Ernst Mach

The Analysis of Sensations

이윤진이카루스 2015. 1. 1. 21:44
UNIVERSITY OF 
ILLINOIS LIBRARY 
AT URBANA-CHAMPA1GN 
BOOKSTACKS 
CENTRAL CIRCULATION BOOKSTACKS 
The person charging this material is re- 
sponsible for its renewal or its return to 
the library from which it was borrowed 
on or before the Latest Date stamped 
below. The Minimum Fee for each Lost 
Book is $50.00. 
Theft, mutilation, and underlining of books are reasons 
for disciplinary action and may result In dismissal from 
the University. 
TO RENEW CALL TELEPHONE CENTER, 333-8400 
UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS LIBRARY AT URBANA-CHAMPAIGN 
FEB 8 1995 
JAN 2 2 1995 
2 9 2003 
When renewing by phone, write new due date below 
previous due date, L162 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
THE 
ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
AND THE RELATION OF THE 
PHYSICAL TO THE PSYCHICAL 
BY 
DR ERNST MACH 
EMERITUS PROFESSOR IN THE UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA 
TRANSLATED FROM THE FIRST GERMAN EDITION 
BY 
C. M. WILLIAMS 
REVISED AND SUPPLEMENTED FROM THE 
FIFTH GERMAN EDITION 
BY 
SYDNEY WATERLOW, M.A. 
CHICAGO AND LONDON 
THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY 
1914 
c ** 
Copyright in Great Britain under the Act of 1911 
TRANSLATOR'S NOTE 
THIS book is not so much a new edition of the 
English translation of Professor Mach's Contri- 
butions to the Analysis of the Sensations^ which was 
published in 1897, 1 but is, as the more comprehensive title 
indicates, an almost entirely new book. The Contributions 
originally appeared in 1886. The English translation of 
1897 contained a certain amount of new matter, most of 
which was embodied by Professor Mach in his second 
edition (1900). Since then there have been three more 
editions : two of them, the third and the fifth, containing 
important changes and additions of such extent that the 
fifth edition, of which this translation is now offered to the 
English-speaking public, is a book nearly twice as long as 
the original English translation. 
It may therefore be convenient to mention here the 
principal respects in which this book differs from the 
translation of 1897. Six chapters are entirely new, 
namely, Chapter III., on "My Relation to Richard 
Avenarius and other Thinkers " ; Chapter V., on " Physics 
and Biology : Causality and Teleology " ; Chapter VIII., on 
" The Will " j Chapter IX., on " Biologico-teleological Con- 
siderations as to Space " ; Chapter XI., on " Sensation, 
1 Contributions to the Analysis of the Sensations, by Dr. Ernst Mach. 
Translated by C. M. Williams. Chicago : Open Court Publishing Co., 
1897- 
5C547B 
vi THE ANAL YSIS OF SENS A TIONS 
Memory and Association," and Chapter XV., on " How my 
Views have been received." Further, the eight chapters of 
the original edition have all been greatly expanded. Chapter 
II. now contains most of the matter which appeared as an 
appendix to the translation of 1897. Chapter VII. contains 
six sections by Dr. Josef Pollak on recent research as to 
the functions of the labyrinth of the ear. 
It will be seen that the changes and additions fall, on 
the whole, into two classes. They are made with the 
object either of amplifying and bringing up to date the 
author's original discussions of points of detail, or of 
explaining and justifying his more general views as to the 
relation between different branches of science and as to 
questions on the borderland between science and philo- 
sophy. It ill becomes a translator to indulge the temptation, 
which he yet must feel, to turn commentator or eulogist ; 
but I may perhaps be allowed to point out the great 
interest attaching to the explanations here given by the 
veteran physicist and philosopher (if Professor Mach will 
allow the word "philosopher") of the way in which his 
views were developed. 
For those parts of the text which are identical with the 
English edition of 1897 I have availed myself largely of 
Miss Williams's excellent translation. Finally, I must add 
that the whole of the present translation has been most 
kindly read, in manuscript, by Professor Mach himself. 
SYDNEY WATERLOW 
28 JOHN STREET, BEDFORD Row, 
LONDON, W.C. 
AUTHOR'S PREFACES 
PREFACE TO THE FIFTH EDITION 
r I A HE text of this edition has been enlarged by a number 
-L of new passages and notes. There is an insertion 
of some length on recent investigations as to the sense of 
orientation ; this is from the pen of Professor Josef Pollak, 
who has also been so kind as to read the proofs of the 
whole book and to correct the index. For all these services 
I owe him my heartiest thanks. A mistake as to Ewald's 
theory of audition has been corrected. I have noted with 
satisfaction that a view of the relation between the physical 
and the psychical, which is almost identical with the view 
advocated here, occurs in a book by Alfred Binet (DAme 
et le Corps, Paris, 1905). 
VIENNA, May 1906 
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION 
THE frequent excursions which I have made into this 
province have all sprung from the profound con- 
viction that the foundations of science as a whole, and of 
vii 
viii THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
physics in particular, await their next greatest elucidations 
from the side of biology, and especially from the analysis 
of the sensations. 
I am aware, of course, that I have succeeded in con- 
tributing but little to the attainment of this end. The very 
fact that my investigations have been carried on, not in 
the way of a profession, but only at odd moments, and 
frequently only after long interruptions, must detract 
considerably from the value of my scattered publications, 
or perhaps even lay me open to the silent reproach of 
desultoriness. So much the more, therefore, am I under 
especial obligations to those investigators, such as E. 
Hering, V. Hensen, W. Preyer and others, who have 
directed attention either to the matter of my writings or to 
my methodological expositions. 
The present compendious and supplementary present- 
ation of my views will, perhaps, place my attitude in a 
somewhat more favorable light, for it will be seen that in 
all cases I have had in mind the same problem, no matter 
how varied or numerous were the single facts investigated. 
Although I can lay no claim whatever to the title of 
physiologist, and still less to that of philosopher, yet I 
venture to hope that the work thus undertaken, purely from 
a strong desire for self-enlightenment, by a physicist 
unconstrained by the conventional barriers of the 
specialist, may not be entirely without value for others 
also, even though I may not be everywhere in the 
right. 
My natural bent for the study of these questions received 
its strongest stimulus twenty-five years ago from Fechner's 
Elemente der Psychophysik (Leipzig, 1860), but my greatest 
A UTHORS PREFA CES ix 
assistance was derived from Bering's solution of the two 
problems referred to on pages 69 and 168. 
To readers who, for any reason, desire to avoid more 
general discussions, I recommend the omission of the 
first and last chapters. For me, however, the conception 
of the whole and the conception of the parts are so 
intimately related that I should scarcely be able to separate 
them. 
PRAGUE, November 1885 
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION 
THIS book was intended to have the effect of an 
aper$u, and, if I may judge from the occasional 
utterances of Avenarius, H. Cornelius, James, Kiilpe, Loeb, 
Pearson, Petzoldt, Willy, and others, it seems to have 
fulfilled its object. It now appears, after fourteen years, in 
a new edition. This is a rather bold undertaking. For to 
allow the book to swell out into a bulky volume, by adding 
accounts of many experimental researches on points of 
detail, and by noticing at length the literature which has 
appeared since it was first published, would not be in 
keeping with its character. Yet I was unwilling to let slip 
this last opportunity without once again saying something 
on a subject which I have so much at heart. I have 
therefore added the supplements and elucidations most 
urgently required, principally by inserting short chapters in 
the original text. one of these, the second, has already 
appeared in the English edition published in 1897. 
x THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 

