
dependence, and covered it with the shield of religion. More-
over, there remained in the towns many wrecks of Roman
institutions. one meets at this epoch (and many facts of this
nature have been collected by MM. de Savigny and Hullman,
Mademoiselle de Lezardiere, etc.) with frequent convocations
of the senate, of the curia; there is mention made of public
assemblies and municipal magistrates. The affairs of the civil
order, wills, grants and a multitude of acts of civil life, were
legalized in the curia by its magistrates, as was the case in
the Roman municipality. The remains of urban activity and
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 109
liberty, it is true, gradually disappeared. Barbarism, disorder
and always increasing misfortunes accelerated the depopula-
tion. The establishment of the masters of the land in the rural
districts, and the growing preponderance of agricultural life,
were new causes of decay to the towns. The bishops them-
selves, when they had entered the frame of feudalism, placed
less importance on their municipal existence. Finally, when
feudalism had completely triumphed, the towns, without falling
into the servitude of serfs, found themselves entirely in the
hands of a lord, inclosed within some fief, and robbed of all
the independence which had been left to them, even in the most
barbarous times, in the first ages of the invasion. So that from
the fifth century down to the time of the complete organiza-
tion of feudalism the condition of the towns was always upon
the decline.
When once feudalism was thoroughly established, when each
man had taken his place, and was settled upon his land, when
the wandering life had ceased, after some time the towns again
began to acquire some importance and to display anew some ac-
tivity. It is, as you know, with human activity as with the
fecundity of the earth; from the time that commotion ceases
it reappears and makes everything germinate and flourish.
With the least glimpse of order and peace man takes hope,
and with hope goes to work. It was thus with the towns ; the
moment that feudalism was a little fixed new wants sprang
up among the fief-holders, a certain taste for progress and
amelioration; to supply this want a Httle commerce and in-
dustry reappeared in the towns of their domain; riches and
population returned to them ; slowly, it is true, but still they
returned. Among the circumstances which contributed thereto,
one, I think, is too little regarded; this is the right of sanc-
tuary in the churches. Before the boroughs had established
themselves, before their strength and their ramparts enabled
them to oflfer an asylum to the afflicted population of the coun-
try, when as yet they had no safety but that afforded by the
church, this sufficed to draw into the towns many unhappy
fugitives. They came to shelter themselves in or around the
church; and it was not only the case with the inferior class,
with serfs and boors, who sought safety, but often with men
of importance, rich outlaws. The chronicles of the time are
filled with examples of this nature. one sees men, formerly
powerful themselves, pursued by a more powerful neighbor, or
even by the king himself, who abandon their domains, carry-
ing with them all they can, shut themselves up within a town,
and putting themselves under the protection of the church
become citizens. These kind of refugees have not been, I
think, without their influence upon the progress of the towns;
no GUIZOT
they introduced into them riches, and elements of a superior
population to the mass of their inhabitants. Besides, who
knows not that when once an association is in part formed,
men flock to it, both because they find more safety and also
for the mere sake of that sociability which never leaves them ?
By the concurrence of all these causes, after the feudal gov-
ernment was in some manner regulated, the towns regained
a little strength. Their security, however, did not return to
them in the same proportion. The wandering life had ceased,
it is true, but the wandering life had been for the conquerors,
for the new proprietors of the soil, a principal means of satis-
fying their passions. When they had wished to pillage they
made an excursion, they went to a distance to seek another
fortune, another domain. When each was nearly established,
when it became necessary to renounce this conquering vagrancy,
there was no cessation of their avidity, their inordinate wants,
nor their violent desires. Their weight then fell on the people
nearest at hand, upon the towns. Instead of going to a distance
to pillage, they pillaged at home. The extortions of the nobility
upon the burgesses were redoubled from the commencement of
the tenth century. Whenever the proprietor of a domain in
which a town was situated had any fit of avarice to satisfy
it was upon the burgesses that he exercised his violence. This,
above all, was the epoch in which the complaints of the bur-
gesses against the absolute want of security of commerce burst
forth. The merchants, after having made their journeys, were
not permitted to enter their towns in peace; the roads and
approaches were incessantly beset by the lord and his followers.
The time at which industry was recommencing was exactly
that in which security was most wanting. Nothing can irri-
tate a man more than being thus interfered with in his work,
and despoiled of the fruits which he had promised himself
from it. He is far more annoyed and enraged than when har-
assed in an existence which has been some time fixed and
monotonous, when that which is carried from him has not
been the result of his own activity, has not excited in his bosom
all the pleasures of hope. There is, in the progressive move-
ment toward fortune of a man or a population, a principle of
resistance against injustice and violence far more energetic
than in any other situation.
This, then, was the position of the towns during the tenth
century; they had more strength, more importance, more
riches, and more interests to defend. At the same time it was
more than ever necessary to defend them, because this strength,
these interests, these riches, became an object of envy to the
lords. The danger and evil increased with the means of resist-
ing them. Moreover, the feudal system gave to all those who
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE iii
participated in it the example of continued resistance ; it never
presented to the mind the idea of an organized government,
capable of ruling and quelling all by imposing its single inter-
vention. It offered, on the contrary, the continuous spectacle
of the individual will refusing submission. Such, for the most
part, was the position of the possessors of fiefs toward their
superiors, of the lesser lords toward the greater; so that at
the moment when the towns were tormented and oppressed,
when they had new and most important interests to sustain,
at that moment they had before their eyes a continual lesson
of insurrection. The feudal system has rendered one service
to humanity, that of incessantly showing to men the individual
will in the full display of its energy. The lesson prospered :
in spite of their weakness, in spite of the infinite inequality
of condition between them and their lords, the towns arose in
insurrection on all sides.
It is difficult to assign an exact date to this event. It is gen-
erally said that the enfranchisement of the commons com-
menced in the eleventh century ; but, in all great events, how
many unhappy and unknown efforts occur before the one which
succeeds ! In all things, to accomplish its designs, Providence
lavishly expends courage, virtues, sacrifices, in a word, man
himself ; and it is only after an unknown number of unrecorded
labors, after a host of noble hearts have succumbed in dis-
couragement, convinced that their cause is lost, it is only
then that the cause triumphs. It doubtless happened thus with
the commons. Doubtless, in the eighth, ninth and tenth cen-
turies, there were many attempts at resistance, and movements
toward enfranchisement, which not only were unsuccessful,
but of which the memory remained alike without glory or
success. It is true, however, that these attempts have in-
fluenced posterior events; they reanimated and sustained the
spirit of liberty, and prepared the way for the great insur-
rection of the eleventh century.
I say designedly, insurrection. The enfranchisement of the
commons in the eleventh century was the fruit of a veritable
insurrection, and a veritable war, a war declared by the popu-
lation of the towns against their lords. The first fact which
is always met with in such histories, is the rising of the bur-
gesses, who arm themselves with the first thing that comes
to hand ; the expulsion of the followers of the lord who have
come to put in force some extortion; or it is an enterprise
against the castle; these are always the characteristics of the
war. If the insurrection fails, what is done by the conqueror ?
He orders the destruction of the fortification raised by the
citizens, not only round the town but round each house. one
sees at the time of the confederation, after having promised
112 GUIZOT
to act in common, and after taking the oath of mutual aid, the
first act of the citizen is to fortify himself within his house.
Some boroughs, of which at this day the name is entirely
obscure, as, for example, the little borough of Vezelay in
Nivernois, maintained a very long and energetic struggle
against their lord. Victory fell to the abbot of Vezelay; he
immediately enjoined the demolition of the fortifications of
the citizens' houses ; the names of many are preserved whose
fortified houses were thus immediately destroyed.
Let us enter the interior of the habitations of our ancestors ;
let us study the mode of their construction and the kind of
life which they suggest; all is devoted to war, all has the
character of war.
This is the construction of a citizen's house in the twelfth
century, as far as we can follow it out: there were generally
three floors, with one room upon each floor; the room on
the ground floor was the common room, where the family
took their meals; the first floor was very high up, by way
of security; this is the most remarkable characteristic of the
construction. on this floor was the room which the citizen
and his wife inhabited. The house was almost always flanked
by a tower at the angle, generally of a square form ; another
symptom of war, a means of defence. on the second floor
was a room, the use of which is doubtful, but which probably
served for the children, and the rest of the family. Above,
very often, was a small platform, evidently intended for a place
of observation. The whole construction of the house sug-
gests war. This was the evident character, the true name of
the movement which produced the enfranchisement of the
commons.
When war has lasted a certain time, whoever may be the
belligerent powers, it necessarily leads to peace. The treaties
of peace between the commons and their adversaries were the
charters. The borough charters are mere treaties of peace
between the burgesses and their lord.
The insurrection was general. When I say general, I do
not mean that there was a union or coalition between all the
citizens in a country ; far from it. The situation of the com-
mons was almost everywhere the same ; they were everywhere
a prey to the same danger, afflicted with the same evil. Having
acquired almost the same means of resistance and defence,
they employed them at nearly the same epoch. Example, too,
may have done something, and the success of one or two bor-
oughs may have been contagious. The charters seem some-
times to have been drawn after the same pattern : that of
Noyon, for example, served as a model for those of Beauvais,
St. Quentin, etc. I doubt, however, whether example had so
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 113
much influence as has been supposed. Communications were
difficuh and rare, and hearsay vague and transient ; it is more
likely that the insurrection was the result of a similar situation,
and of a general and spontaneous movement. When I say
general, I mean to say that it took place almost everywhere;
for, I repeat, that the movement was not unanimous and con-
certed, all was special and local; each borough was insurgent
against its lord upon its own account; all passed in its own
locality.
The vicissitudes of the struggle were great. Not only did
success alternate, but even when peace seemed established,
after the charter had been sworn to by each party, it was
violated and eluded in every way. The kings played a great
part in the alternations of this struggle. Of this I shall speak
in detail when I treat of royalty itself. Its influence in the
movement of communal enfranchisement has been sometimes
praised, perhaps too highly; sometimes, I think, too much
undervalued, and sometimes denied. I shall confine myself at
present to saying that it frequently interfered, sometimes in-
voked by the boroughs and sometimes by the lords; that it
has often played contrary parts; that it has acted sometimes
on one principle, sometimes on another ; that it has unceasingly
changed its intentions, designs, and conduct; but that, upon
the whole, it has done much, and with more of good than of
evil effect.
Despite these vicissitudes, despite the continual violations of
charters, the enfranchisement of the boroughs was consum-
mated in the twelfth century. All Europe, and especially
France, which for a century had been covered with insurrec-
tions, was covered with charters more or less favorable; the
corporations enjoyed them with more or less security, but still
they enjoyed them. The fact prevailed, and the right was
established.
Let us now attempt to discover the immediate results of
this great fact, and what changes it introduced into the con-
dition of the burgesses, in the midst of society.
In the first place, it changed nothing, at least not in the
commencement, in the relations of the burgesses with the gen-
eral government of the country — with what we of the present
day call the state; they interfered no more in it than hereto-
fore, all remained local, inclosed within the limits of the fief.
one circumstance, however, should modify this assertion, a
bond now began to be established between the citizens and the
king. At times the burgesses had invoked the aid of the
king against their lord, or his guarantee, when the charter
was promised or sworn to. At other times, the lords had
invoked the judgment of the king between themselves and the
8
114
GUIZOT
citizens. At the demand of either one or other of the parties,
in a multitude of different causes, royalty had interfered in the
quarrel; from thence resulted a frequent relation, and some-
times a rather intimate one, between the burgesses and the
king. It was by this relation that the burgesses approached
the center of the state, and began to have a connection with
the general government.
Notwithstanding that all remained local, a new and gen-
eral class was created by the enfranchisement. No coalition
had existed between the citizens; they had, as a class, no
common and public existence. But the country was filled
with men in the same situation, having the same interests and
the same manners, between whom a certain bond of unity could
not fail of being gradually established, which should give rise
to the bourgeoisie. The formation of a great social class, the
bourgeoisie, was the necessary result of the local enfranchise-
ment of the burghers.
It must not be imagined that this class was at this time
that which it has since become. Not only has its situation
changed, but its elements were entirely different: in the
twelfth century it consisted almost entirely of merchants,
traders carrying on a petty commerce, and of small proprietors,
either of land or houses, who had taken up their residence
in the town. Three centuries after, the bourgeoisie compre-
hended, besides, advocates, physicians, learned men of all sorts,
and all the local magistrates. The bourgeoisie was formed
gradually, and of very different elements ; as a general thing,
in its history no account is given of its succession or diversity.
Wherever the bourgeoisie is spoken of, it seems to be sup-
posed that at all epochs it was composed of the same elements.
This is an absurd supposition. It is perhaps in the diversity
of its composition at different epochs of history that we should
look for the secret of its destiny. So long as it did not in-
clude magistrates nor men of letters, so long as it was not what
it became in the sixteenth century, it possessed neither the
same importance nor the same character in the state. To
comprehend the vicissitudes of its fortune and power, it is
necessary to observe in its bosom the successive rise of new
professions, new moral positions, and a new intellectual state.
In the twelfth century, I repeat, it was composed of only the
small merchants, who retired into the towns after having made
their purchases and sales, and of the proprietors of houses and
small domains who had fixed their residence there. Here
we see the European burgher class in its first elements.
The third great consequence of the enfranchisement of the
commons was the contest of classes, a contest which constitutes
the fact itself, and which fills modern history. Modern Europe
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 115
was born from the struggle of the various classes of society.
Elsewhere, as I have already observed, this struggle led to very
different results: in Asia, for example, one class completely
triumphed, and the government of castes succeeded to that of
classes, and society sunk into immobility. Thank God, none of
this has happened in Europe. Neither of the classes has been
able to conquer or subdue the others ; the struggle, instead of be-
coming a principle of immobility, has been a cause of prog-
ress; the relations of the principal classes among themselves,
the necessity under which they found themselves of combat-
ing and yielding by turns; the variety of their interests and
passions, the desire to conquer without the power to satisfy it ;
from all this has arisen perhaps the most energetic and fertile
principle of the development of European civilization. The
classes have incessantly struggled; they detested each other;
an utter diversity of situation, of interests, and of manners,
produced between them a profound moral hostility: and yet
they have progressively approached nearer, come to an under-
standing, and assimilated ; every European nation has seen
the birth and development in its bosom of a certain universal
spirit, a certain community of interests, ideas, and sentiments,
which have triumphed over diversity and war. In France, for
example, in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the social
and moral separation of the classes was still very profound ;
yet the fusion was advancing; still, without doubt, at that
time there was a veritable French nation, not an exclusive
class, but which embraced them all, and in which all were
animated by a certain sentiment in common, having a com-
mon social existence, strongly impressed, in a word, with na-
tionality. Thus, from the bosom of variety, enmity and war
has arisen in modern Europe the national unity so striking in
the present day, and which tends to develop and refine itself,
from day to day, with still greater brilliancy.
Such are the great, external, apparent and social effects of
the revolution which at present occupies us. Let us investigate
its moral effects, what changes it brought about in the soul
of the citizens themselves, what they became, what, in fact,
they necessarily became morally in their new situation.
There is a fact by which it is impossible not to be struck
while contemplating the relation of the burghers toward the
state in general, the government of the state, and the general
interests of the country, not only in the twelfth century, but
also in subsequent ages ; I mean the prodigious timidity of
the citizens, their humility, the excessive modesty of their
pretensions as to the government of the country, and the facility
with which they contented themselves. Nothing is seen among
them of the true political spirit which aspires to influence,
ii6 GUIZOT
reform and govern ; nothing which gives proof of boldness of
thought or grandeur of ambition ; one might call them sensible-
minded, honest, freed men.
There are but two sources in the sphere of politics from
which greatness of ambition or firmness of thought can arise.
It is necessary to have either the feeling of immense im-
portance, of great power exercised upon the destiny of others,
and in a vast extent — or else it is necessary to bear within one's
self a feeling of complete individual independence, a confidence
in one's own liberty, a conviction of a destiny foreign to all
will but that of the man himself. To one or other of these
two conditions seem to belong boldness of thought, greatness
of ambition, the desire of acting in an enlarged sphere, and
of obtaining great results.
Neither one nor the other of these conditions entered into
the condition of the burghers of the middle ages. These, as
you have just seen, were only important to themselves; they
exercised no sensible influence beyond their own town, or upon
the state in general. Nor could they have any great senti-
ment of individual independence. It was in vain that they
conquered, in vain that they obtained a charter. The citizen
of a town, in comparing himself with the inferior lord who
dwelt near him, and who had just been conquered, was not
the less sensible of his extreme inferiority; he was not filled
with the haughty sentiment of independence which animated
the proprietor of the fief; he held not his portion of liberty
from himself alone, but from his association with others; a
difficult and precarious succor. Hence that character of re-
serve, of timidity of spirit, of retiring modesty and humility of
language, even in conjunction with a firmness of conduct,
which is so deeply imprinted in the life of the citizens, not
only in the twelfth century, but even of their descendants.
They had no taste for great enterprises, and when fate forced
them among them, they were uneasy and embarrassed ; the
responsibility annoyed them ; they felt that they were out of
their sphere of action, and wished to return to it ; they there-
fore treated on moderate terms. Thus one finds in the course
of European history, especially of France, that the bourgeoisie
has been esteemed, considered, flattered, and even respected,
but rarely feared ; it has rarely produced upon its adversaries
an impression of a great and haughty power, of a truly political
power. There is nothing to be surprised at in this weakness
of the modern bourgeoisie; its principal cause lay in its very
origin, and in the circumstances of its enfranchisement, which
I have just placed before you. A high ambition, independently
of social conditions, enlargement and firmness of poHtical
thought, the desire to participate in the affairs of the country,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 117
the full consciousness of the greatness of man as man, and
of the power which belongs to him, if he is capable of exercis-
ing it, these are in Europe sentiments and dispositions entirely
modern, the fruit of modern civilization, the fruit of that
glorious and powerful universality which characterizes it, and
which cannot fail of insuring to the public an influence and
weight in the government of the country, which were always
wanting, and necessarily so, to the burghers our ancestors.
on the other hand, they acquired and displayed, in the
struggle of local interests which they had to maintain in their
narrow stage, a degree of energy, devotedness, perseverance
and patience which has never been surpassed. The difficulty of
the enterprise was such, and such the perils which they had
to strive against, that a display of unexampled courage was
necessary. In the present day, a very false idea is formed of
the life of the burghers in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries.
You have read in one of the novels of Walter Scott, " Quentin
Durward," the representation he has given of the burgomaster
of Liege ; he has made of him a regular burgher in a comedy,
fat, indolent, without experience or boldness, and wholly oc-
cupied in passing his life easily. Whereas, the burghers of
this period always had a coat of mail upon their breast, a pike
in their hand ; their life was as tempestuous, as warlike and
as hardy as that of the lords with whom they fought. It
was in these continual perils, in struggling against all the
difficulties of practical life, that they acquired that manly char-
acter and that obstinate energy which is, in a measure, lost in
the soft activity of modern times.
None of these social or moral efforts of the enfranchise-
ment of the boroughs had attained their development in the
twelfth century; it is in the following centuries that they
distinctly appeared, and are easily discernible. It is certain,
however, that the germ was laid in the original situation of
the boroughs, in the manner of their enfranchisement, and
the place then taken by the burghers in society. I was, there-
fore, right in placing them before you alone. Let us now
investigate the interior of the borough of the twelfth century ;
let us see how it was governed, what principles and facts
dominated in the relations of the citizens among themselves.
You will recollect that in speaking of the municipal system,
bequeathed by the Roman Empire to the modern world, I
told you that the Roman Empire was a great coalition of
municipalities, formerly sovereign municipalities like Rome
itself. Each of these towns had originally possessed the same
existence as Rome, had once been a small independent republic,
making peace and war, and governing itself as it thought
proper. In proportion as they became incorporated with the
1x8 GUIZOT
Roman Empire the rights which constitute sovereignty, the
riglit of peace and war, the right of legislation, the right of
taxation, etc., left each town and centred in Rome. There re-
mained but one sovereign municipality, Rome, reigning over
a large number of municipalities which had now only a civil
existence. The municipal system changed its character; and
instead of being a political government and a system of sover-
eignty, it became a mode of administration.
This was the great revolution which was consummated under
the Roman Empire. The municipal system became a mode of
administration, was reduced to the government of local affairs
and the civic interests of the city. This was the condition in
which the towns and their institutions were left at the fall of
the Roman Empire. In the midst of the chaos and barbarism,
all ideas, as well as facts, were in utter confusion; all the
attributes of sovereignty and of the administration were con-
founded. These distinctions were no longer attended to. Af-
fairs were abandoned to the course of necessity. There was
a sovereign, or an administrator, in each locality, according
to circumstances. When the towns rose in insurrection to
recover some security, they took upon themselves the sover-
eignty. It was not in any way for the purpose of following out
a political theory, nor from a feeling of their dignity ; it was
that they might have the means of resisting the lords against
whom they rebelled that they appropriated to themselves the
right of levying militia, of taxations for the purposes of war,
of themselves nominating their chiefs and magistrates; in a
word, of governing themselves. The government in the interior
of the towns was the means of defence and security. Thus
sovereignty re-entered the municipal system, from which it had
been eradicated by the conquests of Rome. The boroughs
again became sovereign. We have here the political character
of their enfranchisement.
It does not follow that this sovereignty was complete. It
always retained some trace of external sovereignty: some-
times the lord preserved to himself the right of sending
a magistrate into the town, who took for his assessors the
municipal magistrates; sometimes he possessed the right of
receiving certain revenues ; elsewhere a tribute was secured to
him. Sometimes the external sovereignty of the community
lay in the hands of the king.
The boroughs themselves having entered within the frame
of feudalism had vassals, became suzerains, and by virtue of
this title partly possessed themselves of the sovereignty which
was inherent in the lord paramount. This caused a con-
fusion between the rights which they had from their feudal
position, and those which they had conquered by their insur-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 119
rections ; and under this double title the sovereignty belonged
to them.
Thus we see, as far as can be judged from very deficient
monuments, how government was administered, at least in the
early ages in the interior of a borough. The totality of the
inhabitants formed the assembly of the borough ; all those who
had sworn the borough oath (and whoever lived within the
walls was obliged to do so) were convoked by the ringing
of a bell to the general assembly. It was there that they
nominated the magistrates. The number and form of the mag-
istracy were very various. The magistrates being once nomi-
nated, the assembly was dissolved, and the magistrates gov-
erned almost alone, somewhat arbitrarily, and without any
other responsibility than that of the new elections or popular
riots, which were the chief mode of responsibility in those
times.
You see that the internal organization of boroughs reduced
itself to two very simple elements; the general assembly of
the inhabitants, and a government invested with an almost
arbitrary power, under the responsibility of insurrections and
riots. It was impossible, principally from the state of man-
ners, to establish a regular government, with veritable guaran-
tees for order and duration. The greater portion of the popu-
lation of the boroughs was in a state of ignorance, brutality
and ferocity, which it would have been very difficult to govern.
After a short time, there was almost as little security in the
interior of the borough as there had formerly been in the
relations between the burgher and the lord. There was formed,
however, very quickly a superior bourgeoisie. You can easily
comprehend the causes. The state of ideas and of social rela-
tions led to the establishment of industrial professions, legally
constituted corporations. The system of privilege was intro-
duced into the interior of boroughs, and from this a great
inequality ensued. There was shortly everywhere a certain
number of rich and important burghers, and a working popu-
lation more or less numerous, which, in spite of its inferiority,
had an important influence in the affairs of the borough. The
boroughs were then divided into a high bourgeoisie and a
population subject to all the errors and vices of a populace.
The superior bourgeoisie found itself pressed between the im-
mense difficulty of governing the inferior population, and the
incessant attempts of the ancient master of the borough, who
sought to re-establish his power. Such was its situation, not
only in France but in all Europe, down to the si>fteenth cen-
tury. This perhaps has been the chief means of preventing
the corporations, in most European nations, and especially in
France, from possessing all the important political influence
I20 GUIZOT
which they might otherwise have had. Two principles car-
ried on incessant warfare within them ; in the inferior popula-
tion, a blind, unbridled and ferocious spirit of democracy;
and as a consequence, in the superior population, a spirit of
timidity at making agreements, an excessive facility of concilia-
tion, whether in regard to the king, the ancient lords, or in re-
establishing some peace and order in the interior of the bor-
ough. Each of these principles could not but tend to deprive
the corporation of any great influence in the state.
All these effects were not visible in the twelfth century;
still, however, one might foresee them in the very character
of the insurrection, in the manner of its commencement, and in
the condition of the various elements of the communal popu-
lation.
Such, if I mistake not, are the principal characteristics and
the general results of the enfranchisement of the boroughs
and of their internal government. I forewarn you that these
facts were neither so uniform nor so universal as I have broadly
represented them. There is great diversity in the history of
boroughs in Europe. For example, in Italy and in the south
of France, the Roman municipal system dominated ; there was
not merely so much diversity and inequality here as in the north,
and the communal organization was much better, either by
reason of the Roman traditions, or from the superior condition
of the population. In the north the feudal system prevailed in
the communal existence ; there, all was subordinate to the
struggle against the lords. The boroughs of the south were
more occupied with their internal organization, amelioration
and progress ; they thought only of becoming independent
republics. The destiny of the northern borouglis, in France
particularly, showed thmselves more and more incomplete and
destined for less fine developments. If we glance at the bor-
oughs of Germany, Spain and England, we shall find in them
other differences. I shall not enter into these details ; we shall
remark some of them as we advance in the history of civiliza-
tion. In their origin, all things are nearly confounded under
one physiognomy; it is only by successive developments that
variety shows itself. Then commences a new development
which urges society toward free and high unity, the glorious
end of all the efforts and wishes of the human race.
EIGHTH LECTURE.
I HAVE not as yet explained to you the complete plan of
my course. I commenced by indicating its object; I
then passed in review European civilization without con-
sidering it as a whole, without indicating to you at one and
the same time the point of departure, the route, and the port,
the commencement, the middle and the end. We have now,
however, arrived at an epoch when this entire view, this general
sketch of the region which we survey, has become necessary.
The times which have hitherto occupied us in some measure
explain themselves, or are explained by immediate and evident
results. Those upon which we are about to enter would not
be understood, nor even would they excite any lively interest,
unless they are connected with even the most indirect and
distant of their consequences.
In so extensive a study, moments occur when we can no
longer consent to proceed while all before us is unknown and
dark. We wish not only to know whence we have come and
where we are, but also to what point we tend. This is what
we now feel. The epoch to which we are approaching is not
intelligible, nor can its importance be appreciated except by
the relations which unite it to modern times. Its true mean-
ing is not evident until a later period.
We are in possession of almost all the essential elements
of European civilization. I say almost, because as yet I have
not spoken to you of royalty. The decisive crisis of the de-
velopment of royalty did not take place until the twelfth or
even thirteenth century. It was not until then that the institu-
tion was really constituted, and that it began to occupy a definite
place in modern society. I have, therefore, not treated of it
earlier; it will form the subject of my next lecture. With
this exception, I repeat, we have before us all the great ele-
ments of European civilization. You have beheld the birth
of feudal aristocracy, of the church, the boroughs; you have
seen the institutions which should correspond to these facts;
and not only the institutions, but also the principles and ideas
which these facts should raise up in the mind. Thus, while
treating of feudalism, you were present at the cradle of the
modern family, at the hearth of domestic life ; you have com-
121
122 GUIZOT
prehended, in all its energy, the sentiment of individual inde-
pendence, and the place which it has held in our civilization.
With regard to the church, you have seen the purely religious
society rise up, its relations with the civil society, the theo-
cratical principle, the separation of the spiritual and temporal
powers, the first blows of persecutions, and the first cries of
the liberty of conscience. The rising boroughs have shown
you glimpses of an association founded upon altogether other
principles than those of feudalism and the church, the diversity
of the social classes, their struggles, the first and profound
characteristics of modern burgher manners, timidity of spirit
side by side with energy of soul, the demagogue spirit side
by side with the legal spirit. In a word, all the elements which
have contributed to the formation of European society, all that
it has been, and, so to speak, all that it has suggested, have
already met your view.
Let us now transport ourselves to the heart of modern Europe.
I speak not of existing Europe, after the prodigious meta-
morphoses which we have witnessed, but of Europe in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. I ask you, do you recog-
nize the society which we have just seen in the twelfth cent-
ury? What a wonderful difference! I have already dwelt
upon this difference as regards the boroughs. I afterward tried
to make you sensible of how little the third estate of the eigh-
teenth century resembled that of the twelfth. If we make the
same essay upon feudalism and the church, we shall be struck
with the same metamorphosis. There was no more resemblance
between the nobility at the court of Louis XV and the feudal
aristocracy, or between the church of Cardinal de Bernis and
that of the Abbot Suger, than between the third estate of the
eighteenth century and the bourgeoisie of the twelfth century.
Between these two epochs, although already in possession of all
its elements, society was entirely transformed.
I wish to establish clearly the general and essential character
of this transformation. From the fifth to the twelfth century
society contained all that I have described. It possessed kings,
a lay aristocracy, a clergy, burghers, laborers, religious and
civil powers — in a word, the germs of everything which is
necessary to form a nation and a government, and yet there
was neither government nor nation. Throughout the epoch
upon which we are occupied there was nothing bearing a
resemblance to a people, properly so called, nor to a veritable
government, in the sense which the words have for us in the
present day. We have encountered a multitude of particular
forces, of special facts, and local institutions : but nothing
general or public; no policy, properly so called, nor no true
nationality.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 123
Let us regard, on the contrary, in Europe of the seven-
teenth and eighteenth centuries; we shall everywhere see two
leading figures present themselves upon the scene of the world,
the government and the people. The action of a universal
power upon the whole country, and the influence of the coun-
try upon the power which governs it, this is society, this is
history: the relations of the two great forces, their alliance
or their struggle, this is what history discovers and relates.
The nobility, the clergy and the burghers, all these particular
classes and forces, now only appear in a secondary rank,
almost like shadows effaced by those two great bodies, the
people and its government.
This, if I mistake not, is the essential feature which dis-
tinguishes modern from primitive Europe; this is the meta-
morphosis which was accomplished from the thirteenth to the
sixteenth centuries.
It is then from the thirteenth to the sixteenth century, that
is to say, in the period which we are about to enter upon, that
the secret of this must be sought for; it is the distinctive
character of this epoch that it was employed in converting
primitive Europe into modern Europe ; and hence its historical
importance and interest. If it is not considered from this
point of view, and unless we everywhere seek what has arisen
from it, not only will it not be understood, but we shall soon
be weary of and annoyed by it. Indeed, viewed in itself, and
apart from its results, it is a period without character, a period
when confusion continues to increase, without our being able
to discover its causes, a period of movement without direction,
and of agitation without result. Royalty, nobility, clergy, bour-
geoisie, all the elements of social order seem to turn in the same
circle, equally incapable of progress or repose. They make at-
tempts of all kinds, but all fail ; they attempt to settle govern-
ments and to establish public liberties; they even attempt re-
ligious reforms, but nothing is accomplished — nothing per-
fected. If ever the human race has been abandoned to a destiny,
agitated and yet stationary, to labor incessant, yet barren of
effect, it was between the thirteenth and the fifteenth centuries
that such was the physiognomy of its condition and its history.
I know of but one work in which this physiogomy is
truly shown, the "Histoire des Dues de Burgogne," by M. de
Barante. I do not speak of the truth which sparkles in the
descriptions of manners, or in the detailed recital of facts, but
of that universal truth which makes the entire book a faithful
image, a sincere mirror of the whole epoch, of which it at the
same time shows the movement and the monotony.
Considered, on the contrary, in its relation to that which fol-
lows, as the transition from the primitive to the modern Europe,
124
GUIZOT
this epoch brightens and becomes animated ; we discover in it a
totaHty, a direction and a progress ; its unity and interest con-
sist in the slow and secret work which is accompHshed in it.
The history of European civilization may then be summed
up into three grand periods : First, a period which I shall call
the period of origins, of formation — a time when the various
elements of our society freed themselves from the chaos, took
being, and showed themselves under their native forms with the
principles which animated them. This period extended nearly
to the twelfth century. Second, the second period is a time of
essay, of trial, of groping; the various elements of the social
order drew near each other, combined, and, as it were, felt each
other, without the power to bring forth anything general, reg-
ular, or durable. This state was not ended, properly speaking,
till the sixteenth century. Third, the period of development,
properly so called, when society in Europe took a definite form,
followed a determined tendency, and progressed rapidly and
universally toward a clear and precise end. This commenced at
the sixteenth century, and now pursues its course.
Such appears to me to be the spectacle of European civiliza-
tion in its whole, and such I shall endeavor to represent it to
you. It is the second period that we enter upon now. We have
to seek in it the great crises and determinative causes of the
social transformation which has been the result of it.
The crusades constitute the first great event which presents
itself to us, which, as it were, opens the epoch of which we
speak. They commenced at the eleventh century, and extended
over the twelfth and thirteenth. Of a surety, a great event;
for since it was completed it has not ceased to occupy philosophic
historians ; even before reading the account of it, all have fore-
seen that it was one of those events which change the condition
of the people, and which it is absolutely necessary to study in
order to comprehend the general course of facts.
The first characteristic of the crusades is their universality;
the whole of Europe joined in them — they were the first Euro-
pean event. Previously to the crusades, Europe had never been
excited by one sentiment, or acted in one cause ; there was no
Europe. The crusades revealed Christian Europe. The French
formed the vans of the first army of crusaders ; but there were
also Germans, Italians, Spaniards, and English. Observe the
second, the third crusade ; all the Christian nations engaged in
it. Nothing like it had yet been seen.
This is not all : just as the crusades form an European event,
so in each country do they form a national event. All classes
of society were animated with the same impression, obeyed the
same idea, abandoned themselves to the same impulse. Kings,
lords, priests, burghers, countrymen, all took the same part, the
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 125
same interest in the crusades. The moral unity of nations was
shown — a fact as novel as the European unity.
When such events happen in the infancy of a people, at a
time when men act freely and spontaneously, without premedi-
tation, without political intention or combination, one recognizes
therein what history calls heroic events — the heroic age of na-
tions. In fact, the crusades constitute the heroic event of
modern Europe — a movement at once individual and general,
national, and yet unregulated.
That such was really their primitive character is verified by all
documents, proved by all facts. Who were the first crusaders
that put themselves in motion? Crowds of the populace, who
set out under the guidance of Peter the Hermit, without prepa-
ration, without guides, and without chiefs, followed rather than
guided by a few obscure knights ; they traversed Germany, the
Greek empire, and dispersed or perished in Asia Minor.
The superior class, the feudal nobility, in their turn became
eager in the cause of the crusade. Under the command of
Godefroi de Bouillon, the lords and their followers set out full
of ardor. When they had traversed Asia Minor, a fit of indif-
ference and weariness seized the chiefs of the crusaders. They
cared not to continue their route ; they united to make conquests
and establish themselves. The common people of the army re-
belled ; they wished to go to Jerusalem — the deliverance of Jeru-
salem was the aim of the crusade ; it was not to gain principal-
ities for Raimond de Toulouse, nor for Bohemond, nor for any
other, that the crusaders came. The popular, national and
European impulsion was superior to all individual wishes ; the
chiefs had not sufiicient ascendancy over the masses to subdue
them to their interests. The sovereigns, who had remained
strangers to the first crusade, were at last carried away by the
movement, like the people. The great crusades of the twelfth
century were commanded by kings.
I pass at once to the end of the thirteenth century. People
still spoke in Europe of the crusades, they even preached them
with ardor. The popes excited the sovereigns and the people
— they held councils in recommendation of the Holy Land ; but
no one went there — it was no longer cared for. Something
had passed into the European spirit and European society that
put an end to the crusades. There were still some private ex-
peditions. A few lords, a few bands, still set out for Jerusalem ;
but the general movement was evidently stopped ; and yet it
does not appear that either the necessity or the facility of con-
tinuing it had disappeared. The Moslems triumphed more and
more in Asia. The Christian kingdom founded at Jerusalem
had fallen into their hands. It v/as necessary to reconquer it ;
there were greater means of success than they had at the com-
126 GUIZOT
mencement of the crusades ; a large number of Christians were
established, and still powerful, in Asia Minor, Syria and Pales-
tine. They were better acquainted with the means of travelling
and acting. Still nothing could revive the crusades. It was
clear that the two great forces of society — the sovereigns on
one side and the people on the other — were averse to it.
It has often been said that this was lassitude — that Europe
was tired of thus falling upon Asia. We must come to an un-
derstanding upon this word lassitude, which is so often used
upon similar occasions ; it is strangely inexact. It is not pos-
sible that human generations can be weary with what they
have never taken part in ; weary of the fatigues undergone by
their forefathers. Weariness is personal, it cannot be trans-
mitted like a heritage. Men in the thirteenth century were not
fatigued by the crusades of the twelfth, they were influenced by
another cause. A great change had taken place in ideas, senti-
ments, and social conditions. There were no longer the same
wants and desires. They no longer thought or wished the same
things. It is these political or moral metamorphoses, and not
weariness, which explain the different conduct of successive
generations. The pretended lassitude which is attributed to
them is a false metaphor.
Two great causes, one moral and the other social, threw
Europe into the crusades. The moral cause, as you know, was
the impulsion of religious sentiments and creeds. Since the end
of the seventh century, Christianity had been struggling against
Mahommedanism ; it had conquered it in Europe after being
dangerously menaced ; it had succeeded in confining it to Spain.
Thence also it still constantly strove to expel it. The crusades
have been represented as a kind of accident, as an event unfore-
seen, unheard of, born solely of the recitals of pilgrims on their
return from Jerusalem, and of the preaching of Peter the Hermit.
It was nothing of the kind. The crusades were the continua-
tion, the zenith of the grand struggle which had been going on
for four centuries between Christianity and Mahommedanism.
The theatre of this struggle had been hitherto in Europe ; it
was now transported into Asia. If I put any value upon those
comparisons and parallels, into which some people delight at
times to press, suitable or not, historical facts, I might show you
Christianity running precisely the same career in Asia, and
undergoing the same destiny as Mahommedanism in Europe.
Mahommedanism was established in Spain, and had there con-
quered and founded a kingdom and principalities. The Giris-
tians did the same in Asia. They there found themselves with
regard to Mahommedans in the same situation as the latter in
Spain with regard to the Christians. The kingdom of Jerusa-
lem and the kingdom of Grenada correspond to each other.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 127
But these similitudes are of little importance. The great fact
is the struggle of the two social and religious systems ; and of
this the crusades was the chief crisis. In that lies their historical
character, the connecting link which attaches them to the total-
ity of facts.
There was another cause, the social state of Europe in the
eleventh century, which no less contributed to their outburst.
I have been careful to explain why, between the fifth and the
eleventh century, nothing general could be established in
Europe. I have attempted to show how every thing had be-
come local, how states, existences, minds, were confined within
a very limited horizon. It was thus feudalism had prevailed.
After some time an horizon so restricted did not suffice ; human
thought and activity desired to pass beyond the circle in which
they had been confined. The wandering life had ceased, but not
the inclination for its excitement and adventures. The people
rushed into the crusades as into a new existence, more enlarged
and varied, which at one time recalled the ancient liberty of
barbarism as others opened out the perspective of a vast future.
Such, I believe, were the two determining causes of the cru-
sades of the twelfth century. At the end of the thirteenth cent-
ury neither of these causes existed. Men and society were so
much changed that neither the moral impulsion nor the social
need which had precipitated Europe upon Asia was any longer
felt. I do not know if many of you have read the original
historians of the crusades, or whether it has ever occurred to
you to compare the contemporaneous chroniclers of the first
crusades with those at the end of the twelfth and thirteenth cent-
uries, for example, Albert d'Aix, Robert the Monk and Ray-
mond d'Agiles, who took part in the first crusade, with William
of Tyre and James de Vitry. When we compare these two
classes of writers, it is impossible not to be struck by the distance
which separates them. The first are animated chroniclers, full
of vivid imagination, who recount the events of the crusades
with passion. But they are, at the same time, men of very nar-
row minds, without an idea beyond the little sphere in which
they have lived ; strangers to all science, full of prejudices, and
incapable of forming any judgment whatever upon what passes
around them, or upon the events which they relate. Open,
on the contrary, the history of the crusades by William of Tyre :
you will be surprised to find almost an historian of modern
times, a mind developed, extensive and free, a rare political
understanding of events, completeness of views, a judgment
bearing upon causes and effects. James de Vitry affords an
example of a different kind of development; he is a scholar,
who not only concerns himself with what has reference to the
crusades, but also occupies himself with manners, geography,
128 GUIZOT
ethnography, natural history; who observes and describes the
country. In a word, between the chroniclers of the first cru-
sades and the historians of the last, there is an immense interval,
which indicates a veritable revolution in mind.
This revolution is above all seen in the manner in which each
speaks of the Mahommedans. To the first chroniclers, and con-
sequently to the first crusaders, of whom the first chroniclers are
but the expression, the Mahommedans are only an object of
hatred. It is evident that they knew nothing of them, that they
weighed them not, considered them not, except under the point
of view of the religious hostility which existed between them ;
we discover no trace of any social relation ; they detested and
fought them, and that was all. William of Tyre, James de
Vitry, and Bernard the Treasurer, speak quite differently of the
Mussulmans: one feels that, although fighting them, they do
not look upon them as mere monsters ; that to a certain point
they have entered into their ideas; that they have lived with
them, that there is a sort of relation, and even a kind of sym-
pathy established between them, William of Tyre warmly eulo-
gizes Noureddin — Bernard the Treasurer, Saladin. They even
go far as to compare the manners and conduct of the Mussul-
mans with those of the Christians ; they take advantage of the
Mussulmans to satirize the Christians, as Tacitus painted the
manners of the Germans in contrast with the manners of the
Romans. You see how enormous the change between the two
epochs must have been, when you find in the last, with regard
to the enemies of the Christians, to those against whom the cru-
sades were directed, a liberty and impartiality of spirit which
would have filled the first crusaders with surprise and indigna-
tion.
This, then, was the first and principal effect of the crusades,
a great step toward the enfranchisement of mind, a great prog-
ress toward more extensive and liberal ideas. Commenced in
the name and under the influence of religious creeds, the cru-
sades removed from religious ideas, I will not say their legiti-
mate influence, but the exclusive and despotic possession of
the human mind. This result, doubtless altogether unforeseen,
was born of many causes. The first is evidently the novelty,
extension and variety of the spectacle which was opened to the
view of the crusaders. It happened with them as with travel-
lers. It is a common saying that the mind of travellers becomes
enlarged ; that the habit of observing various nations and man-
ners, and different opinions, extends the ideas, and frees the
judgment from old prejudices. The same fact was accom-
plished among these travelling nations who were caller cru-
saders: their minds were opened and elevated, by seeing a
multitude of different things, and by observing other manners
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 129
than their own. They also found themselves in juxtaposition
with two civilizations, not only different from their own, but
more advanced ; the Greek on the one hand, and the Mahom-
medan on the other. There can be no doubt that the Greek
society, although enervated, perverted, and falling into decay,
had upon the crusaders the effect of a more advanced, polished
and enlightened society than their own. The Mahommedan
society afforded them a spectacle of the same nature. It is
curious to observe in the old chroniclers the impression which
the crusaders made upon the Mussulmans; these latter re-
garded them at first as barbarians, as the rudest, most ferocious
and most stupid class of men they had ever seen. The cru-
saders, on their part, were struck with the riches and elegance
of manners of the Mussulmans. To this first impression suc-
ceeded frequent relations between the two people. These ex-
tended and became much more important than is generally
supposed. Not only had the Christians of the east habitual
relations with the Mussulmans, but the west and the east be-
came acquainted, visited and mixed with each other. It is not
long since that one of those scholars who honor France in
the eyes of Europe, M. Abel Remusat, discovered the existence
of relations between the Mongol emperors and the Christian
kings. Mongol ambassadors were sent to the Frank kings,
to Saint Louis among others, to treat for an alliance with them,
and to recommence the crusades in the common interest of the
Mongols and the Christians against the Turks. And not only
were diplomatic and official relations thus established between
the sovereigns ; frequent and various national relations were
formed. I quote the words of M. Abel Remusat.*
" Many Itahan, French and Flemish monks were charged
with diplomatic missions to the Great Khan. Mongols of
distinction came to Rome, Barcelona, Valentia, Lyons, Paris,
London, Northampton ; and a Franciscan of the kingdom of
Naples was archbishop of Pekin. His successor was a pro-
fessor of theology of the faculty of Paris. But how many
others, less known, were drawn after these, either as slaves or
attracted by the desire for gain, or guided by curiosity into
countries till then unknown ! Chance has preserved the names
of some: the first who came to visit the King of Hungary,
on the part of the Tartars, was an Englishman, banished from
his country for certain crimes, and who, after wandering all
over Asia, ended by taking service among the Mongols. A
Flemish shoemaker met in the depths of Tartary a woman
from Metz, named Paquette, who had been carried off from
*M/moires sur les Relations Politiques des Princes Chretiens avec les
Empereurs Mongols. Deuxieme Memoire, pp. 154-157.
9
I30
GUIZOT
Hungary; a Parisian goldsmith, whose brother was estab-
lished at Paris, upon the great bridge, and a young man from
the environs of Rouen, who had been at the taking of Bel-
grade. He saw, also, Russians, Hungarians and Flemings.
A chorister, named Robert, after having traveled over Eastern
Asia, returned to finish his days in the cathedral of Chartres.
A Tartar was purveyor of helmets in the army of Philip the
Handsome ; John de Plancarpin found near Gayouk a Russian
gentleman, whom he calls Temer, who was serving as an in-
terpreter; many merchants of Breslau, Poland and Austria
accompanied him on his journed to Tartary. Others returned
with him by way of Russia ; these were Genoese, Pisans and
Venetians. Two merchants, whom chance had led to Bok-
hara, consented to follow a Mongol ambassador sent by Koul-
agou to Khoubilai. They sojourned several years both in
China and Tartary, returned with letters from the Great Khan
to the Pope ; again returned to the Great Khan, taking with
them the son of one of them, the celebrated Marco Polo, and
again quitted the court of Khoubilai to return to Venice.
Travels of this kind were not less frequent in the following
century. Among the number are those of Sir John Mande-
ville, an English physician, of Oderic of Friula, of Pegoletti,
of William de Bouldeselle, and several others, and we may
suppose that those whose memorials are preserved, form but
the least part of what were undertaken, and that there were
at this period more persons capable of executing long journeys
than of writing an account of them. Many of these adventur-
ers remained and died in the countries which they visited.
Others returned to their country as obscure as when they left
it, but with an imagination filled with what they had seen,
relating it to their family, exaggerating, no doubt, but leav-
ing around them, amid absurd fables, useful remembrances
and traditions capable of bearing fruit. Thus in Germany,
Italy and France, in the monasteries, in the castles of the lords,
and even down to the lowest ranks of society, were deposited
precious seeds destined before long to germinate. All these
unknown travellers carried the arts of their native land into the
most distant countries, brought back other knowledge no less
precious, and thus made, without being aware of it, more ad-
vantageous exchanges than all those of commerce. By these
means not only the trade in silk, porcelain and Indian com-
modities was extended and facilitated — new routes opened to
commercial industry and activity — but, what was of much more
importance, foreign manners, unknown nations, extraordinary
productions, oflfered themselves in crowds to the minds of the
Europeans, confined, since the fall of the Roman Empire, with-
in too narrow a circle. They began to know the value of the
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE
131
most beautiful, the most populous, and the most anciently
civilized of the four (quarters of the globe. They began to
study the arts, creeds, and idioms of its inhabitants, and there
was even talk of establishing a professorship of the Tartar lan-
guage in the University of Paris. Romantic narrative, v^hen
duly discussed and investigated, spread on all sides more just
and varied notions. The world seemed to open on the side
of the east ; geography took a great stride, and the desire for
discovery became the new form which clothed the adventurous
spirit of the Europeans. The idea of another hemisphere ceased
to present itself as a paradox void of all probability, when our
own became better known; and it was in searching for the
Zipangi of Marco Polo that Christopher Columbus discovered
the New World."
You see, by the facts which led to the impulsion of the
crusades, what, at the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, was
the new and vast world which was thrown open to the Euro-
pean mind. There can be no doubt but that this was one of
the most powerful causes of development, and of the freedom
of mind which shone forth at the end of this great event.
There is another cause which merits observation. Down
to the time of the crusades, the court of Rome, the centre
of the church, had never been in communication with the laity,
except through the medium of ecclesiastics, whether legates
sent from the court of Rome, or the bishops and the entire
clergy. There had always been some laymen in direct relation
with Rome ; but, taken all together, it was through the eccle-
siastics that she communicated with the people. During the
crusades, on the contrary, Rome became a place of passage to
the greater part of the crusaders, both in going and in return-
ing. Numbers of the laity viewed her policy and manners,
and could see how much of personal interest influenced relig-
ious controversy. Doubtless this new knowledge inspired
many minds with a hardihood till then unknown.
When we consider the state of minds in general, at the end
of the crusades, and particularly in ecclesiastical matters, it is
impossible not to be struck by one singular fact: religious
ideas experienced no change ; they had not" been replaced by
contrary or even different opinions. Yet minds were infinitely
more free ; religious creeds were no longer the only sphere in
which it was brought into play ; without abandoning them, it
began to separate itself from them, and carry itself elsewhere.
Thus, at the end of the thirteenth century, the moral cause
which had determined the crusades, which at least was its most
energetic principle, had vanished ; the moral state of Europe
was profoundly modified.
The social state had undergone an analogous change. Much
132
GUIZOT
investigation has been expended upon what was the influence
of the crusades in this respect ; it has been shown how they
reduced a large number of fief holders to the necessity of sell-
ing them to their sovereigns, or of selling charters to the bor-
oughs in order to procure the means of following the crusade.
It has been shown that by their mere absence many of the lords
must have lost the greater portion of their power. Without
entering into the details of this inquiry, we may, I think, resolve
into a few general facts the influence of the crusades upon the
social state.
They greatly diminished the number of petty fiefs and small
domains, of inferior fief-holders ; and they concentred property
and power in a smaller number of hands. It is with the com-
mencement of the crusades that we see the formation and aug-
mentation of large fiefs and great feudal existences.
I have often regretted that there is no map of France divided
into fiefs, as there is of its division into departments, arrondisse-
ments, cantons and parishes, in which all the fiefs should be
marked, with their extent and successive relations and changes.
If we were to compare, with the aid of such a map, the state of
France before and after the crusades, we should see how many
fiefs had vanished, and to what a degree the great and middle
fiefs had increased. This was one of the most important facts
to which the crusades led.
Even where the petty proprietors preserved their fiefs, they
no longer lived as isolated as formerly. The great fief-holders
became so many centres around which the smaller ones con-
verged, and near to which they passed their lives. It had be-
come necessary during the crusades for them to put them-
selves in the train of the richest and most powerful, to receive
succor from him ; they had lived with him, partaken of his
fortune, gone through the same adventures. When the cru-
saders returned home, this sociability, this habit of living near
to the superior lord, remained fixed in their manners. Thus
as we see the augmentation of the great fiefs after the crusades,
so we see the holders of those fiefs holding a much more con-
siderable court in the interior of their castles, having near them
a larger number of gentlemen who still preserved their small
domains, but did not shut themselves up within them.
The extension of the great fiefs and the creation of a certain
number of centres of society, in place of the dispersion which
formerly existed, are the two principal effects brought about
by the crusades in the heart of feudalism.
As to the burghers, a result of the same nature is easily per-
ceptible. The crusades created the great boroughs. Petty
commerce and industry did not suffice to create boroughs such
as the great towns of Italy and Flanders were. It was com-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 133
merce on a great scale, maritime commerce, and especially
that of the east, which gave rise to them ; it was the crusades
which gave to maritime commerce the most powerful impul-
sion it had ever received.
Upon the whole, when we regard the state of society at the
end of the crusades, we find that this movement of dissolution,
of the dispersion of existences and influences, this movement
of universal localization, if such a phrase be permitted, which
had preceded this epoch, had ceased, by a movement with an
exactly contrary tendency, by a movement of centralization.
All now tended to approximation. The lesser existences were
either absorbed in the greater, or were grouped around them.
It was in this direction that society advanced, that all its prog-
ress was made.
You now see why, toward the end of the thirteenth and
fourteenth centuries, neither people nor sovereigns any longer
desired the crusades ; they had no longer either the need or
desire for them ; they had been cast into them by the impul-
sion of the religious spirit, and by the exclusive domination
of religious ideas upon the whole existence; this domination
had lost its energy. They had sought, too, in the crusades a
new life, more extensive and more varied; they now began to
find it in Europe itself, in the progress of social relations. It
was at this epoch the career of political aggrandizement opened
itself to kings. Wherefore seek kingdoms in Asia, when they
had them to conquer at their own doors ? Philip Augustus went
to the crusades against his will : what could be more natural ?
He had to make himself king of France. It was the same with
the people. The career of riches opened before their eyes;
they renounced adventures for work. For the sovereigns, the
place of adventures was supplied by policy ; for the people, by
work on a great scale. one single class of society still had a
taste for adventure; this was that portion of feudal nobility
who, not being in a condition to think of political aggrandize-
ment, and not liking work, preserved their ancient condition
and manners. They therefore continued to rush to the cru-
sades, and attempted their revival.
Such, in my opinion, are the great and true effects of the
crusades : on one side, the extension of ideas, the enfranchise-
ment of mind ; on the other, the aggrandizement of existences
and a large sphere opened to activity of all kind ; they produced
at once a greater degree of individual liberty, and of political
unity. They aided the independence of man and the centrali-
zation of society. Much has been asked as to the means of
civilization — which they directly imported from the east; it
has been said that the chief portion of the great discoveries
which, in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, called forth the
X34 GUIZOT
development of European civilization — the compass, printing,
gunpowder — were known in the east, and that the crusaders
may have brought them thence. This, to a certain point, is
true. But some of these assertions are disputable. That which
is not disputable is this influence, this general effect of the cru-
sades upon the mind on one hand, and upon society on the
other hand ; they drew European society from a very straight-
ened tract, and led it into new and infinitely more extensive
paths; they commenced that transformation of the various
elements of European society into governments and peoples
which is the character of modern civilization. About the same
time, royalty, one of those institutions which have most power-
fully contributed to this great result, developed itself. Its his-
tory, from the birth of modern states down to the thirteenth
century, will form the subject of my next lecture.
NINTH LECTURE.
IN our last lecture I attempted to determine the essential
and distinctive character of modern European society as
compared with primitive European society ; I believe that
we discovered in this fact that all the elements of the social state,
at first numerous and various, reduce themselves to two : on
one hand the government, and on the other the people. Instead
of encountering the feudal nobility, the clergy, the kings, the
burghers, and serfs as the dominant powers and chief actors
in history, we find in modern Europe but two great figures which
alone occupy the historic scene, the government, and the coun-
try.
If such is the fact in which European civilization terminates,
such also is the end to which we should tend, and to which our
researches should conduct us. It is necessary that we should
see this grand result take birth, and progressively develop and
strengthen itself. We are entered upon the epoch in which
we may arrive at its origin : it was, as you have seen, between
the twelfth and the sixteenth century that the slow and con-
cealed work operated in Europe which has led our society to this
new form and definite state. We have likewise studied the first
great event, which, in my opinion, evidently and powerfully im-
pelled Europe, in this direction, that is, the crusades.
About the same epoch, almost at the moment that the crusades
broke out, that institution commenced its aggrandizement,
which has, perhaps, contributed more than anything to the for-
mation of modern society, and to that fusion of all the social ele-
ments into two powers, the government and the people — roy-
alty.
It is evident that royalty has played a prodigious part in the
history of European civilization ; a single glance at facts suffices
to convince one of it ; we see the development of royalty march-
ing with the same step, so to speak, at least for a long period, as
that of society itself ; the progress is mutual.
And not only is the progress mutual, but whenever society ad-
vances toward its modern and definitive character, royalty seems
to extend and prosper ; so that when the work is consummated,
when there is no longer any, or scarcely any, other important or
135
136 GUIZOT
(decisive influence in the great states of Europe, than that of the
government and the public, royalty is the government
And it has thus happened, not only in France, where the fact
is evident, but also in the greater portion of European countries ;
a little earlier or a little later, under somewhat different forms,
the same result is offered us in the history of society in England,
Spain, and Germany. In England, for example, it was under
the Tudors that the ancient, peculiar, and local elements of Eng-
lish society were perverted and dissolved, and gave place to the
system of public powers ; this also was the time of the greatest
influence of royalty. It was the same in Germany, Spain and
all the great European states.
If we leave Europe, and if we turn our view upon the rest of
the world, we shall be struck by an analogous fact ; we shall
everywhere find royalty occupying an important position, ap-
pearing as, perhaps, the most general and permanent of institu-
tions, the most difficult to prevent, where it did not formerly
exist, and the most difficult to root out where it had existed.
From time immemorial it has possessed Asia. At the discovery
of America, all the great states there were found with different
combinations, subject to the monarchical system. When we
penetrate into the interior of Africa, wherever we meet with na-
tions in any way extensive, this is the prevailing system. And
not only has royalty penetrated everywhere, but it has accom-
modated itself to the most diverse situations, to civilization, and
to barbarism, to manners the most pacific, as in China, for ex-
ample, and to those in which war, in which the military spirit
dominates. It has alike established itself in the heart of the
system of castes ; in the most rigorously classified societies, and
in the midst of a system of equality, in societies which are utter
strangers to all legal and permanent classification. Here
despotic and oppressive, there favorable to civilization and even
to liberty, it seems like a head which may be placed upon a mul-
titude of different bodies, a fruit that will spring from the most
dissimilar germs.
In this fact we may discover many curious and important con-
sequences. I will take only two. The first is, that it is impos-
sible such a result should be the fruit of mere chance, of force or
usurpation alone ; it is impossible but that there should be a
profound and powerful analogy between the nature of royalty,
considered as an institution, and the nature, whether of indi-
vidual man, or of human society. Doubtless force is intermixed
with the origin of the institution ; doubtless force has taken an
important part in its progress ; but when we meet with such a
result as this, when we see a great event developing and repro-
ducing itself during the course of many centuries, and in the
midst of such different situations, we cannot attribute it to force.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 137
Force plays a great part and an incessant one in human affairs ;
but it is not their principle, their primum mobile ; above force
and the part which it plays there hovers a moral cause which de-
cides the totality of things. It is with force in the history of
societies as with the body in the history of man. The body
surely holds a high place in the life of man, but still it is not the
principle of life. Life circulates within it, but it does not
emanate from it. So it is with human societies ; whatever part
force takes therein, it is not force which governs them, and which
presides supremely over their destinies ; it is ideas and moral
influences, which conceal themselves under the accidents of force
and regulate the course of the society. It is a cause of this kind,
and not force, which gave success to royalty.
A second fact, and one which is no less worthy of remark, is
the flexibility of the institution, its faculty of modifying and
adapting itself to a multitude of different circumstances. Mark
the contrast : its form is unique, permanent, and simple ; it
does not offer that prodigious variety of combinations which we
see in other institutions, and yet it applies itself to societies which
the least resemble it. It must evidently allow of great diversity,
and must attach itself, whether in man himself or in society, to
many different elements and principles.
It is from not having considered the institution of royalty in
its whole extent ; from not having, on the one hand, penetrated to
its peculiar and fixed principle, which, whatever may be the cir-
cumstances to which it applies itself, is its very essence and being
— and, on the other, from not having estimated all the varieties
to which it lends itself, and all the principles with which it may
enter into alliance ; it is, I say, from not having considered roy-
alty under this vast and two- fold point of view, that the part
taken by it in the history of the world has not been always com-
prehended, that its nature and effects have often been mis-
construed.
This is the work which I wish to go through with you, and in
such a manner as to take an exact and complete estimate of the
effects of this institution in modern Europe, whether they have
flowed from its own peculiar principles or the modifications
which it has undergone.
There can be no doubt that the force of royalty, that moral
power which is its true principle, does not reside in the sole and
personal will of the man momentarily king ; there can be no
doubt that the people, in accepting it as an institution, philoso-
phers in maintaining it as a system, have not intended or con-
sented to accept the empire of the will of a man essentially nar-
row, arbitrary, capricious, and ignorant.
Royalty is quite a distinct thing from the will of a man, al-
though it presents itself in that form ; it is the personification of
138 GUIZOT
the sovereignty of right, of that will, essentially reasonable, en-
lightened, just and impartial, foreign and superior to all indi-
vidual wills, and which in virtue of this title has a right to govern
them. Such is the meaning of royalty in the minds of nations,
such the motive for their adhesion.
Is it true that there is a sovereignty of right, a will which pos-
sesses the right of governing men? It is quite certain that they
believe so; because they seek, and constantly have sought,
and indeed cannot but seek, to place themselves under its empire.
Conceive to yourselves the smallest assembly of men, I will not
say a people : conceive that assembly under the submission to a
sovereign who is only so de facto, under a force which has no
right except that of force, which governs neither according to
reason, justice, nor truth ; human nature revolts at such a sup-
position — it must have right to believe in. It is the supremacy
of right which it seeks, that is the only power to which man con-
sents to submit. What is history but the demonstration of this
universal fact? What are the greater portion of the struggles
which take place in the life of nations but an ardent effort toward
the sovereignty of right, so that they may place themselves un-
der its empire? And not only nations, but philosophers believe
in its existence, and incessantly seek it. What are all the sys-
tems of political philosophy, but the search for the sovereign of
right? What is it that they treat of, but the question of know-
ing who has a right to govern society ? Take the theocratical,
monarchical, aristocratical, or democratical systems, all of them
boast of having discovered wherein the sovereignty of right re-
sides; all promise to society that they will place it under the rule
of its legitimate master. I repeat, this is the end alike of all the
works of philosophers, of all efforts of nations.
How should they but believe in the sovereignty of right ? How
should they but be constantly in search of it? Take the most
simple suppositions ; let there be something to accomplish,
some influence to exercise, whether upon society in its whole, or
upon a number of its members, or upon a single individual ;
there is evidently always a rule for this action, a legitimate will
to follow and apply. Whether you penetrate into the smallest
details of social life, or whether you elevate yourselves to the
greatest events, you will everywhere encounter a truth to be
proved, or a just and reasonable idea to be passed into reality.
This is the sovereign of right, toward which philosophers and
nations have never ceased and never can cease to aspire.
Up to what point can the sovereignty of right be represented
in a general and permanent manner by a terrestial force or by a
human will? How far is such a supposition necessarily false
and dangerous ? What should be thought in particular of the
personification of the sovereignty of right under the image of
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 139
royalty? Upon what conditions, within what limits is this per-
sonification admissible? Great questions, which I have not to
treat of here, but which I could not resist pointing out, and upon
which I shall say a word in passing.
I affirm, and the merest common sense will acknowledge, that
the sovereignty of right completely and permanently can apper-
tain to no one ; that all attribution of the sovereignty of right
to any human power whatsoever is radically false and dangerous.
Hence arises the necessity for the limitation of all powers, what-
ever their names or forms may be ; hence the radical illegiti-
macy of all absolute power, whether its origin be from conquest,
inheritance, or election. People may differ as to the best means
of seeking the sovereign of right ; they may vary as to place and
times ; but in no place, no time, can any legitimate power be
the independent possessor of this sovereignty.
This principle being laid down, it is no less certain that roy-
alty, in whatever system it is considered, presents itself as the
personification of the sovereign of right. Listen to the theocrat-
ical system : it will tell you that kings are the image of God
upon earth ; this is only saying that they are the personification
of sovereign justice, truth, and goodness. Address yourself to
the jurisconsults ; they will tell you that the king is the living
law ; that is to say, the king is the personification of the sover-
eign of right, of the just law, which has the right of governing
society. Ask royalty itself, in the system of pure monarchy ; it
will tell you that it is the personification of the state, of the gen-
eral interest. In whatever alliance and in whatever situation
you consider it, you will always find it summing itself up in the
pretension of representing and reproducing the sovereign of
right, alone capable of legitimately governing society.
There is no occasion for astonishment in all this. What are
the characteristics of the sovereign of right, the characteristics
derivable from his very nature? In the first place he is unique ;
since there is but one truth, one justice, there can be but one
sovereign of right. He is permanent, always the same ; truth
never changes. He is placed in a superior situation, a stranger
to all the vicissitudes and changes of this world ; his part in the
world is, as it were, that of a spectator and judge. Well, is it
royalty which externally reproduces, under the most simple
form, that which appears its most faithful image, these rational
and natural characteristics of the sovereign of right. Open the
work in which M. Benjamin Constant has so ingeniously repre-
sented royalty as a neutral and moderating power, raised above
the accidents and struggles of social life, and only interfering at
great crises. Is not this, so to speak, the attitude of the sover-
eign of right in the government of human things ? There must
be something in this idea well calculated to impress the mind,
I40 GUIZOT
for it has passed with singular rapidity from books to facts. one
sovereign made it in the constitution of Brazil the very founda-
tion of his throne ; there royalty is represented as a moderating
power, raised above all active powers, as a spectator and judge.
Under whatever point of view you regard this institution as
compared with the sovereign of right, you will find that there is
a great external resemblance, and that it is natural for it to have
struck the minds of men. Accordingly, whenever their reflec-
tion or imagination turned with preference toward the contem-
plation or study of the nature of the sovereign of right, and his
essential characteristics, they have inclined toward royalty. As
in the time of the preponderance of religious ideas, the habitual
contemplation of the nature of God led mankind toward the
monarchical system, so when the jurisconsults dominated in so-
ciety, the habit of studying, under the name of the law, the nature
of the sovereign of right, was favorable to the dogma of his per-
sonification in royalty. The attentive application of the human
mind to the contemplation of the nature of the sovereignty of
right when no other causes have interfered to destroy the effect,
has always given force and credit to royalty, which presents its
image.
Moreover, there are times peculiarly favorable to this personi-
fication. These are the times when individual powers display
themselves in the world with all their risks and caprices ; times
when egotism dominates in individuals, whether from ignorance
and brutality, or from corruption. Then society, abandoned to
the contests of personal wills, and unable to raise itself by their
free concurrence to a common and universal will, passionately
long for a sovereign to whom all individuals may be forced to
submit ; and the moment any institution, bearing any one of the
characteristics of the sovereignty of right, presented itself and
promised its empire to society, society rallied round it with
eager earnestness, like outlaws, taking refuge in the asylum of a
church. This is what has been seen in the disorderly youth of
nations, such as we have surveyed. Royalty is admirably
adapted to epochs, of vigorous and fruitful anarchy, so to speak,
when society desires to form and regulate itself, without know-
ing how to do so by the free concord of individual wills. There
are other times when, from directly opposite causes, it has the
same recommendation. Why did the Roman Empire, so nearly
in a state of dissolution at the end of the republic, subsist for
nearly fifteen centuries afterward, under the name of that empire
which, after all, was but a continual decay, a lengthened agony?
Royalty alone could produce such an effect ; that alone could
hold together a society which selfishness incessantly tended to
destroy. The imperial power struggled for fifteen centuries
against the ruin of the Roman world.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 141
Thus there are times when royalty alone can retard the disso-
lution of society, and times when it alone accelerates its forma-
tion. And in both these cases it is because it represents more
clearly and powerfully than any other form the sovereignty of
right, that it exercises this power upon events.
From whatever point of view you may consider this institu-
tion, and at whatever epoch, you will acknowledge then that its
essential characteristic, its moral principle, its true and inmost
meaning is the image, the personification, the presumed inter-
preter of this unique, superior and essentially legitimate will,
which alone has the right of governing society.
Let us now regard royalty from the second point of view, that
is to say, in its flexibility, in the variety of parts which it has
played, and the effects which it has produced; it is necessary
that we should give the reason of these features and determine
their causes.
Here we have an advantage; we can immediately enter upon
history, and upon our own history. By a concourse of singular
circumstances it has happened that in modern Europe royalty
has assumed every character under which it has shown itself in
the history of the world. If I may be allowed to use an arithmet-
ical expression, European royalty is the sum total of all possible
species of royalty. I will run over its history from the fifth to
the twelfth century; you will see how various are the aspects
under which it presents itself, and to what an extent we shall
everywhere find this character of variety, complication and con-
flict which belongs to all European civilization.
In the fifth century, at the time of the great German invasion,
two royalties are present; the barbarian and the imperial royalty,
that of Clovis and that of Constantine, both differing essentially
in principles and effects. Barbaric royalty is essentially elective;
the German kings were elected, although their election did not
take place with the same forms which we are accustomed to
attach to the idea; they were military chiefs, who were bound to
make their power freely acceptable to a large number of com-
panions, who obeyed them as being the most brave and the most
able among them. Election is the true source of barbaric
royalty, its primitive and essential characteristic.
Not that this characteristic in the fifth century was not already
a little modified, or that different elements had not been intro-
duced into royalty. The various tribes had had their chiefs for
a certain time; some families had raised themselves to more
trust, consideration and riches than others. Hence a com-
mencement of inheritance; the chief was now mostly elected out
of these families. This was the first differing principle which
became associated with the dominant principle of election.
Another idea, another element, had also already penetrated
142
GUIZOT
into barbaric royalty: this was the religious element. We find
among some of the barbarous nations, among the Goths, for
example, that the families of their kings descended from the
families of their gods, or from those heroes of whom they had
made gods, such as Odin. This is the situation of the kings of
Homer, who sprang from gods or demi-gods, and by reason of
this title were the objects of a kind of religious veneration,
despite their limited power.
Such, in the fifth century, was barbaric royalty, already vary-
ing and fluctuating, although its primitive principle still
dominated.
I take imperial, Roman royalty; this is a totally different
thing; it is the personification of the state, the heir of the sov-
ereignty and majesty of the Roman people. Consider the
royalty of Augustus and Tiberius; the emperor is the repre-
sentative of the senate, the comitia, and the whole republic ; he
succeeded them, and they are summed up in his person. Who
would not recognize this in the modesty of language of the first
emperors; of those, at least, who were men of sense, and under-
stood their situation? They felt themselves in the presence of
the late sovereign people who had abdicated in their favor; they
addressed them as their representatives and ministers. But, in
fact, they exercised the whole power of the people, and that with
the most formidable intensity. It is easy for us to understand
such a transformation ; we have ourselves witnessed it ; we have
seen the sovereignty pass from the people to a man; that is
the history of Napoleon. He also was the personification of
the sovereign people; he unceasingly repeated to it, " Who like
me has been elected by eighteen millions of men? Who like me
is the representative of the people Reptiblique Frangaise?"
And when upon one side of his coinage we read, The French
Republic, and upon the other. Napoleon, Empereur, what does
this mean, if not the fact which I have described, the people
become king?
Such was the fundamental character of imperial royalty, which
it preserved for the three first centuries of the empire; it was
not till Diocletian that it took its definite and complete form.
It was then, however, upon the point of undergoing a g^eat
change; a new royalty had almost appeared. Christianity
labored for three centuries to introduce the religious element into
society. It was under Constantine that it met with success, not
in making it the prevalent fact, but in making it play an impor-
tant part. Here royalty presents itself under a different aspect ;
its origin is not earthly; the prince is not the representative of
the public sovereignty; he is the image of God, his representa-
tive and delegate. Power came down to him from above, while
in imperial royalty it came from below. These are two utterly
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 143
different situations, and have entirely different results. The
rights of liberty, political guarantees, are difficult to combine
with the principle of religious royalty; but the principle itself
is elevated, moral and salutary. Let us see the idea which was
formed of the prince in the seventh century in the system of
religious royalty. I take it from the canons of the councils of
Toledo.
"The king is called king (r^jir) because he governs justly
(recte). If he act with justice (recte) he legitimately pos-
sesses the name of king; if he act with injustice he miserably
loses it. Our fathers, therefore, said with good reason: Rex
ejus, eris si recta facis, si autem non facis, non eris. The two
principal royal virtues are justice and truth (science of the
reason).
" The royal power is bound, like the people, to respect the
laws . . . Obedience to the will of Heaven, gives to us and
to our subjects wise laws which our greatness and that of our
successors is bound to obey, as well as the whole population of
our kingdom. . . .
" God, the creator of all things, in disposing the structure of
the human body, has raised the head on high and has willed that
the nerves of all the members should proceed therefrom. And
he has placed in the head the torch of the eyes, to the end that
from thence may be viewed all things that might be prejudicial.
He has established the power of intellect, charging it to govern
all the members and wisely to regulate their action. ... It
is first necessary, then, to regulate what relates to princes, to
watch over their safety, and to protect their life, and then to
order what relates to the people; so that in guaranteeing, as is
fitting, the safety of kings, they at the same time guarantee, and
more effectually, that of the people."*
But, in the system of religious royalty, another element, quite
different from that of royalty itself, almost always introduced
itself. A new power took its place by the side of it, a power
nearer to God, to the source whence royalty emanates, than
royalty itself: this was the clergy, the ecclesiastical power which
interposed itself between God and kings and between kings and
the people; so that royalty, the image of divinity, ran a chance
of falling to the rank of an instrument of the human interpreters
of the divine will. This was a new cause of diversity in tHe
destinies and effects of the institution.
Here, then, we see, what in the fifth century were the various
royalties which manifested themselves upon the ruins of the
Roman Empire; the barbaric royalty, the imperial royalty and
the rising religious royalty. Their fortunes were as various as
their principles.
* Forum Judicum, i. lib. 2; tit. i. 1. 2, I.4..
144 GUIZOT
In France, under the first race, barbaric royalty prevailed;
there were many attempts of the clergy to impress upon it the
imperial or religious character; but election in the royal family,
with some mixture of inheritance and religious ideas, remained
dominant. In Italy, among the Ostrogoths, imperial royalty
superseded the barbarian customs. Theodoric asserted himself
the successor of the emperors. You need only read Cassiodorus,
to acknowledge this character of his government.
In Spain, royalty appeared more religious than elsewhere;
as the councils of Toledo were, I will not say the masters, but the
influencing power, the religious character dominated, if not in
the government, properly so-called, of the Visigoth kings at
least, in the laws with which the clergy inspired them and the
language which it made them speak.
In England, among the Saxons, barbarian manners subsisted
almost entire. The kingdoms of the heptarchy were merely the
domains of various bands, having each its chief. The military
election is more evident there than elsewhere. Anglo-Saxon
royalty is the most perfect type of barbaric royalty.
Thus from the fifth to the twelfth century three kinds of
royalty manifested themselves at the same time in general facts;
one or other of them prevailed, according to circumstances, in
each of the different states of Europe.
The chaos was such at this epoch that nothing universal or
permanent could be established; and, from one vicissitude to
another, we arrive at the eighth century, without royalty having
anywhere taken a definitive character. Toward the middle of
the eighth century, with the triumph of the second race of the
Frank kings, events generalized themselves and became clearer;
as they were accomplished upon a greater scale they were better
understood and led to more results. You will shortly see the
different royalties distinctly succeed and combine with each
other.
At the time when the Carlovingjans replace the Merovingians,
a return of barbaric royalty is visible; election again appears.
Pepin causes himself to be elected at Soissons. When the first
Carlovingians give the kingdoms to their sons, they take care
to have them accepted by the chief persons in the states assigned
them; when they make a partition, they wish it to be sanctioned
in the national assemblies. In a word, the elective principle,
under the form of public acceptation, reassumes some reality.
You bear in mind that this change of dynasty was like a new
invasion of the Germans in the west of Europe and brought
back some shadow of their ancient institutions and manners.
At the same time we see the religious principle introduced
more clearly into royalty, and playing therein a more important
part. Pepin was acknowledged and crowned by the pope. He
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 145
had need of religious sanction ; it had already a great power, and
he courted it. Charlemagne took the same precaution ; religious
royalty was developing. Still under Charlemagne this character
did not dominate; imperial royalty was evidently what he
attempted to resuscitate. Although he closely allied himself to
the clergy, and made use of them, he was not their instrument.
The idea of a great state, of a great political unity, the resur-
rection of the Roman Empire, was the favorite idea, the dream
of Charlemagne's reign. He died, and was succeeded by Louis
le Debonnaire. Every one knows what character the royal
power instantly assumed; the king fell into the hands of the
clergy, who censured, deposed, re-estabHshed, and governed
him ; religious royalty, late subordinate, seemed on the point of
being established.
Thus, from the middle of the eighth to the middle of the
ninth century, the diversity of three kinds of royalty manifested
itself in important, closely connected, and palpable events.
After the death of Louis le Debonnaire, in the dissolution
into which Europe fell, the three species of royalty disappeared
almost simultaneously; all became confusion. After some time,
when the feudal system prevailed, a fourth royalty presented
itself, different from any that we have yet seen; this was feudal
royalty. This is confused, and very difficult to define. It has
been said that the king in the feudal system was sovereign of
sovereigns, lord of lords, that he held by sure ties, from one class
to another, the entire society; that in calling around him his
vassals, then the vassals of his vassals, he called the whole nation,
and truly showed himself a king. I do not deny that this was the
theory of feudal royalty; but it is a mere theory, which has never
governed facts. That general influence of the king by the means
of an hierarchial organization, those ties which united royalty
to the entire feudal society, are the dreams of publicists. In
fact, the greater part of the feudal lords were at this epoch
entirely independent of royalty; a large number scarcely knew
the name, and had little or no connection with it. All the
sovereignties were local and independent: the title of king
borne by one of the feudal lords expressed rather a remembrance
than a fact.
This was the state of royalty during the course of the tenth
and eleventh centuries. In the twelfth, with the reign of Louis
le Gros, the aspect of things began to change. We more often
find the king spoken of; his influence penetrated into places
where hitherto he had never made way; his part in society
became more active. If we seek by what title, we shall recognize
none of the titles of which royalty had hitherto been accustomed
to avail itself. It was not as the heir of the emperors, or by the
title of imperial royalty, that it aggrandized itself and assumed
146 GUIZOT
more coherence; nor was it in virtue of election, nor as the
emanation of divine power. All trace of election had disap-
peared, the hereditary principle of succession had become defin-
itively established ; and although religion sanctioned the acces-
sion of kings, the minds of men did not appear at all engrossed
with the religious character of the royalty of Louis le Gros. A
new element, a character hitherto unknown, produced itself in
royalty; a new royalty commenced.
I need not repeat that society was at this epoch in a prodigious
disorder, a prey to unceasing violence. Society had m itself no
means of striving against this deplorable state, of regaining any
regularity or unity. The feudal institutions, those parliaments
of barons, those seigneurial courts, all those forms under which
in modern times, feudalism has been represented as a systematic
and organized regime, all this was devoid of reality, of power;
there was nothing there which could re-establish order or justice ;
so that, amid this social desolation, none knew to whom to
have recourse for the reparation of any great injustice, or to
remedy any great evil, or in any way to constitute anything
resembling a state. The name of king remained; a lord bore it,
and some few addressed themselves to him. The various titles
under which royalty had hitherto presented itself, although they
did not exercise any great control, were still present to many
minds, and on some occasions were recognized. It sometimes
happened that they had recourse to the king to repress any
scandalous violence, or to re-establish something like order, in
any place near to his residence, or to terminate any difference
which had long existed; he was sometimes called upon to inter-
fere in matters not strictly within his jurisdiction ; he interfered
as the protector of public order, as arbitrator and redresser of
wrongs. The moral authority which remained attached to his
name by degrees attracted to him this power.
Such is the character which royalty begun to take under Louis
le Gros, and under the administration of Suger. Then, for the
first time, we see in the minds of men the idea, although very
incomplete, confused and weak, of a public power, foreign to
the powers which possessed society, called to render justice to
those who were unable to obtain it by ordinary means, capable
of establishing, or, at least, of commanding order; the idea of a
great magistrate, whose essential character was that of main-
taining or re-establishing peace, of protecting the weak, and of
ending differences which none others could decide. This is the
entirely new character under which, dating from the twelfth
century, royalty presented itself in Europe, and especially in
France. It was neither as a barbarous royalty, a religious
royalty, nor as an imperial royalty, that it exercised its empire;
it possessed only a limited, incomplete and accidental power;
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 147
the power, as it were (I know of no expression more exact),
of a great justice of peace for the whole nation.
This is the true origin of modern royalty; this, so to speak, is
its vital principle; that which has been developed in the course
of its career, and which, I do not hesitate in saying, has brought
about its success. At the different epochs of history, we see
the different characters of royalty reappear; we see the various
royalties which I have described attempting by turns to regain
the preponderance. Thus the clergy has always preached relig-
ious royalty; jurisconsults labored to resuscitate imperial
royalty; and the nobles have sometimes wished to revive elective
royalty, or the feudal. And not only have the clergy, juriscon-
sults and nobility striven to make dominant in royalty such or
such a character; it has itself made them all subservient to the
aggrandizement of its power; kings have sometimes represented
themselves as the delegates of God, sometimes as the successors
of the emperors, according to the need or inclination of the
moment; they have illegitimately availed themselves of these
various titles, but none of them has been the veritable title of
modern royalty, or the source of its preponderating influence.
It is, I repeat, as the depositary and protector of public order, of
universal justice and common interest — it is under the aspect
of great magistrac)^, the center and union of society — that it has
shown itself to the eyes of the people, and has appropriated
their strength by obtaining their adhesion.
You will see, as we advance; this characteristic of modern
European royalty, which commenced at the twelfth century,
under the reign of Louis le Gros, strengthen and develop itself,
and become, so to speak, its political physiognomy. It is
through it that royalty has contributed to the great result
which characterizes European societies in the present day,
namely, the reduction of all social elements into two, the govern-
ment and the country.
Thus, at the termination of the crusades, Europe entered the
path which was to conduct it to its present state; and royalty
took its appropriate part in the great transformation. In our
next lecture we shall study the different attempts made at polit-
ical organization, from the twelfth to the sixteenth century, with
a view to maintain, by regulating it, the order, then almost in
ruin. We shall consider the efforts of feudalism, of the church,
and even of the boroughs, to constitute society after its ancient
principles, and under its primitive forms, and thus defend them-
selves against the general metamorphosis which was in prepa-
ration.
TENTH LECTURE.
I WISH to determine correctly, and at the outset, the object
of this lecture.
You will recollect that one of the first facts which struck
us in the elements of ancient European society, was their diver-
sity, separation, and independence. The feudal nobility, clergy
and boroughs had a situation, laws and manners, all entirely
different; they were so many societies which governed them-
selves, each upon its own account, and by its own rules and
power. They stood in relation and came in contact, but there
was no true union; they did not form, properly speaking, a
nation, a state.
The fusion of all these societies into one has been accom-
plished. It is precisely, as you have seen, the distinctive fact,
the essential character of modern society. The ancient social
elements are reduced to two, the government and the people;
that is to say, the diversity has ceased, that similitude has led to
union. But before this result was consummated, and even with
a view to its prevention, many efforts were tried to make all
particular societies live and act in common, without destroying
their diversity or independence. It was not wished to strike
a blow in any way prejudicial to their situation, privileges, or
special nature, and yet to unite them in a single state, to form of
them one nation, to rally them under one and the same govern-
ment.
All these attempts failed. The result which I have just men-
tioned, the unity of modern society, proves their ill success.
Even in those European countries where some traces of the
ancient diversity of social elements, in Germany, for example,
where there is still a true feudal nobility, and a bourgeoisie; in
England, where a national church is in possession of special
revenues and a particular jurisdiction, it is clear that this pre-
tended distinct existence is but an appearance, an illusion; that
these special societies are politically confounded with the general
society, absorbed in the state, governed by the public powers,
in subjection to the same system, and carried away in the
current of the same ideas and the same manners. I repeat that,
where even the form of it still subsists, the independence of the
ancient social elements has no reality.
X48
BANQUET OF WALLENSTEIN'S GENERALS
A 7' PILSEN.
Photogravure from a painiing by Julius ScboU^.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 149
Still these attempts to make them co-ordinate without trans-
forming them, to attach them to a national unity without abolish-
ing their diversity, have held an important place in the history
of Europe; they partly fill the epoch which now occupies our
attention, that epoch which separates primitive from modern
Europe, and in which the metamorphosis of European society
was accomplished. And not only has it occupied an important
place therein, but it has also greatly influenced posterior events,
and the manner in which the reduction of all social elements
into two, the government and the public, has been brought '
about. It is, therefore, of consequence to properly estimate and
thoroughly understand all the essays at political organization
which were made from the twelfth to the sixteenth century, to
create nations and governments, without destroying the diver-
sity of the secondary societies placed side by side. Such will be
our business in this lecture.
It is a difficult and even a painful task. These attempts at
political organization have not all been conceived and directed
with a good intention; many of them have had no other views
but those of selfishness and tyranny. More than one, however,
has been pure and disinterested; more than one has really had
for its object the moral and social good of mankind. The state of
incoherence, violence and iniquity, in which society was then
placed, shocked great minds and elevated souls, and they inces-
santly sought the means of escaping from it. Still, even the best
of these noble essays have failed; and so much courage and
virtue, so many sacrifices and efforts, have been lost; is it not a
heart-rending spectacle? There is even one thing still more
painful, the source of a sadness still more bitter; not only have
these attempts at social amelioration failed, but an enormous
mass of error and evil has been mixed up therein. Despite the
good intention, the greater part were absurd, and indicated a
profound ignorance of reason, justice, the rights of humanity,
and the foundations of the social state; so that not only has
success been wanting to mankind, but they have merited their
failures. We here, then, have the spectacle, not only of the hard
destiny of humanity, but also of its weakness. one may here
see how the merest instalment of truth suffices so to occupy the
greatest minds that they entirely forget all the rest, and become
blind to everything which does not come within the straightened
horizon of their ideas; how a mere glimpse of justice in a cause
suffices to make them lose sight of all the injustice which it in-
volves and permits. This outburst of the vices and imperfection
of man, is, in my opinion, a contemplation even more melan-
choly than the misery of his condition; his faults weigh more
heavily upon me than his sufferings. The attempts which I have
to describe exhibit each of these spectacles. It is necessary to
I50 GUIZOT
go through with them, and to be just toward those men, those
ages, who have so often gone astray, and have so cruelly failed,
and who, notwithstanding, have displayed such high virtues,
made such noble efforts, merited so much glory!
The attempts at political organization, formed from the twelfth
to the sixteenth century, are of two kinds : the object of the one
was to bring about the predominance of a particular social ele-
ment, whether the clergy, the feudal nobility, or the boroughs ;
to make all the others subordinate to this, and on these terms
to establish unity. The other proposed to itself to reconcile all
the particular societies, and make them act in common, leaving
to each its liberty, and guaranteeing its share of influence. The
first class of these attempts is much more liable to the suspicion
of selfishness and tyranny than the second. They have, in fact,
oftener been tainted with these vices; they are, indeed, by their
very nature, essentially tyrannical in their means of action.
Some of them, however, may have been — in fact, have been —
conceived with pure views for the good and progress of
humanity.
The first which presents itself is the attempt at a theocratical
organization — that is to say, the design of subduing the various
classes of society to the principles and empire of the ecclesiastical
society. You will call to mind what I have said concern-
ing the history of the church. I have endeavored to show
what principles have been developed within it, what was the
share of legitimacy of each, how they were born of the natural
course of events, what services they have rendered, and what
evil they have brought about. I have characterized the various
states into which the church passed from the eighth to the
twelfth century; I have shown the state of the imperial church,
the barbarian, the feudal, and lastly, the theocratical church. I
suppose these recollections to be present to your minds; I shall
now endeavor to indicate what the clergy did to dominate in
Europe, and why they failed.
The attempt at theocratical organization appeared at a very
early period, whether in the acts of the court of Rome, or in
those of the clergy in general; it naturally resulted from the
political and moral superiority of the church, but we shall find
that it encountered, from the first, obstacles which, even in its
greatest vigor, it did not succeed in removing.
The first was the very nature of Christianity. Wholly different
in this respect from the greater number of religious creeds,
Christianity was established by persuasion alone, by simply
moral means; it was never, from the time of its birth, armed with
force. In the early ages it conquered by the Word alone, and it
only conquered souls. Hence it happened, that even after its
triumph, when the church was in possession of great riches and
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 151
consideration, we never find her invested with the direct govern-
ment of society. Her origin, purely moral, and merely by means
of persuasion, was found impressed in her condition. She had
much influence, but she had no power. She insinuated herself
into the municipal magistracies, she acted powerfully upon the
emperors and their agents, but she had not the positive admin-
istration of public affairs, the government, properly so called.
Now a system of government — the theocratical or any other —
cannot be established in an indirect manner by mere force of
influence; it is necessary to administer, command, receive taxes,
dispose of revenues, govern, in a word, actually to take posses-
sion of society. When nations and governments are acted upon
by persuasion, much may be effected, and a great empire exer-
cised; but there would be no government, no system would be
founded, the future could not be provided for. Such has been,
from its very origin, the situation of the Christian church; she
has always been at the side of the government of society, but
she has never removed it and taken its place; a great obstacle
which the attempt at theocratical organization could not sur-
mount.
She met at a very early period with a second obstacle. The
Roman Empire once fallen, and the barbarian states founded,
the church found herself among the conquered. The first thing
necessary was to escape this situation; the work she had to
commence by converting the conquerors, and thus raising her-
self to their rank. When this task was accomplished, and the
church aspired to domination, she encountered the pride and
resistance of the feudal nobiHty. This was a great service ren-
dered to Europe by the feudal laity; in the eleventh century
nations were almost entirely subjected to the church — sover-
eigns were scarce able to defend themselves ; the feudal nobility
alone never received the yoke of the clergy, never humbled them-
selves before it. one need only recall the general physiognomy
of the middle ages to be struck by the singular mixture of
haughtiness and submission, of blind credulity and freedom of
mind in the relations between the lay lords and the priests ; we
there see some wreck of their primitive condition. You will call
to mind how I endeavored to represent to you the origin of feu-
dalism, its first elements, and the manner in which the elementary
feudal society was formed around the habitation of the fief-
holder. I remarked how in that society the priest was below the
lord. Well, there always remained in the heart of the feudal
nobility a recollection and feeling of this situation; it always
regarded itself, not only as independent of the church, but as
superior to it, as alone called to possess and really govern the
country; it was always willing to live in concord with the
clergy, but so as to guard its own interests, and not to give in
152 GUIZOT
to those of the clergy. During many centuries it was the lay
aristocracy which maintained the independence of society with
regard to the church — that haughtily defended it when kings
and people were subdued. It was the first to oppose, and per-
haps contributed more than any other power to the failure of the
attempt at a theocratical organization of society.
A third obstacle was likewise opposed, of which in general
but little account has been held, and often even its effects been
misconstrued.
Wherever a clergy has seized upon society and subjected it
to a theocratical organization, it is upon a married clergy that
this empire has devolved, upon a body of priests recruiting
themselves from their own bosom, and bringing up their chil-
dren from their very birth in and for the same situation. Exam-
ine history : look at Asia, Egypt ; all the great theocracies are the
work of a clergy which is a complete society in itself, which
suffices for its own wants and borrows nothing from without.
By the celibacy of priests the Christian clergy was in an
entirely different position; it was obliged, in order to its per-
petuation, to have continual recourse to the laity; to seek from
abroad, in all social positions and professions, the means of
duration. In vain did the esprit-de-corps labor afterward to
assimilate these foreign elements; something of the origin of
the new-comers always remained; burghers or nobles, they
always preserved some trace of their ancient spirit, their former
condition. Doubtless celibacy, in placing the Catholic clergy
in an entirely special situation, foreign to the interests and
common life of mankind, has been to it a chief cause of isolation ;
but it has thus unceasingly forced it into connection with lay
society, in order to recruit and renew itself therefrom, to receive
and undergo some part of the moral revolutions which were ac-
complished in it ; and I do not hesitate to say that this necessity,
constantly renewing, has beeli much more prejudicial to the suc-
cess of the attempt at theocratical organization than the csprit-
de-corps, strongly maintained by celibacy, has been able to pro-
mote it.
The church finally encountered, within her own bosom, pow-
erful adversaries to this attempt. Much has been said concern-
ing the unity of the church, and it is true she has constantly
aspired to it, and in some respects has happily attained it. But
let us not be deceived by the pomp of words, nor by that of par-
tial facts. What society has presented more civil dissensions, or
undergone more dismemberment than the clergy? What na-
tion has been more divided, more disordered, more unfixed than
the ecclesiastical nation? The national churches of the majority
of European countries almost incessantly struggled against the
court of Rome ; councils struggled against popes ; heresies have
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 153
been innumerable and constantly renewing, schisms always in
readiness ; nowhere has there been such diversity of opinions,
such fury in contest, such parcelling out of power. The in-
ternal life of the church, the divisions which have broken out in
it, the revolutions which have agitated it, have, perhaps, been
the greatest obstacles to the triumph of that organization which
she has attempted to impose upon society.
All these obstacles were in action and visible in the very cradle
of the great attempt which we have in review. They did not,
however, prevent its following its course, nor its being in prog-
ress for many centuries. Its most glorious time, its day of
crisis, so to speak, was in the reign of Gregory VII, at the end
of the eleventh century. You have already seen that the dom-
inant idea of Gregory VII was to subjugate the world to the
clergy, the clergy to the papal power, and Europe to a vast and
regular theocracy. In this design, as far as it may be permitted
us to judge of events at such a distance, this great man commit-
ted, in my opinion, two great faults ; one the fault of a theorist,
the other of a revolutionist. The first was that of ostentatiously
displaying his plan, of systematically proclaiming his principles
on the nature and rights of spiritual power, of drawing from
them beforehand, like an intractable logician, the most distant
consequences. He thus menaced and attacked all the lay sover-
eignties of Europe, before being assured of the means of con-
quering them. Success in human afifairs is neither obtained by
such absolute proceedings, nor in the name of philosophical
argument. Moreover, Gregory VII fell into the common
error of revolutionists, that of attempting more than they can
execute, and not taking the possible as the measure and limit of
their efforts. In order to hasten the domination of his ideas, he
engaged in contest with the empire, with all the sovereigns and
with the clergy itself. He hesitated at no consequence, nor
cared for any interest, but haughtily proclaimed that he willed
to reign over all kingdoms, as well as over all minds, and thus
raised against him, on one side, all the temporal powers, who
saw themselves in pressing danger, and on the other the free-
thinkers, who began to appear, and who already dreaded the
tyranny over thought. Upon the whole, Gregory perhaps com-
promised more than he advanced the cause he wished to serve.
It, however, continued to prosper during the whole of the
twelfth and down to the middle of the thirteenth century. This
is the time of the greatest power and brilliancy of the church,
though I do not think it can be strictly said that she made any
great progress in that epoch. Down to the end of the reign of
Innocent III she rather cultivated than extended her glory and
power. It was at the moment of her greatest apparent success
that a popular reaction declared itself against her in a large por-
154 GUIZOT
tion of Europe. In the south of France the heresy of the Al-
bigenses broke forth, which took possession of an entire, numer-
ous, and powerful community. Almost at the same time in the
north, in Flanders, ideas and desires of the same nature ap-
peared. A little later, in England, Wyclif attacked with talent
the power of the church, and founded a sect which will never
perish. Sovereigns did not long delay entering the same path
as the people. It was at the commencement of the thirteenth
century that the most powerful and the ablest sovereigns of
Europe, the emperors of the house of Hohenstaufen, succumbed
in their struggle with the papacy. During this century Saint
Louis, the most pious of kings, proclaimed the independence of
the temporal power, and published the first Pragmatic Sanction,
which has been the basis of all others. At the commencement
of the fourteenth century the quarrel broke out between Philip le
Bel and Boniface VIII ; the king of England, Edward I, was
not more docile toward Rome. At this epoch, it is clear, the at-
tempt at a theocratical organization has failed; the church
henceforth, will be on the defensive ; she will no longer under-
take to impose her system upon Europe ; her only thought will
be to preserve what she has conquered. It is from the end of
the thirteenth century that the emancipation of the European
lay society really dates ; it was then that the church ceased to
pretend to the possession of it.
She had long before renounced this claim, in the very sphere
in which she seemed to have had the best chance of success.
Long since, upon the very threshold of the church, around her
very throne in Italy, theocracy had completely failed, and given
place to an entirely different system — to that attempt at a demo-
cratical organization, of which the Italian republics are the type,
and which, from the eleventh to the sixteenth century, played so
brilliant a part in Europe.
You recollect what I have already related of the history of the
boroughs, and the manner in which they were formed. In
Italy, their destiny was more precocious and powerful than any-
where else ; the towns there were much more numerous and
wealthy than in Gaul, Britain, or Spain ; the Roman municipal
system remained more full of life and regular there.
The country parts of Italy, also, were much less fit to become
the habitation of their new masters, than those of the rest of
Europe. They had everywhere been cleared, drained, and culti-
vated ; they were not clothed with forests ; here the barbarians
were unable to follow the hazards of the chase, or to lead an
analogous life to that of Germany. Moreover, one part of this
territory did not belong to them. The south of Italy, the Cam-
pagna di Roma and Ravenna, continued to depend upon the
Greek emperors. Favored by its distance from the sovereign
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 155
and the vicissitudes of war, the repubHcan system, at an early
period, gained strength and developed itself in this part of the
country. And not only the whole of Italy was not in the power
of the barbarians, but even where the barbarians did conquer it,
they did not remain in tranquil and definitive possession. The
Ostrogoths were destroyed and driven out by Belisarius and
Narses. The kingdom of the Lombards succeeded no better in
establishing itself. The Franks destroyed it ; and, without de-
stroying the Lombard population, Pepin and Charlemagne
judged it expedient to form an alliance with the ancient Italian
population, in order to struggle against the recently conquered
Lombards. The barbarians, then, were not in Italy, as else-
where, the exclusive and undisturbed masters of the land and of
society. Hence it was, that beyond the Alps, only a weak, thin,
and scattered feudalism was estabhshed. The preponderance,
instead of passing into the inhabitants of the country parts, as
had happened in Gaul, for example, continued to appertain to
the towns. When this result became evident, a large portion of
the fief-holders, either from free-will or necessity, ceased to in-
habit the country, and settled in the cities. Barbarian nobles
became burghers. You may imagine what power and superiority
this single fact gave the Italian towns as compared with the other
boroughs of Europe. What we have remarked in these latter,
was the inferiority and timidity of the population. The burghers
appeared to us like courageous freed men painfully struggling
against a master who was always at their gates. The burghers
of Italy were very different ; the conquering and the conquered
population mixed within the same walls ; the towns had not to
defend themselves from a neighboring master; their inhab-
itants were citizens, from all time free, at least the majority of
them, who defended their independence and their rights against
distant and foreign sovereigns, at one time against the Frank
kings, at another against the emperors of Germany. Hence, the
immense and early superiority of the towns of Italy : while else-
where even the poorest boroughs were formed with infinite
trouble, here we see republics, states arise.
Thus is explained the success of the attempt at republican
organization in this part of Europe. It subdued feudalism at a
very early period, and became the dominant form of society.
But it was Httle calculated to spread or perpetuate itself; it con-
tained but few germs of amelioration, the necessary condition to
extension and duration.
When we examine the history of the republics of Italy, from
the eleventh to the fifteenth century, we are struck with two ap-
parently contradictory yet incontestable facts. We find an ad-
mirable development of courage, activity and genius, and in con-
sequence great prosperity; there is there a movement and lib-
156 GUIZOT
erty which is wanting to the rest of Europe. Let us ask, what
was the real condition of the inhabitants, how their Hfe was
passed, what was their share of happiness? Here the aspect
changes; no history can be more melancholy and gloomy.
There is, perhaps, no epoch or country in which the position of
man appears to have been more agitated, subject to more de-
plorable mischances, or where we meet with more dissensions,
crimes, and misfortunes. Another fact is manifest at the same
time ; in the political system of the greater part of the republics
liberty continually diminished. The want of security was such
that the factions were inevitably forced to seek refuge in a
system less tempestuous, though less popular, than that with
which the state had commenced. Take the history of Florence,
Venice, Genoa, Milan, Pisa ; you will everywhere see that the
general course of events, instead of developing liberty, and en-
larging the circle of institutions, tends to contract it, and to con-
centre the power within the hands of a small number of men. In
a word, in these republics, so energetic, brilliant, and wealthy,
two things were wanting : security of life, the first condition of
a social state, and the progress of institutions.
Thence a new evil, which did not allow of the extension of the
attempt at republican organization. It was from without, from
foreign sovereigns, that the greatest danger was threatened to
Italy. Yet this danger had never the effect of reconciling these
republics and making them act in concert ; they would never
resist in common a common enemy. Many of the most enlight-
ened Italians, accordingly, the best patriots of our time, deplore
the republican system of Italy in the middle ages as the real cause
of its never having become a nation. It was parcelled out, they
say, into a multitude of petty people, too much under the control
of their passions to allow of their confederating, or constituting
themselves a state. They regret that their country, like the rest
of Europe, has not passed through a despotic centralization
which would have formed it into a nation, and have rendered it
independent of foreigners. It seems, then, that the republican
organization, even under the most favorable circumstances, did
not contain within itself at this epoch the principle of progress,
of duration, extension — that it had no future. Up to a certain
point, one may compare the organization of Italy in the middle
ages to that of ancient Greece. Greece also was a country full
of petty republics, always rivals and often enemies, and some-
times rallying toward a common end. The advantage in this
comparison is entirely with Greece. There can be no doubt
that, although history gives us many instances of iniquity in
them, too, there was more order, security, and justice in the in-
terior of Athens, Lacedaemon, Thebes, than in the Italian repub-
lics. Yet how short was the political existence of Greece I
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 157
What a principle of weakness existed in that parcelling out of
power and territory! When Greece came in contact with great
neighboring states, with Macedonia and Rome, she at once suc-
cumbed. These small republics, so glorious and still so flour-
ishing, could not form a coalition for defense. How much
stronger was the reason for the same result happening in Italy,
where society and human reason had been so much less de-
veloped and less firm than among the Greeks.
If the attempt at republican organization had so little chance
of duration in Italy, where it had triumphed, where the feudal
system had been vanquished, you may easily conceive that it
would much sooner succumb in the other parts of Europe.
I will rapidly place its destinies before you.
There was one portion of Europe which bore a great resem-
blance to Italy ; this was the south of France and the neighbor-
ing Spanish provinces, Catalonia, Navarre, and Biscay. There
likewise the towns had gained great development, importance,
and wealth. Many of the petty lords were allied with the
burghers ; a portion of the clergy had likewise embraced their
cause; in a word, the country was in a situation remarkably
analogous to that of Italy. Accordingly, in the course of the
eleventh century, and at the commencement of the twelfth, the
towns of Provence, Languedoc, and Aquitaine, aimed at a polit-
ical flight, at forming themselves into independent republics,
just like those beyond the Alps. But the south of France was
in contact with a very strong feudalism, that of the north. At
this time occurred the heresy of the Albigenses, and war broke
out between feudal and municipal France. You know the his-
tory of the crusade against the Albigenses, under Simon de
Montfort. This was the contest of the feudalism of the north
against the attempt at democratical organization of the south.
Despite the southern patriotism, the north carried the day;
political unity was wanting in the south, and civilization was not
sufflciently advanced for men to supply its place by concert.
The attempt at republican organization was put down, and the
crusade re-established the feudal system in the south of France.
At a later period, the republican attempt met with better suc-
cess in the mountains of Switzerland. There the theater was
very straitened. They had only to struggle against a foreign
sovereign, who, although of a superior force to the Swiss, was
by no means among the most formidable sovereigns of Europe.
The struggle was courageously sustained. The Swiss feudal
nobility allied themselves in a great measure with the towns — a
powerful succor, which, however, altered the nature of the revo-
lution which it aided, and imprinted upon it a more aristocratic
and less progressive character than it seemed at first intended to
bear.
158 GUIZOT
I now pass to the north of France, to the boroughs of Flan-
ders, the banks of the Rhine, and the Hanseatic league. There
the democratical organization triumphed fully in the interior of
the towns; yet, we perceive, from its outset, that it was not
destined to extend itself, or to take entire possession of society.
The boroughs of the north were surrounded and oppressed by
feudalism, by lords and sovereigns, so that they were constantly
on the defensive. It is clear that all they did was to defend
themselves as well as they could ; they essayed no conquests.
They preserved their privileges, but remained shut up within
their own walls. There the democratical organization was con-
fined and stopped short ; if we go elsewhere into the country, we
do not find it.
You see what was the state of the republican attempt. Tri-
umphant in Italy, but with little chance of success or progress ;
vanquished in the south of Gaul; victorious on a small scale
in the mountains of Switzerland ; in the north, in the boroughs
of Flanders, the Rhine, and the Hanseatic league, con-
demned never to pass beyond the town walls. Still, in this posi-
tion, evidently inferior in force to the other elements of society,
it inspired the feudal nobility with a prodigious terror. The
lords were jealous of the wealth of the boroughs, and feared their
power; the democratical spirit penetrated into the rural dis-
tricts ; the insurrections of the peasants became more frequent
and obstinate. A great coalition was formed among the feudal
nobility against the boroughs, almost throughout Europe. The
party was unequal ; the boroughs were isolated ; there was no
understanding or communication between them ; all was local.
There existed, indeed, a certain sympathy between the burghers
of various countries. The successes or reverses of the towns in
Flanders in the struggles with the dukes of Burgundy certainly
excited a lively emotion in the French towns. But this emotion
was transitory and without result. No tie, no real union, was
established. Nor did the boroughs lend strength to one an-
other. Feudalism, then, had immense advantages over them.
But, itself divided and incoherent, it did not succeed in destroy-
ing them. When the struggle had lasted a certain time, when
they had acquired the conviction that a complete victory was im-
possible, it became necessary to acknowledge the petty republican
burghers, to treat with them, and to receive them as members ol
the state. Then a new order commenced, a new attempt at
political organization, that of mixed organization, the object of
which was to reconcile all the elements of society, the feudal
nobility, the boroughs, clergy and sovereigns, and to make them
live and act together in spite of their profound hostility.
All of you know what are the States-general in France, the
Cortes in Spain and Portugal, the Parliament in England, and
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 1^9
the Diets in Germany. You know, likewise, what were the ele-
ments of these various assemblies. The feudal nobility, the
clergy and the boroughs, collected at them with a view to unite
themselves into a single society, into one state, under one law
and one power. They all, under various names, have the same
tendency and design.
I shall take, as the type of this attempt, the fact which is the
most interesting and the best known to us, namely, the States-
general in France. I say the best known to us ; yet I am con-
vinced that the name of States-general awakens in your minds
only vague and incomplete ideas. None of you can say what
there was fixed or regular in the States-general of France, what
was the number of their members, what the subjects of delibera-
tion, or what the periods of convocation, and the duration of
sessions ; nothing is known of these things ; it is impossible to
draw from history any clear, general, or universal results as to
this subject. When we examine closely the character of these
assemblies in the history of France, they look like mere acci-
dents, political last resource alike for people and knigs ; as a last
resource for kings when they had no money, and knew not how
to escape from their embarrassments ; and as a last resource for
the people when the evil became so great that they knew not
what remedy to apply. The nobility were present in the States-
general ; the clergy likewise took part in them ; but they came
full of indifference, for they knew that this was not their great
means of action, that they could not promote by it the real part
they took in the government. The burghers themselves were
scarcely more eager about it ; it was not a right which they took
an interest in exercising, but a necessity which they tolerated.
Thus may be seen the character of the political activity of these
assemblies. They were sometimes utterly insignificant, and
sometimes terrible. If the king was the strongest, their humility
and docility were carried to an extreme ; if the situation of the
crown was unfortunate, if it had absolute need of the states,
they fell into faction and became the instruments of some aris-
tocratical intrigue, or some ambitious leaders. In a word, they
were sometimes mere assemblies of notables, sometimes regular
conventions. Thus their works almost always died with them ;
they promised and attempted much, and did nothing. None of
the great measures which have really acted upon society in
France, no important reform in the government, the legislation,
or the administration, has emanated from the States-general. It
must not, however, be supposed that they were without utility or
effect ; they have had a moral effect, of which too little account
is generally taken ; they have been, from one epoch to another,
a protest against political servitude, a violent proclamation of
certain tutelary principles; for example, that the country has
i6o GUIZOT
the right to impose taxes, to interfere in its own affairs, and to
impose a responsibility upon the agents of power.
That these maxims have never perished in France is to be at-
tributed to the States-general, and it is no small service to render
to a people, to maintain in its manners, and renew in its thoughts
the remembrances and rights of liberty. The States-general
have possessed this virtue, but they have never been a means of
government; they have never entered into the political organi-
zation ; they have never attained the end for which they were
formed, that is to say, the fusion into a single body of the various
societies which divided the country.
The Cortes of Spain and Portugal offer us the same result. In
a thousand circumstances, however, they are different. The im-
portance of the Cortes varies according to place and time; in
Aragon and Biscay, amid the debates concerning the succession
to the crown, or the struggle against the Moors, they were more
frequently convoked and more powerful. In certain Cortes, for
example, in those of Castile in 1370 and 1373, the nobles and the
clergy were not called. There is a crowd of details which it is
necessary should be taken into account, if we look closely into
events. But in the general view to which I am obliged to con-
fine myself, it may be said of the Cortes, as of the States-general
of France, that they have been an accident in history, and never
a system, political organization, or a regular means of govern-
ment.
The destiny of England was different. I shall not now enter
upon this subject in detail. I propose to devote one lecture
especially to the political life of England ; I shall now merely
say a few words upon the causes which have imparted to it a di-
rection entirely different from that of the continent.
And, first, there were no great vassals in England, no subject
in a condition to strive personally against royalty. The English
barons and great lords were obliged to coalesce in order to resist
in common. Thus have prevailed, in the high aristocracy, the
principle of association and true political manners. Moreover,
English feudalism, the petty fief-holders, have been gradually
led by a series of events, which I cannot enumerate at present, to
unite themselves with the burghers, to sit with them in the
House of Commons, which thus possessed a power superior to
that of the continental assemblies, a force truly capable of influ-
encing the government of the country. Let us see what was the
state of the British Parliament in the fourteenth century. The
House of Lords was the great council of the king, a council
actively associated in the exercise of power. The House of
Commons, composed of the deputies of the petty fief-holders,
and of burghers, took scarcely any part in the government, prop-
erly so called, but it established rights, and very energetically
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE i6i
defended private and local interests. The Parliament, consid-
ered as a whole, did not yet govern, but it was already a regular
institution, a means of government adopted in principle, and
often, in fact, indispensable. Thus the attempt at junction and
alliance between the various elements of society, with a view to
form of them a single political body, a regular state, was success-
ful in England, while it had failed everywhere on the continent.
I shall say but a few words as to Germany, and those only to
indicate the dominant character of its history. There the at-
tempts at fusion, unity, and general political organization, were
followed with little ardor. The various social elements remained
much more distinct and independent than in the rest of Europe.
If a proof is wanted, one may be found in modern times. Ger-
many is the only country in which the feudal election long took
part in the creation of royalty. I do not speak of Poland, nor
the Slavonian nations, which entered at so late an age into the
system of European civilization. Germany is likewise the only
country of Europe where ecclesiastical sovereigns remained;
which preserved free towns, having a true political existence and
sovereignty. It is clear that the attempt to combine in a single
society the elements of primitive European society has there had
much less activity and effect than elsewhere.
I have now placed before you the great essays at political or-
ganization in Europe down to the end of the fourteenth century
and the beginning of the fifteenth. You have seen them all fail.
I have endeavored to indicate, in passing, the causes of this ill-
success ; indeed, truly speaking, they are reduceable to one.
Society was not sufficiently advanced for unity ; everything was
as yet too local, too special, too narrow, too various in existence,
and in men^s minds. There were neither general interests nor
general opinions capable of controlling particular interests and
opinions. The most elevated and vigorous minds had no idea
of administration, nor of true political justice. It was evidently
necessary that a more active and vigorous civilization should
first mix, assimilate, and, so to speak, grind together all these in-
coherent elements ; it was first necessary that a powerful cen-
tralization of interest, laws, manners, and ideas should be
brought about ; in a word, it was necessary that a public power
and public opinion should arise. We have arrived at the epoch
when this great work was consummated. Its first symptoms,
the state of mind and manners during the course of the fifteenth
century, the tendency toward the formation of a central govern-
ment, and a public opinion, will form the subject of our next
Jecture.
zx
ELEVENTH LECTURE.
WE touch the threshold of modern history, properly so
called — the threshold of that society which is our
own, of which the institutions, opinions and man-
ners were, forty years ago, those of France, are still those of
Europe, and still exercise so powerful an influence upon us,
despite the metamorphosis brought about by our revolution.
It was with the sixteenth century, as I have already said, that
modern society really commenced. Before entering upon it,
recall to your minds, I pray you, the roads over which we have
passed. We have discovered amid the ruins of the Roman
Empire all the essential elements of the Europe of the present
day ; we have seen them distinguish and aggrandize themselves,
each on its own account, and independently. We recognized,
during the first epoch of history, the constant tendency of these
elements to separation, isolation and a local and special exist-
ence. Scarcely was this end obtained — scarcely had feudalism,
the boroughs and the clergy each taken its distinct form and
place, than we see them tending to approach each other, to
reunite, and form themselves into a general society, into a
nation and a government. In order to arrive at this result, the
various countries of Europe addressed themselves to all the
different systems which co-existed in its bosom ; they demanded
the principle of social unity, the political and moral tie, from
theocracy, aristocracy, democracy and royalty. Hitherto all
these attempts had failed ; no system or influence had known
how to seize upon society, and by its empire to insure it a truly
public destiny. We have found the cause of this ill-success in
the absence of universal interests and ideas. We have seen
that all was, as yet, too special, individual and local ; that a long
and powerful labor of centralization was necessary to enable so-
ciety to extend and cement itself at the same time, to become
at once great and regular — an end to which it necessarily
aspired. This was the state in which we left Europe at the end
of the fourteenth century.
She was far from understanding her position, such as I have
endeavored to place it before you. She did not know distinctly
what she wanted or what she sought ; still she applied herself
to the search as if she knew. The fourteenth century closed.
x6a
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 163
Europe entered naturally, and, as it were, instinctively, the
path which led to centralization. It is the characteristic of the
fifteenth century to have constantly tended to this result; to
have labored to create universal interests and ideas, to make
the spirit of specialty and locality disappear, to reunite and
elevate existences and minds ; in fine, to create what had hitherto
never existed on a large scale, nations and governments. The
outbreak of this fact belongs to the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries; it was in the fifteenth that it was preparing. It is
this preparation which we have to investigate at present — this
siJent and concealed work of centralization, whether in social
relations or ideas, a work accomplished by the natural course
of events, without premeditation or design.
Thus man advances in the execution of a plan which he has
not himself conceived, or which, perhaps, he does not even un-
derstand. He is the intelligent and free artificer of a work
which does not belong to him. He does not recognize or com-
prehend it until at a later period, when it manifests itself out-
wardly and in realities; and even then he understands it but
very incompletely. Yet it is by him, it is by the development
of his intellect and his liberty that it is accomplished. Con-
ceive a great machine, of which the idea resides in a single
mind, and of which the different pieces are confided to different
workmen, who are scattered, and are strangers to one another ;
none of them knowing the work as a whole, or the definitive
and general result to which it concurs, yet each executing with
intelligence and liberty, by rational and voluntary acts, that of
which he has the charge. So is the plan of Providence upon
the world executed by the hand of mankind ; thus do the two
facts which manifest themselves in the history of civilization
co-exist ; on the one hand, its fatality, that which escapes science
and the human will — and on the other, the part played therein
by the liberty and intellect of man, that which he infuses of his
own will by his own thought and inclination.
In order properly to comprehend the fifteenth century — to
obtain a clear and exact idea of this prelude, as it were, of
modern society — we will distinguish the different classes of
facts. We will first examine the political facts, the changes
which have tended to form both nations and governments.
Thence we will pass to moral facts; we will observe the
changes which have been produced in ideas and manners, and
we will thence deduce what general opinions were in prepara-
tion. As regards political facts, in order to proceed simply
and quickly, I will run over all the great countries of Europe,
and show you what the fifteenth century made of them — in
what state it found and lift them.
I shall commence with France. The last half of the four-
i64 GUIZOT
teenth century and the first half of the fifteenth were, as you
know, the times of great national wars — the wars against the
English. It was the epoch of the struggle for the independence
of France and the French name against a foreign dominion.
A glance at history will show with what ardor, despite a mul-
titude of dissensions and treasons, all classes of society in
France concurred in the struggle ; what patriotism took pos-
session of the feudal nobility, the burghers and even peasants.
If there were nothing else to show the popular character of the
event than the history of Joan of Arc, it would be more than
sufficient proof. Joan of Arc sprung from the people. It was
by the sentiments, creed and passions of the people that she
was inspired and sustained. She was looked upon with dis-
trust, scorn and even enmity by the people of the court and the
chiefs of the army ; but she had the soldiers and the people ever
on her side. It was the peasants of Lorraine who sent her to the
succor of the burghers of Orleans. No event has more strik-
ingly shown the popular character of this war, and the feeling
with which the whole country regarded it.
Thus began the formation of French nationality. Up to the
reign of the Valois it was the feudal character which dominated
in France; the French nation, the French mind, French pa-
triotism, did not as yet exist. With the Valois commenced
France, properly so called. It was in the course of their wars,
through the phases of their destiny, that the nobility, the
burghers and the peasants, were for the first time united by a
moral tie, by the tie of a common name, a common honor and a
common desire to conquer the enemy. But expect not to find
there as yet any true political spirit, not any great purpose of
unity in the government and institutions, such as we conceive
them at the present day. Unity in the France of this epoch
resided in its name, its national honor, and in the existence of a
national royalty, whatever it might be, provided the foreigner
did not appear therein. It is in this way that the struggle
against the English powerfully contributed to the formation of
the French nation, to impel it toward unity. At the same time
that France was thus morally forming herself, and the national
spirit was being developed, she was also forming herself ma-
terially, so to speak — that is to say, her territory was being
regulated, extended, strengthened. This was the period of the
incorporation of the greater part of the provinces which have
become France. Under Charles VII, after the expulsion of
the English, almost all the provinces which they had occupied,
Normandy, Angoumois, Touraine, Poitou, Saintonge, etc.,
became definitively French. Under Louis XI, ten provinces,
three of which were afterward lost and regained, were united
to France; namely, Roussillon and Cerdagne, Burgundy,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 165
Franche-Comte, Picardy, Artois, Provence, Maine, Anjou and
Perche. Under Charles VIII and Louis XII, the successive
marriages of Anne with these two kings brought us Brittany.
Thus, at the same epoch, and during the course of the same
events, the national territory and mind were forming together ;
moral and material France conjointly acquired strength and
unity.
Let us pass from the nation to the government ; we shall see
the accomplishment of similar facts, shall move toward the same
result. Never had the French government been more devoid of
unity, connection and strength than under the reign of Charles
VI and during the first part of that of Charles VII. At the end
of this later reign the aspect of all things changed. There was
evidently a strengthening, extending and organizing of power ;
all the great means of government — taxes, military force, law —
were created upon a great scale and with some uniformity.
This was the time of the formation of standing armies — free
companies, cavalry — and free archers, infantry. By these com-
panies Charles VII re-established some order in those provinces
which had been desolated by the disorders and exactions of
the soldiery, even after war had ceased. All contemporary his-
torians speak with astonishment of the marvellous effects of
the free companies. It was at the same epoch that the poll-tax,
one of the principal revenues of the kingdom, became perpet-
ual ; a serious blow to the liberty of the people, but which pow-
erfully contributed to the regularity and strength of the govern-
ment. At this time, too, the great instrument of power, the
administration of justice, was extended and organized; par-
liaments multiplied. There were five new parliaments con-
stituted within a very short period of time: under Louis XI,
the parliament of Grenoble (in 145 1), of Bordeaux (in 1462),
and of Dijon (in 1477) ; under Louis XII, the parHaments of
Rouen (in 1499), and of Aix (in 1501). The parHament of
Paris, also, at this time greatly increased in importance and
firmness, both as regards the administration of justice and as
charged with the policy of its jurisdiction.
Thus, as regards military force, taxation and justice, that is,
in what constitutes its very essence, government in France in
the fifteenth century acquired a character of permanence and
regularity hitherto unknown; public power definitively took
the place of the feudal powers.
At the same time another and far different change was
brought about ; a change which was less visible and which has
less impressed itself upon historians, but which was perhaps
of still more importance — namely, the change which Louis XI
effected in the manner of governing.
Much has been said concerning the struggle of Louis XI
l66 GUIZOT
against the high nobles of the kingdom, of their abasement,
and of his favor toward the burghers and the lower classes.
There is truth in this, although much of it is exaggerated ; it is
also true that the conduct of Louis XI toward the different
classes oftener troubled than served the state. But he did
something much more important. Up to this time the govern-
ment had proceeded almost entirely by force and by material
means. Persuasion, address, the managing men's minds and
leading them to particular views, in a word, policy — policy
doubtless of falsehood and imposition, but also of management
and prudence, had hitherto been but little attended to. Louis
XI substituted in the government intellectual in place of ma-
terial means, artifice instead of force, the Italian policy in place
of the feudal. Look at the two men whose rivalry occupies
this epoch of our history, Charles le Temeraire and Louis XL
Charles was the representative of the ancient form of govern-
ing; he proceeded by violence alone, he appealed incessantly to
war, he was incapable of exercising patience, or of addressing
himself to the minds of men in order to make them instruments
to his success. It was on the contrary the pleasure of Louis XI
to avoid the use of force and take possession of men individually
by conversation and the skilful handling of interests and minds.
He changed neither the institutions nor the external system,
but only the secret proceedings, the tactics of power. It was
left for modern times to attempt a still greater revolution, by
laboring to introduce, alike into political means as into politi-
cal ends, justice instead of selfishness, and publicity instead of
lying fraud. It is not less true, however, that there was great
indication of progress in renouncing the continual employment
of force, in invoking chiefly intellectual superiority, in govern-
ing through mind, and not by the ruin of existences. It was
this that Louis XI commenced, by force of his high intellect
alone, amid all his crimes and faults, despite his bad nature.
From France I pass to Spain ; there I find events of the same
nature ; it was thus that the national unity of Spain was formed
in the fifteenth century ; at that time, by the conquest of the
kingdom of Grenada, the lengthened struggle between the
Christians and the Arabs was put an end to. Then, also, the
country was centralized ; by the marriage of Ferdinand the
Catholic and Isabella, the two principal kingdoms of Castile
and Aragon were united under one power. As in France, royalty
was here extended and strengthened ; sterner institutions,
and which bore a more mournful name, served as its fulcrum ;
instead of parliament, the inquisition arose. It contained in
germ what it was to be, but it was not then the same as in its
maturer age. It was at first rather political than religious, and
intended rather to maintain order than to defend the faith. The
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 167
analogy extends beyond institutions, it is found even in the
persons. With less artifice, mental movement and restless and
busy activity, the character and government of Ferdinand the
Catholic resembles that of Louis XL I hold as unimportant
all arbitrary comparisons and fanciful parallels; but here the
analogy is profound and visible alike in general facts and in
details.
We find the same in Germany. It was in the middle of the
fifteenth century, in 1438, that the house of Austria returned to
the empire, and with it the imperial power acquired a perma-
nence which it had never possessed before ; election afterward
did little more than consecrate the hereditary successor. At the
end of the fifteenth century Maximilian I definitively founded the
preponderance of his house and the regular exercise of central
authority; Charles VII first created in France a standing army
for the maintenance of order ; Maximilian was also the first, in
his hereditary states, to attain the same end by the same means.
Louis XI established the post-office in France ; and MaximiHan
introduced it into Germany. Everywhere the same progressions
of civilization were similarly cultivated for the good of central
power.
The history of England in the fifteenth century consists of
two great events ; without, the struggle against the French, and
within, that of the two roses, the foreign and the civil war.
These two so dissimilar wars led to the same result. The strug-
gle against the French was sustained by the English people
with an ardor which profited only royalty. This nation, already
more skilful and firm than any other in keeping back its forces
and supplies, at this epoch abandoned them to its kings without
foresight or limit. It was under the reign of Henry V that a
considerable tax, the customs, was granted to the king from the
commencement of his reign until his death. When the foreign
war was ended, or almost so, the civil war, which had been as-
sociated with it, continued alone; the houses of York at first
and Lancaster disputed for the throne. When they came to the
end of their bloody contests, the high English aristocracy found
itself ruined, decimated and incapable of preserving the power
which it had hitherto exercised. The coalition of the great
barons could no longer influence the throne. The Tudors as-
cended it, and with Henry VH, in 1485, commenced the epoch
of poHtical centralization and the triumph of royalty. '
Royalty was not established in Italy, at least not under that
name ; but this matters little as regards the result. It was in
the fifteenth century that the republics fell; even where the
name remained, the power was concentred in the hands of one
or more families ; republican life was extinct. In the north of
Italy, almost all the Lombard republics were absorbed in the
1 68 GUIZOT
duchy of Milan. In 1434 Florence fell under the domination
of Medicis ; in 1464 Genoa became subject to the Milanese. The
greater portion of the republics, great and small, gave place to
sovereign houses. The pretensions of foreign sovereigns were
soon put forth upon the north and south of Italy, upon the
Milanese on one side, and the kingdom of Naples on the other.
Upon v^hatever country of Europe we turn our eyes, and
whatever portion of its history we may consider, whether it has
reference to the nations themselves, or to their governments, to
the institutions of the countries, we shall everywhere see the
ancient elements and forms of society on the point of disappear-
ing. The traditional liberties perish and new and more con-
centrated and regular powers arise. There is something pro-
foundly sad in the fall of the old European liberties; at the
time it inspired the bitterest feelings. In France, Germany,
and above all, Italy, the patriots of the fifteenth century con-
tested with ardor, and deplored with despair, this revolution,
which, on all sides, was bringing about what might justly be
called despotism. one cannot help admiring their courage
and commiserating their sorrow ; but at the same time it must
be understood that this revolution was not only inevitable, but
beneficial also. The primitive system of Europe, the old feudal
and communal liberties, had failed in the organization of so-
ciety. What constitutes social life is security and progress.
Any system which does not procure present order and future
progress, is vicious, and soon abandoned. Such was the fate of
the ancient political forms, the old European liberties, in the
fifteenth century. They could give to society neither se-
curity nor progress. These were sought elsewhere from other
principles and other means. This is the meaning of all the facts
which I have just placed before you.
From the same epoch dates another fact which has held an
important place in the political history of Europe. It was in the
fifteenth century that the relations of governments between
themselves began to be frequent, regular, permanent. It was
then for the first time that those great alliances were formed,
whether for peace or war, which at a later period produced the
system of equilibrium. Diplomacy in Europe dates from the
fifteenth century. Toward the end of this century you see the
principal powers of Continental Europe, the popes, the dukes
of Milan, the Venetians, the emperors of Germany and the
kings of Spain and of France, form connections, negotiate,
unite, balance each other. Thus, at the time that Charles VII
formed his expedition to conquer the kingdom of Naples, a
great league was formed against him, between Spain, the pope,
and the Venetians. The league of Cambrai was formed some
years later (in 1508), against the Venetians. The holy league,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 169
directed against Louis XII, succeeded in 151 1 to the league of
Cambrai. All these alliances arose from Italian policy, from
the desire of various sovereigns to possess Italy, and from the
fear that some one of them, by seizing it exclusively, should ac-
quire an overpowering preponderance. This new order of facts
was highly favorable to the development of royalty. on the
one hand, from the nature of the external relations of states,
they can only be conducted by a single person or a small num-
ber of persons, and exact a certain secrecy; on the other, the
people had so little foresight, that the consequences of an al-
liance of this kind escaped them ; it was not for them of any in-
ternal or direct interest ; they cared little about it, and left such
events to the discretion of the central power. Thus diplomacy
at its birth fell into the hands of the kings, and the idea that it
belonged exclusively to them, that the country, although free,
and having the right of voting its taxes and interfering in its
afifairs> was not called upon to mix itself in external matters —
this idea, I say, was established in almost all European minds
as an accepted principle, a maxim of common law. Open Eng-
lish history at the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, you will
see what power this idea exercised, and what obstacle it opposed
to EngHsh liberties under the reigns of EHzabeth, James I and
Charles I. It was always under the name of this principle that
peace and war, commercial relations, and all external affairs,
appertained to the royal prerogative ; and it was by this that ab-
solute power defended itself against the rights of the country.
Nations have been excessively timid in contesting this part of
prerogative; and this timidity has cost them the more dear,
since, from the epoch upon which we are now entering, that is
to say, the sixteenth century, the history of Europe is essen-
tially diplomatic. External relations, during nearly three cen-
turies, are the important fact of history. Within nations be-
came regulated, the internal government, upon the continent
at least, led to no more violent agitations, nor absorbed public
activity. It is external relations, wars, negotiations and al-
liances, which attract attention, and fill the pages of history, so
that the greater portion of the destiny of nations has been aban-
doned to the royal prerogative and to central power.
Indeed, it was hardly possible it should be otherwise. A very
great progress in civilization, and a great development of intel-
lect and political skill are necessary, before the public can inter-
fere with any success in affairs of this kind. From the
sixteenth to the eighteenth century, the people were very far
from being thus quahfied. See what took place under James I
in England at the commencement of the seventeenth century :
his son-in-law, the elector-palatine, elected king of Bohemia,
lost his crown ; he was even robbed of his hereditary states, the
I70 GUIZOT
palatinate. The whole of Protestantism was interested in his
cause, and for that reason England testified a lively interest to-
ward him. There was a powerful ebullition of public opinion to
force King James to take the part of his son-in-law, and regain
for him the palatinate. Parliament furiously demanded war,
promising all the means for carrying it on. James was unwill-
ing ; he eluded the matter, made some attempts at negotiation,
sent some troops to Germany, and then came to tell Parliament
that £900,000 sterling were necessary to maintain the contest
with any chance of success. It is not said, nor indeed does it
appear to have been the case, that his calculation was exagger-
ated. But the Parliament recoiled with surprise and terror at
the prospect of such a charge, and it unwilHngly voted £70,000
sterling to re-establish a prince, and reconquer a country three
hundred leagues from England. Such was the political igno-
rance and incapacity of the public in matters of this kind ; it
acted without knowledge of facts, and without troubling itself
with any responsibility. It was not then in a condition to inter-
fere in a regular or efficacious manner. This is the principal
cause of the external relations falling into the hands of the cen-
tral power ; that alone was in a condition to direct them, I do not
say for the public interest, for it was far from being always con-
sulted, but with any continuity or good sense.
You see, under whatever point of view the political history of
Europe at this epoch is presented to us, whether we turn our
eyes upon the internal state of nations, or upon the relations of
nations with each other, whether we consider the administration
of war, justice, or taxation, we everywhere find the same char-
acter ; everywhere we see the same tendency to the centraliza-
tion, unity, formation and preponderance of general interests
and public powers. This was the secret work of the fifteenth
century, a work which did not as yet lead to any very prominent
result, nor any revolution, properly so called, in society, but
which prepared the way for all of them. I shall immediately
place before you facts of another nature, moral facts, facts which
relate to the development of the human mind and universal
ideas. There also we shall acknowledge the same phenomenon,
and arrive at the same result.
I shall commence with a class of facts which has often occu-
pied us, and which, under the most various forms, has always
held an important place in the history of Europe, namely, facts
relative to the church. Down to the fifteenth century we have
seen in Europe no universal and powerful ideas acting truly upon
the masses, except those of a religious nature. We have seen the
church alone invested with the power of regulating, promulgat-
ing and prescribing them. Often, it is true, attempts at inde-
pendence, even separation, were formed, and the church had
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 171
much to do to overcome them. But hitherto she had conquered
them; creeds repudiated by the church had taken no general
and permanent possession of the minds of the people ; the Albi-
genses themselves were crushed. Dissension and contest were
of incessant occurrence in the heart of the church, but without
any decisive or eminent result. At the beginning of the fifteenth
century an entirely dififerent fact announced itself ; new ideas, a
public and avowed want of change and reform, agitated the
church herself. The end of the fourteenth and commencement
of the fifteenth century were marked by the great schism of the
west, the result of the translation of the holy see to Avignon,
and of the creation of two popes, one at Avignon, the other at
Rome. The struggle between these two papacies is what is
called the great schism of the west. It commenced in 1378.
In 1409, the council of Pisa wishing to end it, deposed both
popes, and nominated a third, Alexander V. So far from being
appeased, the schism became warmer ; there were three popes
instead of two. The disorder and abuses continued to increase.
In 1414 the council of Constance assembled at the summons of
the Emperor Sigismond. It proposed to itself a work very dif-
ferent from nominating a new pope ; it undertook the reform of
the church. It first proclaimed the indissolubility of the gen-
eral council, and its superiority over the papal power ; it under-
took to make these principles prevalent in the church, and to
reform the abuses which had crept into it, above all the exac-
tions by which the court of Rome had procured supplies. For
the attainment of this end, the council nominated what we will
call a commission of inquiry, that is to say, a college of reform,
composed of deputies of the council taken from different na-
tions ; it was the duty of this college to seek what were the
abuses which disgraced the church, and how they might best be
remedied, and to make a report to the council, which would con-
sult upon the means of execution. But while the council was
occupied in this work, the question was mooted as to whether
they could proceed in the reformation of abuses, without the
visible participation of the chief of the church, without the
sanction of the pope. The negative was passed by the influence
of the Romanist party, supported by honest, but timid men;
the council elected a new pope, Martin V, in 1417. The pope
was desired to present on his part a plan of reform in the
church. This plan was not approved, and the council sepa-
rated. In 143 1 a new council assembled at Basle with the same
view. It resumed and continued the work of reform of the
council of Constance, and met with no better success. Schism
broke out in the interior of the assembly, the same as in Chris-
tianity. The pope transferred the council of Basle to Ferrara,
and afterward to Florence. Part of the prelates refused to obey
172 GUIZOT
the pope, and remained at Basle ; and as formerly there had been
two popes, so there were now two councils. That of Basle con-
tinued its projects of reform, and nominated its pope, Felix V.
After a certain time it transported itself to Lausanne; and in
1449 dissolved itself, without having effected anything.
Thus papacy carried the day, and remained in possession of
the field of battle and the government of the church. The
council could not accomplish what it had undertaken ; but it
effected things which it had not undertaken, and which sur-
vived it. At the time that the council of Basle failed in its at-
tempts at reform, sovereigns seized upon the ideas which it pro-
claimed, and the institution which it suggested. In France,
upon the foundation of the decrees of the council of Basle,
Charles V formed the Pragmatic Sanction, which he issued at
Bourges in 1438; it enunciated the election of bishops, the sup-
pression of first fruits, and the reform of the principal abuses
which had been introduced into the church. The Pragmatic
Sanction was declared in France the law of the state. In Ger-
many, the diet of Mayence adopted it in 1439, ^^^ likewise made
it a law of the German Empire. What the spiritual power had
unsuccessfully attempted, the temporal power seemed destined
to accomplish.
New reverses sprung up for the projects of reform. As the
council had failed, so did the Pragmatic Sanction. In Ger-
many it perished very abruptly. The diet abandoned it in 1448,
in consequence of a negotiation with Nicholas V. In 15 16,
Francis I likewise abandoned it, and in its place substituted
his Concordat with Leo X. The princes' reform did not suc-
ceed any better than that of the clergy. But it must not be sup-
posed that it entirely perished. As the council effected things
which survived it, so also the Pragmatic Sanction had conse-
quences which it left behind, and which played an important
part in modern history. The principles of the council of Basle
were powerful and fertile. Superior men, and men of ener-
getic character, have adopted and supported them. John of
Paris, D'Ailly, Gerson, and many distinguished men of the
fifteenth century, devoted themselves to their defense. In vain
was the council dissolved ; in vain was the Pragmatic Sanction
abandoned ; its general doctrines upon the government of the
church, and upon the reforms necessary to be carried out, had
taken root in France ; they were perpetuated ; they passed into
the parliaments; and became a powerful opinion. They gave
rise first to the Jansenists and afterward to the Gallicans. All
this series of maxims and efforts tending to reform the church,
which commenced with the council of Constance and terminated
with the four propositions of Bossuet, emanated from the same
source and were directed toward the same end ; it was the same
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 173
fact successively transformed. It was in vain that the attempt
at legal reform in the fifteenth century failed ; not the less has
it taken its place in the course of civilization — not the less has
it indirectly exercised an enormous influence.
The councils were right in pursuing a legal reform, for that
alone could prevent a revolution. Almost at the moment when
the council of Pisa undertook to bring the great schism of the
west to a termination, and the council of Constance to reform
the church, the first essays at popular religious reform violently
burst forth in Bohemia. The predictions and progress of John
Huss date from 1404, at which period he began to teach at
Prague. Here, then, are two reforms marching side by side ;
the one in the very heart of the church, attempted by the eccle-
siastical aristocracy itself — a wise, but embarrassed and timid
reform ; the other, outside and against the church, violent and
passionate. A contest arose between these two powers and
designs. The council summoned John Huss and Jerome of
Prague to Constance, and condemned them as heretics and
revolutionists. These events are perfectly intelligible to us at
the present day. We can very well understand this simulta-
neousness of separate reforms — enterprises undertaken, one by
the governments, the other by the people, opposed to one
another, and yet emanating from the same cause and tending to
the same end, and, in fine, although at war with each other, still
concurring to the same result. This is what occurred in the
fifteenth century.
The popular reform of John Huss was for the instant stifled ;
the war of the Hussites broke forth three or four years after
the death of their master. It lasted long, and was violent, but
the empire finally triumphed. But as the reform of the councils
had failed, as the end which they pursued had not been attained,
the popular reform ceased not to ferment. It watched the first
opportunity, and found it at the commencement of the sixteenth
century. If the reform undertaken by the councils had been
well carried out, the reformation might have been prevented.
But one or the other must have succeeded; their coincidence
shows a necessity.
This, then, is the state in which Europe was left by the
fifteenth century with regard to religious matters — an aristo-
cratical reform unsuccessfully attempted, and a popular reform
commenced, stifled, and always ready to reappear. But it was
not to the sphere of religious creeds that the fermentation of the
human mind at this epoch was confined. It was in the course
of the fourteenth century, as you all know, that Greek and
Roman antiquity were, so to speak, restored in Europe. You
know with what eagerness Dante, Petrarch, Boccaccio, and all
their contemporaries sought for the Greek and Latin manu-
174 GUIZOT
scripts, and published and promulgated them, and what noise
and transports the least discovery of this kind excited.
In the midst of this excitement, a school was commenced in
Europe which has played a very much more important part in
the development of the human mind than has generally been at-
tributed to it : this was the classical school. Let me warn you
from attaching the same sense to this word which we give to it
in the present day ; it was then a very different thing from a lit-
erary system or contest. The classical school of that period
was inflamed with admiration, not only for the writings of the
ancients, for Virgil and Homer, but for the whole of ancient
society, for its institutions, opinions and philosophy, as well as
for its literature. It must be confessed that antiquity, under
the heads of politics, philosophy and literature, was far superior
to the Europe of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. It can-
not, therefore, be wondered at that it should exercise so great a
sway, or that for the most part, elevated, active, refined and
fastidious minds should take a disgust at the coarse manners,
confused ideas, and barbarous forms of their own times, and
that they should devote themselves with enthusiasm to the
study, and almost to the worship of a society at once more reg-
ular and developed. Thus was formed that school of free-
thinkers which appeared at the commencement of the fifteenth
century, and in which prelates, jurisconsults and scholars met
together.
Amid this excitement happened the taking of Constantinople
by the Turks, the fall of the Eastern Empire, and the flight into
Italy of the Greek fugitives. They brought with them a higher
knowledge of antiquity, numerous manuscripts, and a thou-
sand new means of studying ancient civilization. The re-
doubled admiration and ardor with which the classical school
was animated may easily be imagined. This was the time of
the most brilliant development of the high clergy, particularly
in Italy, not as regards political power, properly speaking, but
in point of luxury and wealth ; they abandoned themselves with
pride to all the pleasures of a voluptuous, indolent, elegant and
licentious civilization — to the taste for letters and arts, and for
social and material enjoyments. Look at the kind of life led by
the men who played a great political and literary part at this
epoch — by Cardinal Bembo, for instance ; you will be surprised
at the mixture of sybaritism and intellectual development, of
effeminate manners and hardihood of mind. one would think,
indeed, when we glance over this epoch, when we are present
at the spectacle of its ideas and the state of its moral relations,
one would think we were living in France in the midst of the
eighteenth century. There is the same taste for intellectual ex-
citement, for new ideas, for an easy, agreeable life ; the same
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 175
effeminateness and licentiousness ; the same deficiency in politi-
cal energy and moral faith, with a singular sincerity and activity
of mind. The literati of the fifteenth century were, with regard
to the prelates of the high church, in the same relation as men of
letters and philosophers of the eighteenth century with the high
aristocracy ; they all had the same opinions and the same man-
ners, lived harmoniously together and did not trouble them-
selves about the commotions that were in preparation around
them. The prelates of the fifteenth century, commencing with
Cardinal Bembo, most certainly no more foresaw Luther and
Calvin than the people of the court foresaw the French revo-
lution. The position, however, was analogous.
Three great facts, then, present themselves at this epoch in
the moral order : first, an ecclesiastical reform attempted by the
church herself ; secondly, a popular reHgious reform ; and finally
an intellectual reform, which gave rise to a school of free-think-
ers. And all these metamorphoses were in preparation amid
the greatest political change which had taken place in Europe,
amid the work of centralization of people and governments.
This was not all. This also was the time of the greatest ex-
ternal activity of mankind ; it was a period of voyages, enter-
prises, discoveries and inventions of all kinds. This was the
time of the great expeditions of the Portuguese along the coast
of Africa, of the discovery of the passage of the Cape of Good
Hope by Vasco de Gama, of the discovery of America by Chris-
topher Columbus, and of the wonderful extension of European
commerce. A thousand new inventions came forth ; others al-
ready known, but only within a narrow sphere, became popular
and of common use. Gunpowder changed the system of war,
the compass changed the system of navigation. The art of oil-
painting developed itself and covered Europe with masterpieces
of art: engraving on copper, invented in 1460, multiplied and
promulgated them. Linen paper became common ; and lastly,
from 1436 to 1452, printing was invented ; printing, the theme
of so much declamation and so many commonplaces, but the
merit and effects of which no commonplace nor any declama-
tion can ever exhaust.
You see what was the greatness and activity of this century —
a greatness still only partially apparent, an activity, the results
of which have not yet been fully developed. Violent reforms
seem unsuccessful, governments strengthened and nations paci-
fied. It might be thought that society was preparing to enjoy
a better order of things, amid a more rapid progress. But the
powerful revolutions of the sixteenth century were impending :
the fifteenth had been preparing them. They will be the sub-
ject of my next lecture.
TWELFTH LECTURE.
WE have often deplored the disorder and chaos of Euro-
pean society ; we have complained of the difficulty of
understanding and describing a society thus scat-
tered, incoherent and broken up; we have longed for, and
patiently invoked, the epoch of general interests, order and so-
cial unity. We have now arrived at it ; we are entering upon
the epoch when all is general facts and general ideas, the epoch
of order and unity. We shall here encounter a difficulty of
another kind. Hitherto we have had much trouble in connect-
ing facts with one another, in making them co-ordinate, in per-
ceiving whatever they may possess in common, and distinguish-
ing some completeness. Everything reverses itself in modem
Europe; all the elements and incidents of social life modify
themselves and act and react on one another; the relations of
men among themselves become much more numerous and com-
plicated. It is the same in their relations with the government
of the state, the same in the relations of the states among them-
selves, the same in ideas and in the works of the human mind.
In the times which we have gone through a large number of
facts passed away, isolated, foreign to one another, and without
reciprocal influence. We shall now no longer find this isola-
tion ; all things touch, commingle and modify as they meet. Is
there anything more difficult than to seize the true unity amid
such diversity, to determine the direction of a movement so ex-
tended and complex, to recapitulate this prodigious number of
various elements so clearly connected with one another ; in fine,
to ascertain the general dominant fact, which sums up a long
series of facts, which characterizes an epoch, and is the faithful
expression of its influence and its share in the history of civili-
zation? You will measure with a glance this difficulty in the
great event which now occupies our attention. We encoun-
tered, in the twelfth century, an event which was religious in its
origin if not in its nature ; I mean the crusades. Despite the
greatness of this event, despite its long duration and the va-
riety of incidents to which it led, we found it difficult enough to
distinguish its general character, and to determine with any
precision its unity and its influence. We have now to consider
the religious revolution of the sixteenth century, usually called
176
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 177
the Reformation. Permit me to say, in passing, that I shall use
the word reformation as a simple and understood term, as
synonymous with religious revolution, and without implying any
judgment of it. You see at the very commencement how diffi-
cult it is to recognize the true character of this great crisis, to say
in a general manner what it was and what it effected.
It is between the commencement of the sixteenth and the
middle of the seventeenth century that we must look for the
reformation ; for that period comprises, so to speak, the life of
the event, its origin and end. All historical events, have, so to
speak, a limited career; their consequences are prolonged to
infinity ; they have a hold upon all the past and all the future ; but
it is not the less true that they have a particular and limited exist-
ence, that they are born, that they increase, that they fill with
their development a certain duration of time, and then decrease
and retire from the scene in order to make room for some new
event.
The precise date assigned to the origin of the reformation is
of little importance; we may take the year 1520, when Luther
pubHcly burnt, at Wittemberg, the bull of Leo X, which con-
demned him, and thus formally separated himself from the
Roman church. It was between this epoch and the middle of
the seventeenth century, the year 1648, the date of the treaty of
Westphalia, that the life of the reformation was comprised.
Here is the proof of it. The first and greatest effect of the re-
ligious revolution was to create in Europe two classes of states
— the Catholic states and the Protestant states, to place them op-
posite each other, and open the contest between them. With
many vicissitudes, this struggle lasted from the commencement
of the sixteenth century down to the middle of the seventeenth.
It was by the treaty of Westphalia, in 1648, that the Catholic
and Protestant states at last acknowledged one another ; agreed
to, then, a mutual existence, and promised to live in society and
peace, independently of the diversity of religion. Dating from
1648, diversity in religion ceased to be the dominant principle
of the classification of states, of their external policy, their re-
lations, and alliances. Up to this epoch, in spite of great varia-
tions, Europe was essentially divided into a Catholic and a
Protestant league. After the treaty of Westphalia, this dis-
tinction vanished ; states were either allied or divided upon other
considerations than religious creeds. At that point, then, the
preponderance, that is to say, the career, of the reformation
stopped, although its consequences did not then cease to de-
velop themselves. Let us now glance hastily over this career ;
and without doing more than naming the events and men, let
us indicate what it contains. You will see by this mere indica-
tion, by this dry and incomplete nomenclature, what must be
12
178 GUIZOT
the difficulty of recapitulating a series of facts so varied and so
complex — of recapitulating them, I say, in one general fact ; of
determining what was the true character of the religious revolu-
tion of the sixteenth century, and of assigning its part in the his-
tory of our civilization. At the moment when the reformation
broke forth, it fell, so to speak, into the midst of a great political
event, the struggle between Francis I and Charles V, between
France and Spain; a contest, first for the possession of Italy,
afterward for that of the empire of Germany, and, lastly, for the
preponderance in Europe. It was then the house of Austria
elevated itself, and became dominant in Europe. It was then,
also, that England, under Henry VIII, interfered in continental
politics with more regularity, permanence, and to a greater ex-
tent that she had hitherto done.
Let us follow the course of the sixteenth century in France.
It was filled by the great religious wars of the Protestants and
Catholics, the means and the occasion of a new attempt of the
great lords to regain the power they had lost. This is the politi-
cal purport of our religious wars, of the League, of the struggle
of the Guises against the Valois, a struggle which ended by the
accession of Henry IV.
In Spain, during the reign of Philip II, the revolution of the
United Provinces broke out. The inquisition and civil and re-
ligious liberty waged war under the names of the Duke of Alva
and the Prince of Orange. While liberty triumphed in Holland
by force of perseverance and good sense, she perished in the in-
terior of Spain, where absolute power prevailed, both lay and
ecclesiastical.
In England, during this period, Mary and Elizabeth reigned ;
there was the contest of Elizabeth, the head of Protestantism,
against Philip II. This period is also marked by the accession
of James Stuart to the throne of England, and by the com-
mencement of the great quarrels between royalty and the Eng-
lish people.
About the same time new powers were created in the north.
Sweden was reinstated by Gustavus Vasa in 1523. Prussia
was created by the secularizing of the Teutonic Order. The
powers of the north then took in European politics a place
which they had never hitherto occupied, the importance of
which was soon to be shown in the Thirty Years' War.
I return to France. The reign of Louis XIII ; Cardinal
Richelieu changed the internal administration of France, en-
tered into relations with Germany, and lent aid to the Protestant
party. In Germany, during the last part of the sixteenth cen-
tury, the contest took place against the Turks ; and at the com-
mencement of the seventeenth century the Thirty Years' War,
the greatest event of modern Eastern Europe. At this time
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 179
flourished Gustavus Adolphus, Wallenstein, Tilly, the Duke of
Brunswick and the Duke of Weimar, the greatest names that
Germany has yet to pronounce.
At the same epoch, in France, Louis XIV ascended the
throne; the Fronde commenced. In England, the revolution
which dethroned Charles I broke out.
I only take the leading events of history, events whose name
every one knows; you see their number, variety and impor-
tance. If we seek events of another nature, events which are
less apparent, and which are less summed up in names, we shall
find this epoch equally full. This is the period of the greatest
changes in the political institutions of almost all nations, the
time when pure monarchy prevailed in the majority of great
states, while in Holland the most powerful republic in Europe
was created, and in England constitutional monarchy tri-
umphed definitively, or nearly so. In the church, this was the
period when the ancient monastic orders lost almost all political
power, and were replaced by a new order of another character,
and the importance of which, perhaps erroneously, is held as far
superior to theirs, the Jesuits. At this epoch the council of
Trent effaced what might still remain of the influence of the
councils of Constance and Basle, and secured the definitive tri-
umph of the court of Rome in the ecclesiastical order. Let us
leave the church and cast an eye upon philosophy, upon the free
career of the human mind ; two men present themselves, Bacon
and Descartes, the authors of the greatest philosophical revolu-
tion which the modern world has undergone, the chiefs of the
two schools which disputed its empire. This also was the
period of the brilliancy of Italian literature, and of the com-
mencement of French and of English literature. And lastly, it
was the time of the foundation of great colonies and the most
active developments of the commercial system. Thus, under
whatever point of view you consider this epoch, its political,
ecclesiastical, philosophical and literary events are in great num-
ber, and more varied and important than in any century preced-
ing it. The activity of the human mind manifested itself in
every way : in the relations of men between themselves, in their
relations with power, in the relations of states, and in purely in-
tellectual labors ; in a word, it was a time for great men and for
great things. And in the midst of this period, the religious rev-
olution which occupies our attention is the greatest event of all ;
it is the dominant fact of this epoch, the fact which gives to it
its name and determines its character. Among so many power-
ful causes which have played so important a part, the reforma-
tion is the most powerful, that in which all the others ended,
which modified them all, or was by them modified. So that
what we have to do at present is to truly characterize and ac-
i8o GUIZOT
curately sum up the event which in a period of the greatest
events, dominated over all, the cause which effected more than
all others in a time of the most influential causes.
You will easily comprehend the difficulty of reducing facts
so various, so important, and so closely united to a true his-
torical unity. It is, however, necessary to do this. When
events are once consummated, when they have become history,
what are more important, and what man seeks above all things,
are general facts, the connection of causes and effects. These,
so to speak, are the immortal part of history, that to which all
generations must refer in order to understand the past and to
understand themselves. The necessity for generalization and
rational result is the most powerful and the most glorious of all
intellectual wants ; but we should be careful not to be contented
with incomplete and precipitate generalizations. Nothing can
be more tempting than to give way to the pleasure of assigning
immediately and at the first view, the general character and per-
manent results of an epoch or event. The human mind is like
the will, always urgent for action, impatient of obstacles, and
eager for liberty and conclusions ; it willingly forgets facts
which impede and cramp it ; but in forgetting, it does not de-
stroy them ; they subsist to condemn it some day and convict it
of error. There is but one means for the human mind to escape
this danger ; that is, courageously and patiently to exhaust the
study of facts before generalizing and concluding. Facts are
to the mind what rules of morality are to the will. It is bound
to know them and to bear their weight ; and it is only when it has
fulfilled this duty, when it has viewed and measured their whole
extent, it is then only that it is permitted to unfold its wings and
take flight to the higher region where it will see all things in
their totality and their results. If it attempt to mount too
quickly, and without having gained a knowledge of all the
territory which it will have to contemplate from thence, the
chance of error and failure is very great. It is the same as in an
arithmetical calculation, where one error leads to others, ad
infinitum. So in history, if in the first labor we do not attend to
all the facts, if we give ourselves up to the taste for precipitate
generalization, it is impossible to say to what mistakes we may
be led.
I am warning you in a measure against myself. I have only
made, and, indeed, could only make, attempts at generalization,
general recapitulations of facts which we have not studied
closely and at large. But having arrived at an epoch when this
undertaking is much more difficult than at any other, and when
the chances of error are much greater, I have thought it a duty
thus to warn you. That done, I shall now proceed and attempt
as to the reformation what I have done as to other events; I
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE i8l
shall endeavor to distinguish its dominant fact, to describe its
general character, to say, in a word, what is the place and the
share of this great event in European civiHzation.
You will call to mind how we left Europe at the end of the
fifteenth century. We have seen in its course, two great at-
tempts at religious revolution and reform: an attempt at legal
reform by the councils, and an attempt at revolutionary reform
in Bohemia by the Hussites ; we have seen them stifled and fail-
ing, one after the other ; but still we have seen that it was im-
possible the event should be prevented, that it must be repro-
duced under one form or another ; that what the fifteenth century
had attempted, the sixteenth would inevitably accomplish. I
shall not recount in any way the details of the religious revolu-
tion of the sixteenth century : I take it for granted that they are
almost universally known. I attend only to its general influence
upon the destinies of the human race.
When the causes which determined this great event have
been investigated, the adversaries of the reformation have im-
puted it to accidents, to misfortunes in the course of civilization ;
for example, to the sale of indulgences having been confided to
the Dominicans, which made theAugustines jealous; Luther was
an Augustine, and, therefore, was the determining cause of the
reformation. Others have attributed it to the ambition of sov-
ereigns, to their rivalry with the ecclesiastical power, and to the
cupidity of the lay nobles, who wished to seize upon the prop-
erty of the church. They have thus sought to explain the re-
ligious revolution merely from the ill side of men and human
affairs, by suggestions of private interests and personal pas-
sions.
on the other hand, the partisans and friends of the reforma-
tion have endeavored to explain it merely by the necessity for
reform in the existing abuses of the church ; they have repre-
sented it as a redressing of religious grievances, as an attempt
conceived and executed with the sole design of reconstituting
a pure and primitive church. Neither of these explanations
seems to me sound. The second has more truth in it than the
first; at least it is more noble, more in unison with the extent
and importance of the event ; still I do not think it correct. In
my opinion, the reformation was neither an accident, the result
of some great chance, of personal interest, nor a mere aim at
religious amelioration, the fruit of an Utopia of humanity and
truth. It had a far more powerful cause than all this, and
which dominates over all particular causes. It was a great
movement of the liberty of the human mind, a new necessity
for freely thinking and judging on its own account, and with its
own powers, of facts and ideas which hitherto Europe had re-
ceived, or was held bound to receive, from the hands of authority.
i82 GUIZOT
It was a grand attempt at the enfranchisement of the human
mind ; and to call things by their proper names, an insurrection
of the human mind against absolute power in the spiritual order.
Such I believe to be the true, general and dominant character of
the reformation.
When we consider the state at this epoch, of the human
mind on the one hand, and on the other that of the church which
governed the human mind, we are struck by this twofold fact :
on the part of the human mind there was much more activity,
and much more thirst for development and empire than it had
ever felt. This new activity was the result of various causes,
but which had been accumulating for ages. For example, there
had been ages when heresies took birth, occupied some space of
time, fell, and were replaced by others ; and ages when philo-
sophical opinions had run the same course as the heresies. The
labor of the human mind, whether in the religious or in the
philosophical sphere, had accumulated from the eleventh to the
sixteenth century: and at last the moment had arrived when
it was necessary that the result should appear. Moreover, all
the means of instruction created or encouraged in the very
bosom of the church bore their fruits. Schools had been in-
stituted : from these schools had issued men with some knowl-
edge, and their number was daily augmented. These men
wished at last to think for themselves, and on their own ac-
count, for they felt stronger than they had ever yet done.
Finally arrived that renewal and regeneration of the human
mind by the restoration of antiquity, the progress and effects of
which I have described to you.
The union of all these causes at the commencement of the
sixteenth century, impressed upon the mind a highly energetic
movement, an imperative necessity for progress.
The situation of the government of the human mind, the
spiritual power, was quite different; it, on the contrary, had
fallen into a state of indolence and immobility. The political
credit of the church, of the court of Rome, had much dimin-
ished ; European society no longer belonged to it ; it had passed
into the dominion of lay governments. Still the spiritual
power preserved all its pretensions, all its splendor and external
importance. It happened with it as it has more than once done
with old governments. The greater part of the complaints
urged against it were no longer applied. It is not true that the
court of Rome in the sixteenth century was very tyrannical ; nor
is it true that its abuses, properly so called, were more numer-
ous or more crying than they had been in other times. on the
contrary, perhaps ecclesiastical government had never been
more easy and tolerant, more disposed to let all things take
their course, provided they did not put itself in question, pro-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 183
vided it was so far acknowledged as to be left in the enjoyment
of the rights which it had hitherto possessed, that it was secured
the same existence and paid the same tributes. It would will-
ingly have left the human mind in tranquillity if the human mind
would have done the same toward it. But it is precisely when
governments are least held in consideration, when they are the
least powerful, and do the least evil that they are attacked, be-
cause then they can be attacked, and formerly they could not be.
It is evident, then, by the mere examination of the state of the
human mind, and that of its government at this epoch, that the
character of the reformation must have been a new impulse of
liberty, a great insurrection of the human intellect. Do not
doubt but this was the dominant cause, the cause which rose
above all the others — a cause superior to all interests, whether
of nations or sovereigns — superior also to any mere necessity
for reform, or the necessity for redressing of grievances which
were then complained of.
I will suppose that after the first years of the reformation,
when it had displayed all its pretensions, set forth all its griev-
ances, the spiritual power had suddenly fallen in with its views,
and had said, "Well, so be it. I will reform everything ; I will
return to a more legal and religious order ; I will suppress all
vexations, arbitrariness and tributes ; even in doctrinal matters,
I will modify, explain, and return to the primitive meaning. But
when all grievances are thus redressed, I will preserve my posi-
tion — I will be as formerly, the government of the human mind,
with the same power and the same rights." Do you suppose
that on these conditions the religious revolution would have
been content, and would have stopped its progress ? I do not
think it. I firmly believe that it would have continued its
career, and that after having demanded reformation, it would
have demanded liberty. The crisis of the sixteenth century
was not merely a reforming one, it was essentially revolutionary.
It is impossible to take from it this character, its merits and its
vices ; it had all the effects of this character.
Let us cast a glance upon the destinies of the reformation;
let us see, especially and before all, what it effected in the differ-
ent countries where it was developed. Observe that it was de-
veloped in very various situations, and amid very unequal
chances. If we find that In spite of the diversity of situations,
and the inequality of chances, it everywhere pursued a
certain end, obtained a certain result, and preserved a certain
character, it will be evident that this character, which sur-
mounted all diversities of situation, and all unequalities of
chances, must have been the fundamental character of the
event — that this result must have been its essential aim.
Well, wherever the religious revolution of the sixteenth cen-
i84 GUIZOT
tury prevailed, if it did not effect the entire enfranchisement of
the human mind, it procured for it new and very great increase
of Hberty. It doubtless often left the mind to all the chances of
the liberty or servitude of political institution ; but it abolished
or disarmed the spiritual power, the systematic and formidable
government of thought. This is the result which the reforma-
tion attained amid the most various combinations. In Ger-
many there was no political liberty; nor did the reformation
introduce it. It fortified rather than weakened the power of
princes. It was more against the free institutions of the middle
ages than favorable to their development. Nevertheless, it re-
suscitated and maintained in Germany a liberty of thought
greater, perhaps, than anywhere else.
In Denmark, a country where absolute power dominated,
where it penetrated into the municipal institutions as well as
into the general institutions of the state, there also, by the in-
fluence of the reformation, thought was enfranchised and freely
exercised in all directions.
In Holland, in the midst of a republic, and in England, under
constitutional monarchy, and despite a religious tyranny of
long duration, the emancipation of the human mind was like-
wise accomplished. And, lastly, in France, in a situation which
seemed the least favorable to the effects of the religious revolu-
tion, in a country where it had been conquered, there even it
was a principle of intellectual independence and liberty. Down
to 1685, that is to say, until the revocation of the edict of Nantes,
the reformation had a legal existence in France. During this
lengthened period it wrote and discussed, and provoked its ad-
versaries to write and discuss with it. This single fact, this
war of pamphlets and conferences between the old and new
opinions, spread in France a liberty far more real and active
than is commonly believed — a liberty which tended to the profit
of science, the honor of the French clergy, as well as to the
profit of thought in general. Take a glance at the conferences
of Bossuet with Claude upon all the religious polemics of that
period, and ask yourselves whether Louis XIV would have
allowed a similar degree of liberty upon any other subject. It
was between the reformation and the opposite party that there
existed the greatest degree of liberty in France during the seven-
teenth century. Religious thought was then far more bold, and
treated questions with more freedom than the political spirit of
Fenelon himself in "Telemachus." This state of things did not
cease until the revocation of the edict of Nantes. Now, from
1685 to the outburst of the human mind in the eighteenth cent-
ury, there were not forty years ; and the influence of the re-
ligious revolution in favor of intellectual liberty had scarcely
ceased when that of the philosophical revolution commenced.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 185
You see that wherever the reformation penetrated, wherever
it played an important part, victorious or vanquished, it had
as a general, dominant and constant result, an immense prog-
ress in the activity and liberty of thought, and toward the eman-
cipation of the human mind.
And not only had the reformation this result, but with this
it was satisfied ; wherever it obtained that, it sought for nothing
further, so much was it the foundation of the event, its prim-
itive and fundamental character. Thus, in Germany it ac-
cepted, I will not say political servitude, but, at least, the ab-
sence of liberty. In England it consented to the constitutional
hierarchy of the clergy and the presence of a church with quite
as many abuses as there had ever been in the Romish church,
and far more servile.
Why should the reformation, so passionate and stubborn in
some respects, show itself in this so easy and pliant? It was
because it had obtained the general fact to which it tended, the
abolition of spiritual power, the enfranchisement of the human
mind. I repeat, that wherever it attained this end, it accom-
modated itself to all systems and all situations.
Let us now take the counter-proof of this inquiry ; let us see
what happened in countries into which the religious revolution
had not penetrated, where it had been stifled in the beginning,
where it had never been developed. History shows that there
the human mind has not been enfranchised ; two great countries,
Spain and Italy, will prove this. While in those European
countries where the reformation had taken an important place,
the human mind, during the three last centuries, has gained an
activity and a freedom before unknown ; in those where it has
not penetrated, it has fallen, during the same period, into ef-
feminacy and indolence; so that the proof and counter-proof
have been made, so to speak, simultaneously, and given the
same result.
Impulse of thought and the abolition of absolute power in
the spiritual order, are therefore the essential character of the
reformation, the most general result of its influence and the
dominant fact of its destiny.
I designedly say, the fact. The emancipation of the human
mind was in reality, in the course of the reformation, a fact
rather than a principle, a result rather than an intention. In
this respect I think the reformation executed more than it had
undertaken; more perhaps than it had even desired. Con-
trary to most other revolutions, which have remained far be-
hind their wishes, of which the event is far inferior to the
thought, the consequences of the revolution surpassed its views ;
it is greater as an event than as a plan ; what it effected it did
not fully foresee, nor fully avow.
1 86 GUIZOT
What were the reproaches with which its adversaries con-
stantly upbraid the reformation ? Which of its results did they
in a manner cast in its teeth to reduce it to silence ?
Two principal ones. First: The multiplicity of sects, the
prodigious license allowed to mind, the dissolutions of the re-
ligious society as a whole. Second : Tyranny and persecution.
" You provoke Hcense," said they to the reformers ; "you even
produce it ; and when you have created it, you wish to restrain
and repress it. And how do you repress it? By the most
severe and violent means. You yourselves persecute heresy,
and by virtue of an illegitimate authority."
Survey and sum up all the great attacks directed against the
reformation, discarding the purely dogmatical questions ; these
are the two fundamental reproaches to which they reduce them-
selves.
The reformed party was greatly embarrassed by them. When
they imputed it to the multiplicity of sects, instead of avowing
them, and maintaining the legitimacy of their development, it
anathematized them, deplored their existence and denied them.
Taxed with persecution, it defended itself with the same em-
barrassment ; it alleged the necessity ; it had, it said, the right
to repress and punish error, because it was in the possession of
truth ; its creed and institutions alone were legitimate ; and if
the Roman church had not the right to punish the reformers,
it was because she was in the wrong as against them.
And when the reproach of persecution was addressed to the
dominant party in the reformation, not by its enemies, but by
its own offspring, when the sects which it anathematized said
to it, " We only do what you have done ; we only separate our-
selves as you separated yourselves," it was still more embar-
rassed for an answer, and often only replied by redoubled rigor.
In fact, while laboring for the destruction of absolute power
in the spiritual order, the revolution of the sixteenth century
was ignorant of the true principles of intellectual liberty, it en-
franchised the human mind, and yet pretended to govern it by
the law ; in practice it was giving prevalence to free inquiry, and
in theory it was only substituting a legitimate in place of an
illegitimate power. It did not elevate itself to the first cause,
nor descend to the last consequences of its work. Thus it fell
into a double fault; on the one hand, it neither knew nor re-
spected all the rights of human thought ; at the moment that
it clamored for them on its own account, it violated them with
regard to others ; on the other hand, it knew not how to meas^
ure the rights of authority in the intellectual order; I do not
speak of coercive authority, which in such matters should possess
none, but of purely moral authority, acting upon the mind alone,
and simply by way of influence. Something is wanting in most
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 187
of the reformed countries, to the good organization of the intel-
lectual society, and to the regular action of ancient and general
opinions. They could not reconcile the rights and wants of
tradition with those of hberty, and the cause doubtless lay in
this fact, that the reformation did not fully comprehend and
receive its own principles and effects.
Hence, also, it had a certain air of inconsistency and narrow-
mindedness, which often gave a hold and advantage over it to
its adversaries. These last knew perfectly well what they did,
and what they wished to do ; they went back to the principles
of their conduct, and avowed all the consequences of it. There
was never a government more consistent and systematic than
that of the Roman church. In practice the court of Rome has
greatly yielded and given way, much more so than the refor-
mation; in theory, it has much more completely adopted its
peculiar system, and kept to a much more coherent conduct.
This is a great power, this full knowledge of what one does
and wishes, this complete and rational adoption of a doctrine
and a design. The religious revolution of the sixteenth century
presented in its course a striking example of it. Every one
knows that the chief power instituted to struggle against it
was the order of Jesuits. Throw a glance upon their history ;
they have everywhere failed. Wherever they have interfered
to any extent, they have carried misfortune into the cause with
which they mixed. In England they ruined kings; in Spain
the people. The general course of events, the development
of modern civilization, the liberty of the human mind, all these
powers against which the Jesuits were called upon to contest,
fought and conquered them. And not only have they failed,
but call to mind the means they have been obliged to employ.
No splendor or grandeur ; they brought about no great events,
nor put in motion powerful masses of men; they have acted
only by underhanded, obscure and subordinate means ; by ways
which are nothing suited to strike the imagination, to conciliate
that public interest which attaches to great things, whatever
may be their principle or end. The party against which it
struggled, on the contrary, not only conquered, but conquered
with splendor; it did great things, and by great means; it
aroused the people, it gave to Europe great men, and changed,
in the face of day, the fashion and form of states. In a word,
everything was against the Jesuits, both fortune and appear-
ances; neither good sense, which desires success, nor imag-
ination, which requires splendor, were satisfied by their career.
And yet nothing can be more certain than that they have had
grandeur ; that a great idea is attached to their name, their in-
fluence, and their history. How so?
It is because they knew what they were doing, and what they
i88 GUIZOT
desired to do ; because they had a full and clear acquaintance
with the principles upon which they acted, and the aim to which
they tended ; that is to say, they had greatness of thought and
greatness of will, and this saved them from the ridicule which
attaches itself to constant reverses and contemptible means.
Where, on the contrary, the event was greater than the thought,
where the actors appeared to want a knowledge of the first prin-
ciples and last results of their action, there remained something
incomplete, inconsistent and narrow, which placed the conquer-
ors themselves in a sort of rational and philosophical inferiority,
of which the influence has been sometimes felt in events. This
was, I conceive, in the struggle of the old against the new
spiritual order, the weak side of the reformation, the circum-
stance which often embarrassed it, and hindered it from de-
fending itself as it ought to have done.
We might consider the religious revolution of the sixteenth
century under many other aspects. I have said nothing, and
have nothing to say, concerning its dogmas, concerning its
effect on religion, in regard to the relations of the human soul
with God and the eternal future ; but I might exhibit it to you
in the diversity of its relations with the social order, bringing
on, in all directions, results of mighty importance. For in-
stance, it awoke religion amid the laity, and in the world of
the faithful. Up to that time religion had been, so to speak,
the exclusive domain of the clergy, of the ecclesiastical order,
who distributed the fruits but disposed themselves of the tree,
and had almost alone the right to speak of it. The reformation
caused a general circulation of religious creeds ; it opened to
believers the field of faith, which hitherto they had had no right
to enter. It had, at the same time, a second result — it banished,
or nearly banished, religion from politics; it restored the in-
dependence of the temporal power. At the very moment when,
so to speak, religion came again to the possession of the faith-
ful, it quitted the government of society. In the reformed
countries, notwithstanding the diversity of ecclesiastical con-
stitutions, even in England, where that constitution is nearer
to the ancient order of things, the spiritual power no longer
makes any serious pretensions to the direction of the temporal
power.
I might enumerate many other consequences of the reforma-
tion, but I must check myself, and rest content with having
placed before you its principal character, the emancipation of
the human mind, and the abolition of absolute power in the
spiritual order — an abolition which, no doubt, was not com-
plete, but nevertheless formed the greatest step that has, up
to our days, been taken in this direction.
Before concluding, I must pray you to remark the striking
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 189
similarity of destiny which, in the history of modern Europe,
presents itself as existing between the civil and religious so-
cieties, in the revolutions to which they have been subject.
The Christian society, as we saw when I spoke of the church,
began by being a perfectly free society, and formed solely in
virtue of a common creed, without institutions or government,
properly so called, and regulated only by moral powers, vary-
ing according to the necessity of the moment. Civil society
commenced in like manner in Europe, or partially at least, with
bands of barbarians ; a society perfectly free, each one remain-
ing in it because he thought proper, without laws or constituted
powers. At the close of this state, which could not co-exist
with any considerable development, religious society placed
itself under an essentially aristocratic government; it was the
body of the clergy, the bishops, councils and ecclesiastical
aristocracy which governed it. A fact of the same kind hap-
pened in civil society at the termination of barbarism; it was
the lay aristocracy, the lay feudal chiefs, by which it was
governed. Religious society left the aristocratic form to as-
sume that of pure monarchy; that is the meaning of the tri-
umph of the court of Rome over the councils and over the
European ecclesiastical aristocracy. The same revolution ac-
complished itself in civil society; it was by the destruction of
aristocratical power that royalty prevailed and took possession
of the European world. In the sixteenth century, in the bosom
of religious society, an insurrection burst forth against the sys-
tem of pure monarchy, against absolute power in the spiritual
order. This revolution brought on, consecrated, and estab-
lished free inquiry in Europe. In our own days we have seen
the same event occurring in the civil order. Absolute tem-
poral power was attacked and conquered. Thus you have seen
that the two societies have undergone the same vicissitudes,
have been subject to the same revolutions; only religious so-
ciety has always been the foremost in this career.
We are now in possession of one of the great facts of modern
society — namely, free inquiry, the liberty of the human mind.
We have seen that, at the same time, political centralization al-
most everywhere prevailed. In my next lecture I shall treat
of the English revolution — that is to say, of the event in which
free inquiry and pure monarchy, both results of the progress
of civilization, found themselves for the first time in conflict.
THIRTEENTH LECTURE.
YOU have seen that during the sixteenth century all the
elements and features that had belonged to former Eu-
ropean society resolved themselves into two great facts,
free inquiry and the centralization of power. The first pre-
vailed among the clergy, the second among the laity. There
simultaneously triumphed in Europe the emancipation of the
human mind, and the establishment of pure monarchy.
It was scarcely to be expected but that sooner or later a
struggle should arise between these two principles; for they
were contradictory; the one was the overthrow of absolute
power in the spiritual order, the other was its victory in the tem-
poral ; the first paved the way for the decay of the ancient ec-
clesiastical monarchy, the last perfected the ruin of the ancient
feudal and communal liberties. The fact of their advent being
simultaneous arose, as you have seen, from the revolution in re-
ligious society advancing with a more rapid step than that in the
civil society ; the one occurred exactly at the time of the enfran-
chisement of the individual mind, the other not until the mo-
ment of the centralization of universal power under one head.
The coincidence of these two facts, so far from springing out of
their similitude, did not prevent their inconsistency. They
were each advances in the course of civilization, but they
were advances arising from dissimilar situations, and of
a different moral date, if I may be allowed the expression, al-
though contemporary. That they should run against one an-
other before they came to an understanding was inevitable.
Their first collision was in England. In the struggle of
free inquiry, the fruit of the reformation, against the ruin of
political liberty, the fruit of the triumph of pure monarchy;
and in the effort to abolish absolute power, both in the tem-
poral and spiritual orders, we have the purport of the English
revolution, its share in the course of our civilization.
The question arises, why should this struggle take place in
England sooner than elsewhere? Wherefore should the rev-
olutions in the political order have coincided more closely with
those in the moral order in that country than on the continent?
Royalty in England has undergone the same vicissitudes as
on the continent. Under the Tudors it attained to a concen-
190
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 191
tration and energy which it has never known since. It does
not follow that the despotism of the Tudors was more violent,
or that it cost dearer to England than that of their predeces-
sors. I believe that there were at least as many acts of tyranny
and instances of vexation and injustice under the Plantagenets
as under the Tudors, perhaps even more. And I beHeve, like-
wise, that at this era the government of pure monarchy was
more harsh and arbitrary on the continent than in England.
The new feature under the Tudors was that absolute power be-
came systematic ; royalty assumed a primitive and independent
sovereignty; it adopted a style hitherto unknown. The theo-
retical pretensions of Henry VIII, of EHzabeth, of James I,
or of Charles I, are entirely different to those of Edward I or
Edward III ; though the power of these two last kings was
neither less arbitrary nor less extensive. I repeat, that it was
the principle, the rational system of monarchy, rather than its
practical power, which experienced a mutation in England
during the sixteenth century ; royalty assumed absolute power,
and pretended to be superior to all laws, to those even which it
had declared should be respected.
Again, the religious revolution was not accomplished in Eng-
land in the same manner as on the continent ; here it was the
work of the kings themselves. Not but that in this country,
as elsewhere, there had long been the germs of, and even at-
tempts at a popular reformation, which would probably, ere
long, have been carried out. But Henry VIII took the initia-
tive; power became revolutionary. The result was that, in
its origin, at least, as a redress of ecclesiastical tyranny and
abuse, and as the emancipation of the human mind, the refor-
mation was far less complete in England than on the continent.
It consulted, and very naturally, the interest of its authors.
The king and the retained episcopacy shared the riches and
power, the spoils of the preceding government, of the papacy.
It was not long before the consequence was felt. It was said
that the reformation was finished ; yet most of the motives which
had made it necessary still existed. It reappeared under a pop-
ular form ; it exclaimed against the bishops as it had done
against the court of Rome ; it accused them of being so many
popes. As often as the general character of the religious
reformation was compromised, whenever there was a question
of a struggle with the ancient church, all portions of the re-
formed party rallied and made head against the common
enemy; but the danger passed, the interior struggle recom-
menced ; popular reform again attacked regal and aristocratical
reform, denounced its abuses, complained of its tyranny, called
upon it for a fulfillment of its promises, and not again to estab-
lish the power which it had dethroned.
192
GUIZOT
There was, about the same time, a movement of enfranchise-
ment manifested in civil society, a need for political freedom, till
then unknown, or at least powerless. During the sixteenth
century the commercial prosperity of England increased with
excessive rapidity; at the same time territorial wealth, landed
property, in a great measure changed hands. The division of
land in England in the sixteenth century, consequent on the
ruin of the feudal aristocracy and other causes, too many for
present enumeration, is a fact deserving more attention than has
yet been given to it. All documents show us the number of
landed proprietors increasing to an immense extent, and the
larger portion of the lands passing into the hands of the gentry,
or inferior nobility, and the citizens. The upper house, the
higher nobility, was not nearly so rich at the commencement of
the seventeenth century as the House of Commons. There was
then at the same time a great development of commercial wealth,
and a great mutation in landed property. Amid these two in-
fluences came a third — the new movement in the minds of men.
The reign of Elizabeth is, perhaps, the greatest period of Eng-
lish history for literary and philosophical activity, the era of
lofty and fertile imaginations; the Puritans without hesitation
followed out all the consequences of a vigorous although nar-
row doctrine ; the opposite class of minds, less moral and more
free, strangers to any principle or method, received with en-
thusiasm everything which promised to satisfy their curiosity
or feed their excitement. Wherever the impulse of intelligence
brings with it a lively pleasure, liberty will soon become a want,
and will quickly pass from the public mind into the government.
There was on the Continent, in some of those countries where
the reformation had gone forth, a manifestation of a similar
feeling, a certain want of political liberty; but the means of
satisfying it were wanting ; they knew not where to look for it ;
no aid for it could be found either in the institutions or in man-
ners; they remained vague and uncertain, seeking in vain to
satisfy their want. In England, it was very different : there the
spirit of political freedom, which reappeared in the sixteenth
century, following the reformation, found its fulcrum and the
means of action in the ancient institutions and social conditions.
Every one knows the origin of the free institutions of Eng-
land ; it is universally known how the union of the great barons
in 12 1 5 forced Magna Charta from King John. What is not so
generally known is that the great charter was from time to
time recalled and again confirmed by most of the succeeding
kings. There were more than thirty confirmations of it be-
tween the thirteenth and the sixteenth centuries. And not only
was the charter confirmed, but new statutes were introduced
for the purpose of maintaining and developing it. It therefore
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 193
lived, as it were, without interval or interruption. At the same
time, the House of Commons was formed, and took its place
among the supreme institutions of the country. It was under
the Plantagenets that it truly struck root ; not that it took any
great part in the state during that period ; the government did
not, properly speaking, belong to it even in the way of influ-
ence ; it only interfered therein at the call of the king, and then
always reluctantly and hesitatingly, as if it was more fearful of
engaging and compromising itself than desirous of augment-
ing its power. But when the matter in hand was the defence of
private rights, the families of fortunes of the citizens, in a word,
the liberties of the individual, the House of Commons acquitted
itself of its duty with much energy and perseverance, and
founded all those principles which have become the basis of the
English constitution.
After the Plantagenets, and especially under the Tudors, the
House of Commons, or rather the entire Parliament, presented
itself under a different aspect. It no longer defended the in-
dividual liberties, as under the Plantagenets. Arbitrary deten-
tions, the violation of private rights, now become much more
frequent, are often passed over in silence. on the other hand,
the Parliament took a much more active part in the general gov-
ernment of the state.
In changing the religion, and in regulating the order of suc-
cession, Henry VIII had need of some medium, some public
instrument, and in this want he was supplied by the Parliament,
and especially by the House of Commons. Under the Planta-
genets it had been an instrument of resistance, the guardian of
private rights; under the Tudors it became an instrument of
government and general policy ; so that at the end of the six-
teenth century, although it had undergone almost every species
of tyranny, its importance was much augmented, its great
power began, that power upon which the representative gov-
ernment depends.
When we glance at the state of the free institutions of Eng-
land at the end of the sixteenth century, we find first, funda-
mental rules and principles of liberty, of which neither the
country nor the legislature had ever lost sight ; second, prece-
dents, examples of liberty, a good deal mixed, it is true, with
inconsistent examples and precedents, but sufficing to legalize
and sustain the claims, and to support the defenders of liberty
in any struggle against tyranny or despotism ; third, special and
local institutions, replete with germs of liberty; the jury, the
right of assembling, and of being armed ; the independence of
municipal administrations and jurisdictions; fourth, and last,
the Parliament and its power, of which the crown had more need
than ever, since it had lavished away the greater part of its in-
13
194
GUIZOT
dependent revenues, domains, feudal rights, etc., and was de-
pendent for its very support upon the national vote.
The political condition of England, therefore, in the six-
teenth century was wholly different from that of the continent.
In spite of the tyranny of the Tudors, and the systematic tri-
umph of pure monarchy, there was still a fixed fulcrum, a sure
means of action for the new spirit of liberty.
There were, then, two national wants in England at this
period: on one side was the need of religious revolution and
liberty in the heart of the reformation already commenced ; and
on thfe other, was required political liberty in the heart of the
pure monarchy then in progress ; and in the course of their
progress these two wants were able to invoke all that had al-
ready been done in either direction. They combined. The
party who wished to pursue religious reformation invoked polit-
ical liberty to the assistance of its faith and conscience against
the king and the bishops. The friends of political liberty again
sought the aid of the popular reformation. The two parties
united to struggle against absolute power in the temporal and
in the spiritual orders, a power now concentrated in the hands
of the king. This is the origin and purport of the English revo-
lution.
It was thus essentially devoted to the defence or achievement
of liberty. For the religious party it was a means, and for the
political party an end ; but with both liberty was the question,
and they were obliged to pursue it in common. There was no
real religious quarrel between the Episcopal and Puritan party ;
little dispute upon dogmas, or concerning faith ; not but there
existed real differences of opinion between them, differences of
great importance ; but this was not the principal point. Prac-
tical liberty was what the Puritans wished to force from the
Episcopal party: it was for this that they strove. There was
also another religious party who had to found a system, to es-
tablish its dogmas, ecclesiastical constitution, and discipline;
this was the Presbyterian party : but although it worked to the
utmost of its power, it did not in this point progress in propor-
tion to its desire. Placed on the defensive, oppressed by the
bishops, unable to act without the assent of the political re-
formers, its allies and chief supporters, its dominant aim was
liberty, the general interest and common aim of all the parties,
whatever their diversity, who concurred in the movement.
Taking everything together, the English revolution was essen-
tially political ; it was brought about in the midst of a religious
people and in a religious age ; religious thoughts and passions
were its instruments ; but its chief design and definite aim were
political, were devoted to liberty, and the abolition of all abso-
lute power.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 195
I shall now glance at the different phases of this revolution
and its great parties ; I shall then connect it with the general
course of European civilization ; I shall mark its place and in-
fluence therein ; and show you by a detail of the facts, as at the
first view, that it was the first blow which had been struck in
the cause of free inquiry and pure monarchy, the first manifes-
tation of a struggle between these two great powers.
Three principal parties sprung up in this great crisis, three
revolutions in a manner were comprised in it, and successively
appeared upon the scene. In each party, and in each revolu-
tion, two parties are allied, and work conjointly, a political and
a religious party ; the first at the head, the second followed, but
each necessary to the other; so that the twofold character of
the event is impressed upon all its phases.
The first party which appeared was the party of legal reform,
under whose banner all the others at first ranged themselves.
When the English revolution commenced, when the Long Par-
liament was assembled in 1640, it was universally said, and by
many sincerely believed, that the legal reform would suffice for
all things ; that in the ancient laws and customs of the country
there was that which would remedy all abuses, and which would
re-establish a system of government entirely conformable to the
public wishes. This party loudly censured and sincerely wished
to prevent the illegal collecting of taxes, arbitrary imprison-
ments, in a word, all acts disallowed by the known laws of the
country. At the root of its ideas was the belief in the king's
sovereignty — that is, in absolute power. A secret instinct
warned it, indeed, that there was something false and dangerous
therein; it wished, therefore, to say nothing of it; pushed to
the extremity, however, and forced to explain itself, it admitted
in royalty a power superior to all human origin, and
above all control, and, when need was, defended it. It be-
lieved at the same time that this sovereignty, absolute in
theory, was bound to observe certain forms and rules ; that it
could not extend beyond certain limits ; and these rules, forms,
and limits were sufficiently established and guaranteed in the
great charter, in the confirmatory statutes, and in the ancient
laws of the country. Such was its political idea. In religious
matters, the legal party thought that the Episcopal power was
excessive ; that the bishops had too much political power, that
their jurisdiction was too extensive, and that it was necessary to
overlook and restrain its exercise. Still, it firmly supported the
episcopacy, not only as an ecclesiastical institution, and as a sys-
tem of church government, but as a necessary support for the
royal prerogative, as a means of defending and maintaining the
supremacy of the king in religious matters. The sovereignty
of the king in the political order being exercised according to
196 GUIZOT
known forms, and within the limits of acknowledged rules, roy-
alty in the religious order should be sustained by the episcopacy ;
such was the twofold system of the legal party, of which the
chiefs were Clarendon, Colepepper, Lord Capel, and Lord Falk-
land himself, although an ardent advocate of public liberty, and
a man who numbered in his ranks almost all the high nobility
who were not servilely devoted to the court.
Behind these followed a second party, which I shall call the
party of the political revolution ; these were of opinion that the
ancient guarantees and legal barriers had been and still were in-
sufficient ; that a great change, a regular revolution was neces-
sary, not in the forms, but in the realities of government : that
it was necessary to withdraw from the king and his counsel the
independence of their power, and to place the political prepon-
derance in the House of Commons ; that the government, prop-
erly so called, should belong to this assembly and its chiefs. This
party did not give an account of their ideas and intentions as
clearly and systematically as I have done ; but this was the es-
sence of its doctrines, of its political tendencies. Instead of the
sovereignty of the king, pure monarchy, it believed in the sover-
eignty of the House of Commons as the representative of the
country. Under this idea was hidden that of the sovereignty of
the people, an idea, the bearing of which and its consequences,
the party was very far from contemplating, but which presented
itself, and was received under the form of the sovereignty of the
House of Commons.
A religious party, that of the Presbyterians, was closely united
with the party of the political revolution. The Presbyterians
wished to bring about in the church a revolution analogous to
that meditated by their allies in the state. They wished to gov-
ern the church by assemblies, giving the religious power to an
hierarchy of assemblages agreeing one with the other, as their
allies had invested the House of Commons with the political
power. But the Presbyterian revolution was more vigorous
and complete, for it tended to change the form as well as the prin-
ciple of the government of the church, while the political party
wished only to moderate the influences and preponderating
power of institutions, and did not meditate an overthrow of the
form of the institutions themselves.
But the chiefs of the political party were not all of them favor-
able to the Presbyterian organization of the church. Many of
them, as for instance, Hampden and Holies, would have pre-
ferred, it seems, a moderate episcopacy, confined to purely ec-
clesiastical duties, and more freedom of conscience. But they
resigned themselves to it, being unable to do without their fanat-
ical allies.
A third party was yet more exorbitant in its demands ; this
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 197
party asserted that an entire change was necessary, not only in
the form of government, but in government itself ; that the
whole political constitution was bad. This party repudiated the
past ages of England, renounced the national institutions and
memories, with the intention of founding a new government,
according to a pure theory, or what it supposed to be such. It
was not a mere reform in the government, but a social revolu-
tion which this party wished to bring about. The party of which
I just now spoke, that of the political revolution, wished to in-
troduce important changes in the relations between the Parlia-
ment and the crown ; it wished to extend the power of Parlia-
ment, particularly that of the House of Commons, giving them
the nomination to high public offices, and the supreme direction
in general affairs ; but its project of reform extended very little
further than this. For instance, it had no idea of changing the
electoral, judicial or municipal and administrative systems of
the country. The republican party meditated on all these
changes, and proclaimed their necessity ; and, in a word, wished
to reform, not only the public administration, but also the social
relations and the distribution of private rights.
This party, like that which preceded it, was partly religious
and partly political. The political portion included the repub-
licans, properly so called, the theorists, Ludlow, Harrington,
Milton, etc. on that side were ranged the republicans from in-
terest, the chief officers of the army, Ireton, Cromwell, and Lam-
bert, who, more or less sincere at the onset, were soon swayed
and guided by interested views and the necessities of their situa-
tions. Around these collected the religious republican party,
which included all those enthusiasts who acknowledged no legiti-
mate power except that of Jesus Christ, and who, while waiting
for his advent, wished to be governed by his elect. And, lastly,
the party was followed by a large number of inferior free-think-
ers, and fantastical dreamers, the one set in hope of license, the
other of equality of property and universal suffrage.
In 1653, after a struggle of twelve years, all these parties had
successively failed ; at least, they had reason to believe they had
failed, and the public was convinced of their failure. The legal
party, which quickly disappeared, had seen the ancient laws and
constitution disdained and trodden under foot, and innovation
visible upon every side. The party of political reform saw par-
liamentary forms perish under the new use which they wished to
make of them ; they saw the House of Commons, after a sway of
twelve years, reduced by the successive expulsion of the royal-
ists and the Presbyterians to a very trifling number of members,
and those looked upon by the public with contempt and detesta-
tion, and incapable of governing. The republican party seemed
to have succeeded better : it remained, to all appearance, master
198 GUIZOT
of the field of battle, of power ; the House of Commons reckoned
no more than from fifty to sixty members, and all of these were
republicans. They might fairly deem themselves and declare
themselves masters of the country. But the contrary absolutely
rejected them ; they could nowhere carry their resolutions into
effect ; they exercised no practical influence either over the
army or over the people. There no longer subsisted any social
tie, any social security ; justice was no longer administered, or,
if it was, it was no longer justice, but the arbitrary rendering of
decrees at the dictation of passion, prejudice, party. And not
only was there an entire disappearance of security from the social
relations of men, there was none whatever on the highways,
which were covered with thieves and robbers ; material anarchy,
as well as moral anarchy, manifested itself in every direction, and
the House of Commons and the Republican Council were wholly
incapable of repressing either the one or the other.
The three great parties of the revolution had thus been called
successively to conduct it, to govern the country according to
their knowledge and will, and they had not been able to do
it ; they had all three of them completely failed ; they could do
nothing more. " It was then," says Bossuet, " that a man was
found who left nothing to fortune which he could take from it
by council or foresight ;" an expression full of error, and con-
troverted by all history. Never did man leave more to fortune
than Cromwell ; never has man hazarded more, gone on with
more temerity, without design or aim, but determined to go as
far as fate should carry him. An unlimited ambition, an ad-
mirable faculty of extracting from every day and circumstance
some new means of progress, the art of turning chance to profit,
without pretending to rule it — all these were Cromwell's. It
was with Cromwell, as perhaps it has been with no other man in
his circumstances ; he sufficed for all the most various phases of
the revolution ; he was a man for its first and latest epochs ;
first of all, he was the leader of insurrection, the abettor of an-
archy, the most fiery of the English revolutionists ; afterward
the man for the anti-revolutionary reaction, for the re-establish-
ment of order, and for social organization ; thus performing
singly all the parts which, in the course of revolutions, are divid-
ed among the greatest actors. one can hardly say that Crom-
well was a Mirabeau ; he wanted eloquence, and, although very
active, did not make any show during the first years of the Long
Parliament. But he was successively a Danton and a Bona-
parte. He, more than any others, had contributed to the over-
throw of power ; and he raised it up again because none but he
knew how to assume and manage it ; some one must govern ;
all had failed, and he succeeded. That constituted his title.
once master of the government, this man, whose ambition had
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 199
shown itself so bold and insatiable, who, in his progress had al-
ways driven fortune before him, determined never to stop, now
displayed a good sense, prudence, and knowledge of the possible,
which dominated all his most violent passions. He had, no
doubt, a great love for absolute power and a strong desire to
place the crown on his own head and establish it in his family.
He renounced this last design, the danger of which he saw in
time ; and, as to the absolute power, although, in fact, he exer-
cised it, he always knew that the tendency of his age was against
it ; that the revolution in which he had co-operated and which
he had followed through all its phases, had been directed against
despotism, and that the imperishable desire of England was to
be governed by a parliament and in parliamentary forms. There-
fore, he himself, a despot by inclination and in fact, undertook
to have a parliament and to govern in a parliamentary manner.
He addressed himself unceasingly to all parties ; he endeavored
to form a parliament of reHgious enthusiasts, of republicans, of
Presbyterians, of officers of the army. He attempted all means
to constitute a parliament which could and would co-operate
with him. He tried in vain : all parties, once seated in West-
minster, wished to snatch from him the power which he exer-
cised, and rule in their turn. I do not say that his own interest
and personal passion were not first in his thoughts ; but it is not
therefore the less certain that, if he had abandoned power, he
would have been obliged to take it up again the next day.
Neither Puritans nor royalists, republicans nor officers, none,
besides Cromwell, was in condition to govern with any degree
of order or justice. The proof had been shown. It was impos-
sible to allow the Parliament, that is to say, the parties sitting in
Parliament, to take the empire which they could not keep. Such,
then, was the situation of Cromwell ; he governed according to
a system which he knew very well was not that of the country ;
he exercised a power acknowledged as necessary, but accepted
by no one. No party regarded his dominion as a definitive
government. The royalists, the Presbyterians, the republicans,
the army itself, the party which seemed most devoted to Crom-
well, all were convinced that he was but a transitory master.
At bottom he never reigned over men's minds; he was never
anything but a make-shift, a necessity of the moment. The
protector, the absolute master of England, was all his life
obliged to employ force in order to protect his power ; no party
could govern like him, but no party wished him for governor :
he was constantly attacked by all parties at once.
At his death the republicans alone were in a condition to seize
upon power ; they did so, and succeeded no better than they had
done before. This was not for want of confidence, at least as
regards the fanatics of the party. A pamphlet of Milton, pub-
200 GUIZOT
lished at this period and full of talent and enthusiasm, is entitled,
" A ready and easy way to establish a free commonwealth." You
see what was the blindness of these men. They very soon fell
again into that impossibility of governing which they had already
experienced. Monk undertook the conduct of the event which
all England looked for. The restoration was accomplished.
The restoration of the Stuarts in England was a deeply na-
tional event. It presented itself with the advantages at once of
an ancient government, of a government which rests upon its
traditions, upon the recollections of the country and with the
advantages of a new government, of which no recent trial has
been made and of which the faults and weight have not been ex-
perienced. The ancient monarchy was the only species of gov-
ernment which for the last twenty years had not been despised
for its incapacity and ill-success in the administration of the
country. These two causes rendered the restoration popular ;
it had nothing to oppose it but the remnants of violent parties,
and the public ralHed around it heartily. It was, in the opinion
of the country, the only means of legal government ; that is to
say, of that which the country most ardently desired. This was
also what the restoration promised, and it was careful to present
itself under the aspect of a legal government.
The first royalist party which, at the return of Charles II, un-
dertook the management of affairs was, in fact, the legal party,
represented by its most able chief, the Chancellor Clarendon.
You are aware that, from 1660 to 1667, Clarendon was prime
minister, and the truly predominating influence in England.
Clarendon and his friends reappeared with their ancient system,
the absolute sovereignty of the king, kept within legal limits,
and restrained, in matters of taxation, by Parliament, and in
matters of private rights and individual liberties, by the tribu-
nals ; but possessing, as regards government, properly so called,
an almost complete independence, the most decisive preponder-
ance, to the exclusion, or even against the wishes of the ma-
jority in Parliament, especially in the House of Commons. As
to the rest, they had a due respect for legal order, a sufficient
solicitude for the interests of the country, a noble sentiment of
its dignity, and a grave and honorable moral tone; such was the
character of Clarendon's administration of seven years.
But the fundamental ideas upon which this administra-
tion rested, the absolute sovereignty of the king, and the govern-
ment, placed beyond the influence of the preponderating opinion
of Parliament, these ideas, I say, were obsolete, impotent. In
spite of the reaction of the first moments of the restoration,
twenty years of parliamentary rule, in opposition to royalty, had
irremediably ruined them. A new element soon burst forth in
the center of the royalist party: free-thinkers, rakes and liber-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 201
tines, who participated in the ideas of the time, conceived that
power was vested in the Commons, and caring very httle for
legal order or the absolute sovereignty of the king, troubled
themselves only for their own success, and sought it whenever
they caught a glimpse of any means of influence or power.
These formed a party which became allied with the national dis-
contented party, and Clarendon was overthrown.
Thus arose a new system of government, namely, that of that
portion of the royalist party which I have now described: profli-
gates and libertines formed the ministry, which is called the min-
istry of the Cabal, and many other administrations which suc-
ceeded it. This was their character; no care for principles, laws
or rights; as little for justice and for truth; they sought upon
each occasion to discover the means of succeeding; if success
depended upon the influence of the Commons, they chimed in
with their opinions ; if it seemed expedient to flout the House of
Commons, they did so, and begged its pardon on the morrow.
Corruption was tried one day, flattery of the national spirit,
another; there was no regard paid to the general interests of the
country, to its dignity, or to its honor; in a word, their govern-
ment was profoundly selfish and immoral, a stranger to all pub-
lic doctrine or views ; but at bottom, and in the practical admin-
istration of affairs, very intelligent and liberal. Such was the
character of the Cabal, of the ministry of the Earl of Danby, and
of the entire English government, from 1667 to 1678. Notwith-
standing its immorality, notwithstanding its contempt of the
principles and the true interests of the country, this government
was less odious and less unpopular than the ministry of Claren-
don had been: and why? because it was much better adapted to
the times, and because it better understood the sentiments of the
people, even in mocking them. It was not antiquated and for-
eign to them, like that of Clarendon; and though it did the coun-
try much more harm, the country found it more agreeable.
Nevertheless, there came a moment when corruption, servility
and contempt of rights and public honor were pushed to such
a point that the people could no longer remain resigned. There
was a general rising against the government of the profligates.
A national and patriotic party had formed itself in the bosom of
the House of Commons. The king decided upon calling its
chiefs to the council. Then came to the direction of affairs Lord
Essex, the son of him who had commanded the first parliament-
ary armies during the civil war. Lord Russell, and a man who,
without having any of their virtues, was far superior to them in
political ability. Lord Shaftesbury. Brought thus to the man-
agement of affairs, the national party showed itself incompetent ;
it knew not how to possess itself of the moral force of the country ;
it knew not how to treat the interests either of the king, the court
or of any of those with whom it had to do. It gave to no one ;
202 GUIZOT
neither to the people nor to the king, any great notion of its
abiHty and energy. After remaining a short time in power, it
failed. The virtue of its chiefs, their generous courage, the
nobleness of their deaths, have exalted them in history, and have
justly placed them in the highest rank ; but their political capac-
ity did not answer to their virtue, and they knew not how to
wield the power which could not corrupt them, nor to secure
the triumph of the cause for the sake of which they knew how to
die.
This attempt having failed, you perceive the condition of the
English restoration ; it had, after a manner, and like the revolu-
tion, tried all parties and all ministries, the legal ministry, the
corrupted ministry, and the national ministry, but none had suc-
ceeded. The country and the court found themselves in much
the same situation as that of England in 1653, at the end of the
revolutionary tempest. Recourse was had to the same ex-
pedient; what Cromwell had done for the good of the revolution,
Charles II did for the good of his crown; he entered the career
of absolute power.
James II succeeded his brother. Then a second question was
added to that of absolute power; namely, the question of reli-
gion. James II desired to bring about the triumph of popery
as well as that of despotism. Here, then, as at the beginning of
the revolution, we have a religious and a political warfare, both
directed against the government. It has often been asked, what
would have happened had William III never existed, or had he
not come with his Hollanders to put an end to the quarrel which
had arisen between James II and the English nation? I firmly
believe that the same event would have been accomplished. Ail
England, except a very small party, had rallied, at this epoch,
against James, and, under one form or another, it would have
accomplished the revolution of 1688. But this crisis was pro-
duced by other and higher causes than the internal state of Eng-
land. It was European as well as English. It is here that the
English revolution connects itself by facts themselves, and inde-
pendently of the influence which its example may have had with
the general course of European civilization.
While this struggle, which I have sketched in outline, this
struggle of absolute power against civil and religious liberty,
was taking place in England, a struggle of the same kind was
going on upon the continent, very different, indeed, as regards
the actors, forms and theater, but at bottom the same, and
originated by the same cause. The pure monarchy of Louis
XIV endeavored to become an universal monarchy; at least it
gave reason for the fear that such was the case; and, in fact,
Europe did fear that it was. A league was made in Europe,
between various political parties, in order to resist this attempt,
and the chief of this league was the chief of the party in favor of
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 203
civil and religious liberty upon the continent, William, Prince of
Orange. The Protestant republic of Holland, with William at
its head, undertook to resist the pure monarchy represented and
conducted by Louis XIV. It was not civil and religious liberty
in the interior of the states, but their external independence
which was apparently the question. Louis XIV and his adver-
saries did not imagine that, in fact, they were contesting between
them the question which was being contested in England. This
struggle went on, not between parties, but between states; it pro-
ceeded by war and diplomacy, not by political movements and
by revolutions. But, at bottom, one and the same question was
at issue.
When, therefore, James II resumed in England the contest
between absolute power and liberty, this contest occurred just in
the midst of the general struggle which was going on in Europe
between Louis XIV and the Prince of Orange, the represent-
atives, severally, of the two great systems at war upon the banks
of the Scheldt, as well as on those of the Thames. The league
was so powerful against Louis XIV that, openly, or in a hidden
but very real manner, sovereigns were seen to enter it, who were
assuredly very far from being interested in favor of civil and
religious liberty. The emperor of Germany and Pope Innocent
XI supported William III against Louis XIV. William passed
into England, less in order to serve the internal interests of the
country than to draw it completely into the struggle against
Louis XIV. He took this new kingdom as a new power of
which he was in want, and of which his opponent had, up to that
time, made use against them. While Charles II and James II
reigned, England belonged to Louis XIV; he had directed its
external relations, and had constantly opposed it to Holland.
England was now snatched from the party of pure and universal
monarchy in order to become the instrument and strongest sup-
port of the party of religious liberty. This is the European
aspect of the revolution of 1688; it was thus that it occupied a
place in the total result of the events of Europe, independently of
the part which it played by means of its example, and the influ-
ence which it exercised upon minds in the following century.
Thus you see that, as I told you in the beginning, the true
meaning and essential character of this revolution was the at-
tempt to abolish absolute power in temporal as well as spiritual
things. This act discovers itself in all the phases of the revo-
lution — in its first period up to the restoration, in the second up
to the crisis of 1688 — and whether we consider it in its internal
development or in its relations with Europe in general.
It now remains for us to study the same great event upon the
continent, the struggle of pure monarchy and free inquiry, or,
at least, its causes and approaches. This will be the subject of
our next lecture.
FOURTEENTH LECTURE.
IN my last lecture I endeavored to determine the true char-
acter and political meaning of the English revolution. We
have seen that it was the first shock of the two great facts
to which all the civilization of primitive Europe reduced itself in
the course of the sixteenth century, namely, pure monarchy on
one hand and free inquiry on the other; those two powers came
to strife for the first time in England. Attempts have been made
to infer from this fact the existence of a radical difference
between the social state of England and that of the continent;
some have pretended that no comparison was possible between
countries of destinies so different; they have affirmed that the
English people had existed in a kind of moral isolation analo-
gous to its material situation.
It is true that there had been an important difference between
English civilization and the civilization of the continental
states — a difference which we are bound to calculate. You
have already, in the course of my lectures, been enabled to catch
a glimpse of it. The development of the different principles and
elements of society occurred in England simultaneously, and, as
it were, abreast; at least far more so than upon the continent.
When I attempted to determine the peculiar physiognomy of
European civilization as compared with the ancient and Asiatic
civilizations, I showed you the first, varied, rich and complex;
that it never fell under the dominion of an exclusive principle;
that therein the various elements of the social state were modi-
fied, combined, and struggled with each other, and had been
constantly compelled to agree and live in common. This fact,
the general characteristic of European civilization, has above all
characterized the English civilization; it was in England that
this character developed itself with the most continuity and ob-
viousness ; it was there that the civil and religious orders, aris-
tocracy, democracy, royalty, local and central institutions, moral
and political developments, progressed and increased together,
pell-mell, so to speak, and if not with an equal rapidity, at least
always within a short distance of each other. Under the reign
of the Tudors, for instance, in the midst of the most brilliant
progress of pure monarchy, we see the democratical principle,
the popular power, arising and strengthening itself at the same
204
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 205
time. The revolution of the seventeenth century burst forth ; it
was at the same time reHgious and poHtical. The feudal aristoc-
racy appeared here in a very weakened condition, and with all
the symptoms of decline; nevertheless, it was ever in a position
to preserve a place and play an important part therein, and to
take its share in the results. It is the same with the entire
course of English history : never has any ancient element com-
pletely perished ; never has any new element wholly triumphed,
or any special principle attained to an exclusive preponderance.
There has always been a simultaneous development of different
forces, a compromise between their pretensions and their in-
terests.
Upon the continent the progress of civilization has been much
less complex and complete. The various elements of society —
the religious and civil orders — monarchy, aristocracy and
democracy, have developed themselves, not together and
abreast, but in succession. Each principle, each system has
had, after a certain manner, its turn. Such a century belongs, I
will not say exclusively, which would be saying too much, but
with a very marked preponderance, to feudal aristocracy, for ex-
ample; another belongs to the monarchical principle; a third to
the democratical system.
Compare the French with the English middle ages, the
eleventh, twelfth and thirteenth centuries of our history with
the corresponding centuries beyond the channel; you will find
that at this period in France feudalism was almost absolutely
sovereign, while royalty and the democratical principle were
next to nullities. Look to England: it is, indeed, the feudal
aristocracy which predominates ; but royalty and democracy
were nevertheless powerful and important.
Royalty triumphed in England under Elizabeth, as in France
under Louis XIV; but how many precautions was it obliged to
take ; to how many restrictions — now from the aristocracy, now
from the democracy, did it submit! In England, also, each sys-
tem and each principle has had its day of power and success, but
never so completely, so exclusively as upon the continent; the
conqueror has always been compelled to tolerate the presence
of his rivals, and to allow each his share.
With the differences in the progress of the two civilizations are
connected advantages and disadvantages, which manifest them-
selves, in fact, in the history of the two countries. There can be
no doubt, for instance, but that this simultaneous development
of the different social elements greatly contributed to carry
England, more rapidly than any other of the continental states,
to the final aim of all society — namely, the establishment of a
government at once regular and free. It is precisely the nature
of a government to concern itself for all interests and all powers,
2o6 GUIZOT
to reconcile them, and to induce them to live and prosper in com-
mon ; now, such, beforehand, by the concurrence of a multitude
of causes, was the disposition and relation of the different ele-
ments of English society ; a general and somewhat regular gov-
ernment had therefore less difficulty in becoming constituted
there. So the essence of liberty is the manifestation and simul-
taneous action of all interests, rights, powers and social ele-
ments. England was therefore much nearer to its possessions
than the majority of other states. For the same reasons, na-
tional good sense, the comprehension of public affairs, neces-
sarily formed themselves there more rapidly than elsewhere;
political good sense consists in knowing how to estimate all
facts, to appreciate them, and render to each its share of consid-
eration ; this, in England, was a necessity of the social state, a
natural result of the course of civilization.
on the other hand, in the continental states, each system, each
principle having had its turn, having predominated after a more
complete and more exclusive manner, its development was
wrought upon a larger scale, and with more grandeur and brill-
iancy. Royalty and feudal aristocracy, for instance, came upon
the continental stage with far greater boldness, extension and
freedom. Our political experiments, so to speak, have been
broader and more finished : the result of this has been that politi-
cal ideas (I speak of general ideas, and not of good sense ap-
plied to the conduct of affairs) and political doctrines have risen
higher, and displayed themselves with much more rational
vigor. Each system having, in some measure, presented itself
alone, and having remained a long time upon the stage, men
have been enabled to consider it in its entirety, to mount up to
its first principles, to follow it out into its last consequences, and
fully to unfold its theory. Whoever attentively observes the
English character must be struck with a twofold fact — on the
one hand, with the soundness of its good sense and its practical
ability ; on the other, with its lack of general ideas, and its pride
as to theoretical questions. Whether we open a work upon
English history, upon jurisprudence, or any other subject, it is
rarely that we find the grand reason of things, the fundamental
reason. In all things, and especially in the political sciences,
pure doctrine, philosophy and science, properly so called, have
prospered much better on the continent than in England ; their
flights have, at least, been far more powerful and bold ; and we
cannot doubt but that the different developments of civilization
in the two countries have greatly contributed to this result.
For the rest, whatever we may think of the advantages or dis-
advantages which this difference has entailed, it is a real and
incontestable fact, the fact which most deeply distinguishes
England from the continent. But it does not follow, because
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 207
the different principles and social elements have been there de-
veloped more simultaneously, here more successively, that, at
bottom, the path and the goal have not been one and the same.
Considered in their entirety, the continent and England have
traversed the same grand phases of civilization ; events have, in
either, followed the same course, and the same causes have led
to the same effects. You have been enabled to convince your-
selves of this fact from the picture which I have placed before
you of civilization up to the sixteenth century, and you will
equally recognize it in studying the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries. The development of free inquiry, and that of pure
monarchy, almost simultaneous in England, accomplished
themselves upon the continent at long intervals ; but they did
not accomplish themselves, and the two powers, after having
successively preponderated with splendor, came equally, at last,
to blows. The general path of societies, considering all things,
has thus been the same, and though the points of difference are
real, those of resemblance are more deeply seated. A rapid
sketch of modern times will leave you in no doubt upon this
subject.
Glancing over the history of Europe in the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries, it is impossible not to perceive that France
has advanced at the head of European civilization. At the
beginning of this work I have already insisted upon this fact,
and I have endeavored to point out its cause. We shall now
find it more striking than ever.
The principle of pure monarchy, of absolute royalty, pre-
dominated in Spain under Charles V and Phillip II, before de-
veloping itself in France under Louis XIV. In the same man-
ner the principle of free inquiry had reigned in England in the
seventeenth century, before developing itself in France in the
eighteenth. Nevertheless, pure monarchy and free inquiry
came not from Spain and England to take possession of the
world. The two principles, the two systems remained, in a
manner, confined to the countries in which they had arisen. It
was necessary that they should pass through France in order
that they might extend their conquests ; it was necessary that
pure monarchy and free inquiry should become French in order
to become European. This communicative character of French
civilization, this social genius of France, which has displayed
itself at all periods, was thus more than ever manifest at the
period with which we now occupy ourselves. I will not further
insist upon this fact ; it has been developed to you with as much
reason of brilliancy in other lectures wherein you have been
called upon to observe the influence of French literature and
philosophy in the eighteenth century. You have seen that
philosophic France possessed more authority over Europe, in
20S GUIZOT
regard to liberty, than even free England. You have seen that
French civilization showed itself far more active and contagious
than that of any other country. I need not, therefore, pause
upon the details of this fact, which I mention only in order to
rest upon it any right to confine my picture of modern European
civilization to France alone. Between the civilization of France
and that of the other states of Europe at this period, there have,
no doubt, been differences, which it would have been necessary
to bear in mind, if my present purpose had been a full and faith-
ful exposition of the history of those civilizations ; but I must go
on so rapidly that I am compelled to omit entire nations and
ages, so to speak. I choose rather to concentrate your atten-
tion for a moment upon the course of French civilization, an
image, though imperfect, of the general course of things in
Europe.
The influence of France in Europe during the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries, presents itself under very different
aspects. In the former it was French government that acted
upon Europe and advanced at the head of general civiliza-
tion. In the latter it was no longer to the government, but
France herself, that the preponderance belonged. In the first
case, it was Louis XIV and his court, afterward France and her
opinion, that governed minds and attracted attention. In the
seventeenth century there were peoples who, as peoples, ap-
peared more prominently upon the scene and took a greater
part in events, than the French people. Thus, during the thirty
years' war, the German nation, in the English revolution, the
English people played, in their own destinies, a much greater
part than was played at this period by the French in theirs. So,
also, in the eighteenth century, there were governments
stronger, of greater consideration and more to be dreaded, than
the French government. No doubt Frederick II, Catherine II
and Maria Theresa, had more influence and weight in Europe
than Louis XV; nevertheless, at both periods, it was France
that was at the head of European civilization, placed there first,
by its government, afterward by itself; now by the political
action of its masters, now by its peculiar intellectual develop-
ment.
In order to fully understand the predominant influence in the
course of civilization in France, and therefore in Europe, we
must study, in the seventeenth century, French government, in
the eighteenth, French society. We must change the plan and
the drama according as time alters the stage and the actors.
When we occupy ourselvies with the government of Louis
XIV, when we endeavor to appreciate the causes of his power
and influence in Europe, we scarcely think of anything but his
renown, his conquests, his magnificence and the literary glory
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 209
of his time. It is to external causes that we apply ourselves and
attribute the European preponderance of the French govern-
ment. But I conceive that this preponderance had deeper and
more serious foundations. We must not believe that it was
simply by means of victories, fetes^ or even master-works of
genius, that Louis XIV and his government, at this epoch,
played the part which it is impossible to deny them.
Many of you may remember, and all of you have heard speak
of the effect which the consular government produced in France
twenty-nine years ago, and of the condition in which it found
our country. Without was impending foreign invasion, and
continual disasters were occurring in our armies ; within was an
almost complete dissolution of power and of the people ; there
were no revenues, no public order ; in a word, society was pros-
trate, humiliated and disorganized : such was France on the ad-
vent of the consulate government. Who does not recall the
prodigious and felicitous activity of this government, that ac-
tivity which, in a little time, secured the independence of the
land, revived national honor, reorganized the administration,
remodelled the legislation and, after a manner, regenerated
society under the hand of power.
Well, the government of Louis XIV when it commenced, did
something analogous to this for France ; with great differences
of times, proceedings and forms, it pursued and attained nearly
the same results.
Recall to your memory the state into which France was fallen
after the government of Cardinal Richelieu, and during the
minority of Louis XIV : the Spanish armies always on the fron-
tiers, sometimes in the interior; continual danger of an in-
vasion ; internal dissensions urged to extremity, civil war, the
government weak and discredited at home and abroad. Society
was perhaps in a less violent, but still sufficiently analogous
state to ours, prior to the eighteenth Brumaire. It was from
this state that the government of Louis XIV extricated France.
His first victories had the effect of the victory of Marengo:
they secured the country, and retrieved the national honor. I
am about to consider this government under its principal
aspects — in its wars, in its external relations, in its administra-
tion, and in its legislation ; and you will see, I imagine, that the
comparison of which I speak, and to which I attach no puerile
importance (for I think very little of the value of historical par-
allels), you will see, I say, that this comparison has a real founda-
tion, and that I have a right to employ it.
First of all let us speak of the wars of Louis XIV. The wars
of Europe have originated, as you know, and as I have often
taken occasion to remind you, in great popular movements.
Urged by necessity, caprice, or any other cause, entire popula-
14
310 GUIZOT
tions, sometimes numerous, sometimes in simple bands, have
transported themselves from one territory to another. This
was the general character of European wars until after the cru-
sades, at the end of the thirteenth century.
At that time began a species of wars scarcely less diflferent
from modern wars than the above. These were the distant
wars, undertaken no longer by the people, but by governments,
which went at the head of their armies to seek states and ad-
venturers afar oflf. They quitted their countries, abandoned
their own territories, and plunged, some into Germany, others
into Italy, and others into Africa, with no other motives than
personal caprice. Almost all the wars of the fifteenth and even
of a part of the sixteenth century were of this description. What
interest — I speak not of legitimate interest — but what pos-
sible motive had France that Charles VIII should possess the
kingdom of Naples ? This evidently was a war dictated by no
political consideration : the king conceived that he had a per-
sonal right to the kingdom of Naples, and with a personal aim
and to satisfy his personal desire, he undertook the conquest of
a distant country, which was in no way adapted for annexation
to his kingdom ; which, on the contrary, did nothing but com-
promise his power externally, and internally his repose. It was
the same with the expedition of Charles the Fifth to Africa. The
latest war of this kind was the expedition of Charles XII
against Russia. The wars of Louis XIV had no such character ;
they were the wars of a regular government, fixed in the centre
of its states, and laboring to make conquests around it, to extend
or consolidate its territory ; in a word, they were political wars.
They may have been just or unjust; they may have cost
France too dearly ; there are a thousand reasons which might be
adduced against their morality and their excess ; but they bear a
character incomparably more rational than the antecedent
wars : they were no longer undertaken for whim or adventure ;
they were dictated by some serious motive ; it was some natural
limit that it seemed desirable to attain ; some population speak-
ing the same language that they aimed at annexing ; some point
of defence against a neighboring power, which it was thought
necessary to acquire. No doubt personal ambition had a share
in these wars; but examine one after another of the wars of
Louis XIV, particularly those of the first part of his reign, and
you will find that they had truly political motives ; and that they
were conceived for the interest of France, for obtaining power,
and for the country's safety.
The results are proofs of the fact. France of the present day
is still, in many respects, what the wars of Louis XIV have
made it. The provinces which he conquered, Franche-Comte,
Flanders and Alsace, remain yet incorporated with France.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 211
There are sensible as well as senseless conquests: those of Louis
XIV were of the former species; his enterprises have not the un-
reasonable and capricious character which, up to this time, was
so general; a skilful, if not always just and wise poHcy, presided
over them.
Leaving the wars of Louis XIV, and passing to the consider-
ation of his relations with foreign states, of his diplomacy, prop-
erly so called, I find an analogous result. I have insisted upon
the occurrence of the birth of diplomacy in Europe at the end of
the fifteenth century. I have endeavored to show how the rela-
tions of governments and states between themselves, up to that
time accidental, rare and transitory, became at this period more
regular and enduring, how they took a character of great pub-
lic interest; how, in a word, at the end of the fifteenth, and
during the first half of the sixteenth century, diplomacy came to
play an immense part in events. Nevertheless, up to the seven-
teenth century, it had not been, truly speaking, systematic; it
had not led to long alliances, or to great, and, above all, durable
combinations, directed, according to fixed principles, toward a
constant aim, with that spirit of continuity which is the true
character of established governments. During the course of
the religious revolution, the external relations of states were
almost completely under the power of the religious interest; the
Protestant and CathoHc leagues divided Europe. It was in the
seventeenth century, after the treaty of Westphalia, and under
the influence of the government of Louis XIV, that diplomacy
changed its character. It then escaped from the exclusive in-
fluences of the rehgious principle; alliances and political combi-
nations were formed upon other considerations. At the same
time it became much more systematic, regular, and constantly
directed toward a certain aim, according to permanent prin-
ciples. The regular origin of this system of balance in Europe
belongs to this period. It was under the government of Louis
XIV that the system, together with all the considerations at-
tached to it, truly took possession of European policy. When
we investigate what was the general idea in regard to this sub-
ject, what was the predominating principle of the policy of Louis
XIV, I believe that the following is what we discover:
I have spoken of the great struggle between the pure mon-
achy of Louis XIV, aspiring to become universal monarchy,
and civil and religious liberty, and the independence of states,
under the direction of the Prince of Orange, William III. You
have seen that the great fact of this period was the division of the
powers under these two banners. But this fact was not then
estimated as we estimate it now; it was hidden and unknown
even to those who accompHshed it; the suppression of the
system of pure monarchy and the consecration of civil and re-
3X3 GUIZOT
ligious liberty was, at bottom, the necessary result of the resist-
ance of Holland and its allies to Louis XIV, but the question
was not thus openly enunciated between absolute power and
liberty. It has been often said that the propagation of absolute
power was the predominant principle of the diplomacy of Louis
XIV; but I do not believe it. This consideration played no
very great part in his policy, until latterly, in his old age. The
power of France, its preponderance in Europe, the humbling of
rival powers, in a word, the political interest and strength of the
state, was the aim which Louis XIV constantly pursued,
whether in lighting against Spain, the Emperor of Germany or
England ; he acted far less with a view to the propagation of ab-
solute power than from a desire for the power and aggrandize-
ment of France and of its government. Among many proofs, I
will adduce one which emanates from Louis XIV himself. In
his Memoirs, under the year 1666, if I remember right, we find a
note nearly in these words :
" I have had, this morning, a conversation with Mr. Sidney,
an English gentleman, who maintained to me the possibility of
reanimating the republican party in England. Mr. Sidney
demanded from me, for that purpose, 400,000 livres. I told him
that I could give no more than 200,000. He induced me to
summon from Switzerland another English gentleman named
Ludlow, and to converse with him of the same design."
And, accordingly, we find among the Memoirs of Ludlow,
about the same date, a paragraph to this effect :
" I have received from the French government an invitation
to go to Paris, in order to speak of the affairs of my country ; but
I am distrustful of that government."
And Ludlow remained in Switzerland.
You see that the diminution of the royal power in England
was, at this time, the aim of Louis XIV. He fomented internal
dissensions, and labored to resuscitate the republican party, to
prevent Charles II from becoming too powerful in his country.
During the embassy of Barillon in England the same fact con-
stantly reappears. Whenever the authority of Charles seemed
to obtain the advantage and the national party seemed on the
point of being crushed, the French ambassador directed his in-
fluence to this side, gave money to the chiefs of the opposition,
and fought, in a word, against absolute power, when that
became a means of weakening a rival power to France. When-
ever you attentively consider the conduct of external relations
under Louis XIV, it is with this fact that you will be the most
struck.
You will also be struck with the capacity and skill of French
diplomacy at this period. The names of MM. de Torcy,
d'Avaux, de Bonrepos, are known to all well-informed persons.
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 213
When we compare the despatches, the memoirs, the skill and
conduct of these counsellors of Louis XIV with those of Span-
ish, Portuguese, and German negotiators, we must be struck
with the superiority of the French ministers ; not only as re-
gards their earnest activity and their application to affairs, but
also as regards their liberty of spirit. These courtiers of an
absolute king judged of external events, of parties, of the re-
quirements of liberty, and of popular revolutions, much better
even than the majority of the English ministers themselves at
this period. There was no diplomacy in Europe in the seven-
teenth century which appears equal to the French, except the
Dutch. The ministers of John de Witt and of William of
Orange, those illustrious chiefs of the party of civil and re-
ligious liberty, were the only ministers who seemed in con-
dition to wrestle with the servants of the great and absolute
king.
You see, then, that whether we consider the wars of Louis
XIV, or his diplomatical relations we arrive at the same results.
We can easily conceive that a government, which conducted
its wars and negotiations in this manner, should have assumed
a high standing in Europe, and presented itself therein, not only
as dreadworthy, but as skilful and imposing.
Let us now consider the interior of France, the administra-
tion and legislation of Louis XIV ; we shall there discern new
explanations of the power and splendor of his government.
It is difficult to determine with any degree of precision what
we ought to understand by administration in the government
of a state. Nevertheless, when we endeavor to investigate
this fact, we discover, I believe, that, under the most general
point of view, administration consists in an aggregate of means
destined to propel, as promptly and certainly as possible, the
will of the central power through all parts of society, and to
make the force of society, whether consisting of men or money,
return again, under the same conditions, to the central power.
This, if I mistake not, is the true aim, the predominant charac-
teristic of administration. Accordingly we find that in times
when it is above all things needful to establish unity and order
in society, administration is the chief means of attaining this
end, of bringing together, of cementing, and of uniting inco-
herent and scattered elements. Such, in fact, was the work of
the administration of Louis XIV. Up to this time, there
had been nothing so difficult, in France as in the
rest of Europe, as to eflfect the penetration of the action
of the central power into all parts of society, and to gather
into the bosom of the central power the means of force
existing in society. To this end Louis XIV labored, and
succeeded, up to a certain point ; incomparably better, at least,
214 GUIZOT
than preceding governments had done. I cannot enter into
details : just run over, in thought, all kinds of public services,
taxes, roads, industry, military administration, all the estab-
lishments which belong to whatsoever branch of administra-
tion ; there is scarcely one of which you do not find either the
origin, development, or great amelioration under Louis XIV.
It was as administrators that the greatest men of his time,
Colbert and Louvois, displayed their genius and exercised their
ministry. It was by the excellence of its administration that
his government acquired a generality, decision, and consistency
which were wanting to all the European governments around
him.
Under the legislative point of view this reign presents to you
the same fact. I return to the comparison which I have al-
ready made use of, to the legislative activity of the consular
government, to its prodigious work of revising and generally
recasting the laws. A work of the same nature took place
under Louis XIV. The great ordinances which he promul-
gated, the criminal ordinances, the ordinances of procedure,
commerce, the marine, waters, and woods, are true codes,
which were constructed in the same manner as our codes, dis-
cussed in the council of state, some of them under the presi-
dency of Lamoignon. There are men whose glory consists
in having taken part in this labor and this discussion, M. Pus-
sort, for instance. If we were to consider it in itself, we should
have much to say against the legislation of Louis XIV; it was
full of vices, which now fully declare themselves, and which no
one can deny ; it was not conceived in the interest of true justice
and of liberty, but in the interest of public order, and for giving
more regularity and firmness to the laws. But even that was
a great progress ; and we cannot doubt but that the ordinances
of Louis XIV, so very superior to anything preceding them,
powerfully contributed to advance French society in the career
of civilization.
You see that under whatever point of view we regard this
government, we very soon discover the source of its power and
influence. It was the first government that presented itself to
the eyes of Europe as a power sure of its position, which had
not to dispute its existence with internal enemies — tranquil as
to its dominions and the people, and intent only on governing.
Up to that time all European governments had been unceasing-
ly thrown into wars, which deprived them of security as well as
leisure, or had been so beset with parties and internal enemies
that they were compelled to spend their time in fighting for
their lives. The government of Louis XIV appeared as the
first which applied itself solely to the conduct of affairs, as a
power at once definitive and progressive ; which was not afraid
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 215
of innovating, because it could count upon the future. There
have, in fact, existed very few governments of such an inno-
vating spirit. Compare it with a government of the same
nature, with the pure monarchy of PhiHp II in Spain; it was
more absolute than that of Louis XIV, and yet far less regular
and less tranquil. But how did Philip II succeed in establish-
ing absolute power in Spain? By stifling the activity of the
country, by refusing to it every species of amelioration, by ren-
dering the condition of Spain completely stationary. The gov-
ernment of Louis XIV, on the contrary, showed itself active
in all kinds of innovations, favorable to the progress of letters,
of arts, of riches, and, in a word, of civilization. These are the
true causes of its preponderance in Europe; a preponderance
such that it became upon the continent, during the whole of the
seventeenth century, the type of government, not only for sov-
ereigns, but even for nations.
And now we inquire — and it is impossible to help doing so —
how it happened that a power, thus brilliant, and, judging from
the facts which I have placed before you, thus well established,
so rapidly fell into decline ? How, after having played such a
part in Europe, it became, in the next century, so inconsistent,
weak, and inconsiderable ? The fact is incontestable. In the
seventeenth century the French government was at the head
of European civilization; in the eighteenth century it disap-
peared ; and it was French society, separated from its govern-
ment, often even opposed to it, that now preceded and guided
the European world in its progress.
It is here that we discover the incorrigible evil and the in-
fallible effect of absolute power. I will not go into any detail
concerning the faults of the government of Louis XIV ; he com-
mitted many; I will speak neither of the war of the Spanish
succession, nor of the revocation of the edict of Nantes, nor
of excessive expenses, nor of many other of the fatal measures
that compromised his fortunes. I will take the merits of the;
government as I have described them. I will agree that per-
haps there has never existed an absolute power more fully rec-
ognized by its age and nation, nor one which has rendered more
real services to the civilization of its country and of Europe in
general. But, by the very fact that this government had no
other principle than absolute power, and reposed upon no other
base than this, its decline became sudden and well merited.
What France, under Louis XIV, essentially wanted, was po-
litical institutions and forces, independent, subsisting of them-
selves, and, in a word, capable of spontaneous action and re-
sistance. The ancient French institutions, if they merited that
name, no longer existed : Louis XIV completed their ruin. He
took no care to endeavor to replace them by new institutions ;
2i6 GUIZOT
they would have cramped him, and he did not choose to be
cramped. All that appeared conspicuous at that period was
will, and the action of central power. The government of
Louis XIV was a great fact, a fact powerful and splendid, but
without roots.
Free institutions are a guarantee, not only of the wisdom
of governments, but also of their duration. No system
can endure except by means of institutions. When absolute
power has endured, it has been supported by true in-
stitutions, sometimes by the division of society into strongly
distinct castes, sometimes by a system of religious institutions.
Under the reign of Louis XIV institutions were wanting to
power as well as to Hberty. In France, at this period, nothing
guaranteed either the country against the illegitimate actions
of the government, or the government itself against the inevita-
ble action of time. Thus we see the government helping on
its own decay. It was not Louis XIV alone who was becoming
aged and weak at the end of his reign : it was the whole abso-
lute power. Pure monarchy was as much worn out in 171 2 as
was the monarch himself : and the evil was so much the more
grave, as Louis XIV had abolished political morals as well as
political institutions. There are no political morals without
independence. He alone who feels that he has a strength of
his own is always capable either of serving or opposing power.
Energetic characters disappear with independent situations,
and dignity of soul alone gives birth to security of rights.
This, then, is the state in which Louis XIV left France and
power: a society in full development of riches, power and all
kinds of intellecttial activity; and side by side with this pro-
gressive society, a government essentially stationary, having
no means of renewing itself, of adapting itself to the move-
ment of its people ; devoted, after half a century of the greatest
splendor, to immobility and weakness, and already, during the
life of its founder, fallen into a decline which seemed like disso-
lution. Such was the condition of France at the conclusion
of the seventeenth century, a condition which impressed the
epoch that followed with a direction and a character so dif-
ferent
I need hardly say that the onward impulse of the human
mind, that free inquiry was the predominating feature, the es-
sential fact of the eighteenth century. You have already heard
much concerning this fact from this chair; already you have
heard that powerful epoch characterized by a philosophical ora-
tor, and by that of an eloquent philosopher. I cannot pretend,
in the short space of time which remains to me, to trace all
the phases of the great moral revolution which then accom-
plished itself, I would, nevertheless, fain not leave you with-
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 217
out calling your attention to some characteristics which have
been too little remarked upon.
The first — one which strikes me most, and which I have
already mentioned — is the, so to speak, almost complete dis-
appearance of the government in the course of the eighteenth
century, and the appearance of the human mind as the prin-
cipal and almost the only actor.
Except in that which is connected with external relations un-
der the ministry of the Due de Choiseul, and in certain great
concessions made to the general tendency of opinion, for in-
stance, in the American war; except, I say, in some events of
this nature, perhaps there has scarcely ever been so inactive,
apathetic and inert a government as was the French govern-
ment of this period. Instead of the energetic, ambitious gov-
ernment of Louis XIV which appeared everywhere, and put
itself at the head of everything, you have a government which
labored only to hide itself, to keep itself in the background,
so weak and compromised did it feel itself to be. Activity and
ambition had passed over wholly to the people. It was the
nation which, by its opinion and its intellectual movement,
mingled itself with all things, interfered in all, and, in short,
alone possessed moral authority, which is the only true au-
thority.
A second characteristic which strikes me, in the condition
of the human mind in the eighteenth century, is the universality
of free inquiry. Up to that time, and particularly in the sev-
enteenth century, free inquiry had been exercised within a lim-
ited and partial field; it had had for its object sometimes re-
ligious questions, sometimes religious and political questions
together, but it did not extend its pretensions to all subjects. In
the eighteenth century, on the contrary, the character of free
inquiry is universality ; religion, politics, pure philosophy, man
and society, moral and material nature, all at the same time be-
came the object of study, doubt and system; ancient sciences
were overturned, new sciences were called into existence. The
movement extended itself in all directions, although it had
emanated from one and the same impulse.
This movement, moreover, had a peculiar character; one
which, perhaps, is not to be met elsewhere in the history of
the world ; it was purely speculative. Up to that time, in all
great human revolutions, action had commingled itself with
speculation. Thus, in the sixteenth century, the religious rev-
olution began with ideas, with purely intellectual discussions,
but it very soon terminated in events. The heads of intellec-
tual parties soon became the heads of political parties; the
realities of life were mixed with the labor of the understanding.
Thus, too, it happened in the seventeenth century, in the Eng-
2i8 GUIZOT
lish revolution. But in France, in the eighteenth century, you
find the human spirit exercising itself upon all things, upon
ideas which, connecting themselves with the real interests of
life, seemed calculated to have the most prompt and powerful
influence upon facts. Nevertheless, the leaders and actors of
these great discussions remained strangers to all species of
practical activity — mere spectators, who observed, judged and
spoke, without ever interfering in events. At no other time
has the government of facts, of external realities, been so
completely distinct from the government of minds. The sep-
aration of the spiritual and temporal orders was never com-
pletely real in Europe until the eighteenth century. For the
first time, perhaps, the spiritual order developed itself wholly
apart from the temporal order; an important fact, and one
which exercised a prodigious influence upon the course of
events.
It gave to the ideas of the time a singular character of
ambition and inexperience ; never before had philosophy
aspired so strongly to rule the world, never had philosophy
been so little acquainted with the world. It became obvious
that a day must arrive for coming to facts ; for the intellectual
movement to pass into external events ; and as they had been
totally separated, their meeting was the more difficult, the shock
far more violent.
How can we now be surprised with another character of
the condition of the human mind at this epoch, I mean its pro-
digious boldness? Up to that time its greatest activity had
always been confined by certain barriers ; the mind of man had
always existed amid facts, whereof some inspired it with cau-
tion, and, to a certain extent, checked its movements. In the
eighteenth century, I should be at a loss to say what external
facts the human mind respected, or what external facts exer-
cised any empire over it ; it hated or despised the entire social
state. It concluded, therefore, that it was called upon to re-
form all things ; it came to consider itself a sort of creator ;
institutions, opinions, manners, society, and man himself, all
seemed to require reform, and human reason charged itself
with the enterprise. What audacity equal to this had ever be-
fore been imagined by it !
Such was the power which, in the course of the eighteenth
century, confronted what still remained of the government of
Louis XIV. You perceive that it was impossible to avoid the
occurrence of a shock between these two so unequal forces.
The predominant fact of the English revolution, the struggle
between free inquiry and pure monarchy, was now also to burst
forth in France. No doubt the differences were great, and
these necessarily perpetuated themselves in the results; but,
CIVILIZATION IN EUROPE 219
at bottom, the general conditions were similar, and the defini-
tive event had the same meaning.
I do not pretend to exhibit the infinite consequences of this
struggle. The time for concluding this course of lectures has
arrived ; I must check myself. I merely desire, before leaving
you, to call your attention to the most grave, and, in my opinion,
the most instructive fact which was revealed to us by this great
struggle. This is the danger, the evil, and the insurmountable
vice of absolute power, whatever form, whatever name it may
bear, and toward whatever aim it may direct itself. You have
seen that the government of Louis XIV perished by almost
this cause only. Well, the power which succeeded it, the human
mind, the true sovereign of the eighteenth century, suffered the
same fate ; in its turn, it possessed an almost absolute power ; it,
in its turn, placed an excessive confidence in itself. Its on-
ward impulse was beautiful, good, most useful; and were it
necessary that I should express a definitive opinion, I should
say that the eighteenth century appears to me to have been
one of the greatest ages of history, that which, perhaps, has done
the greatest services for humanity, that which has in the great-
est degree aided its progress, and rendered that progress of the
most general character : were I asked to pronounce upon it as a
public administration, I should pronounce in its favor. But it is
not the less true that, at this epoch, the human mind, possessed
of absolute power, became corrupted and misled by it; hold-
ing established facts and former ideas in an illegitimate disdain
and aversion ; an aversion which carried it into error and tyr-
anny. The share of error and tyranny, indeed, which mingled
itself with the triumph of human reason, at the end of this cen-
tury, a portion which we cannot conceal from ourselves, was
very great and which we must proclaim and not deny; this
portion of error and tyranny was chiefly the result of extrava-
gance into which the mind of man had been thrown, at this
period, by the extension of his power.
It is the duty, and, I believe, it will be the peculiar merit of
our times, to know that all power, whether intellectual or tem-
poral, whether belonging to governments or people, to philos-
ophers or ministers, whether exercising itself in one cause or
in another, bears wathin itself a natural vice, a principle of weak-
ness and of abuse which ought to render it limited. Now
nothing but the general freedom of all rights, all interests and
all opinions, the free manifestation and legal co-existence of all
these forces, can ever restrain each force and each power within
its legitimate limits, prevent it from encroaching on the rest,
and, in a word, cause the real and generally profitable existence
of free inquiry. Herein consists for us the grand lesson of
the struggle which occurred at the end of the eighteenth cen-
2 20 GUIZOT
tury, between absolute temporal power and absolute spiritual
power.
I have now arrived at the term which I proposed to myself.
You remember that my object in commencing this course was
to present you with a general picture of the development of
European civilization, from the fall of the Roman Empire to
our own days. I have traversed this career very rapidly and
without being able to inform you, far from it, of all that was
important, or to bring proofs of all that I have said. I have
been compelled to omit much and often to request you to be-
lieve me upon my word. I hope, nevertheless, that I have at-
tained my aim, which was to mark the grand crisis in the de-
velopment of modern society. Allow me yet one word more.
I endeavored, in the beginning, to define civilization and to
describe the fact which bears this name. Civilization seemed
to me to consist of two principal facts: the development of
human society and that of man himself ; on the one hand, po-
litical and social development ; on the other, internal and moral
development. I have confined myself so far to the history of
society. I have presented civilization only under the social
point of view; and have said nothing of the development of
man himself. I have not endeavored to unfold to you the
history of opinions, of the moral progress of humanity. I pro-
pose, when we meet again, to confine myself especially to
France, to study with you the history of French civilization, to
study it in detail and under its various aspects. I shall en-
deavor to make you acquainted, not only with the history of
society in France, but also with that of man ; to be present with
you at the progress of institutions, of opinions and of intellectual
works of all kinds; and to arrive thus at a complete under-
standing of the development of our glorious country in its
entirety. In the past, as well as in the future, our country may
well lay claim to our tenderest affections.
FOURTEEN DAY USE
RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED
t
LIBRARY USE •
RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED ' °'
LOAN DEPT. L_
THIS BOOK IS DUE BEFORE CLOSING TIME
on I.AST DATE STAMPED BELOW
LiBRAfiyiiSE Jul
REC'DLO JULl
I
©72 3 0-
72 -4 PM 4 5
, LD 62A-30m-2,'69
(J6684gl0)9412A — A-82
3^ """ rary
General Library ilifornia
University of California
Berkeley
/
-D/l:.
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY
.;-.i.
^ii^ #.4t. ^-^^^