one and the same view underlies both my epistemo- 
logico-physical writings and my present attempt to deal 
with the physiology of the senses the view, namely, that 
all metaphysical elements are to be eliminated as super- 
fluous and as destructive of the economy of science. If I 
have not entered in these pages upon a detailed critical 
and polemical discussion of views that are opposed to my 
own, this is in truth not from contempt of my opponents, 
but because I am convinced that questions of this kind 
cannot be decided by controversies and dialectic combats. 
The only really profitable course is to carry one's half- 
thought or, it may be, one's paradoxical idea patiently 
about with one for years, and to make an honest effort to 
complete the half-thought, or to strip away the paradoxical 
element, as the case may be. Those readers who, after 
turning over the first pages, lay the book aside, because 
their convictions are such that they cannot follow me any 
further, will only be doing exactly what I myself have 
sometimes been compelled to do. 
In its former shape the book met with much friendly 
acceptance, but it also aroused strenuous opposition. 
Readers who wish to go more deeply into the subjects of 
which it treats, may find it useful to know that Willy, in 
a recently published work (Die Krisis in der Psychologic, 
Leipzig, 1899), in which a position closely allied to my 
own is adopted, opposes my views in many points of 
detail. 
VIENNA, April 1900 
A UTHOR'S PREFA CES xi 
PREFACE TO THE THIRD EDITION 
/""CONTRARY to my expectation, the second edition 
V^/ was exhausted in a few months. I have not 
hesitated to make certain additions which may help to put 
my views in a clearer light, though without altering the 
text of 1886 in any essential respect. Two passages only 
of the second edition (paragraph 7, p. n, and paragraph n, 
p. 15) have been cast in a clearer form. Dr. A. Lampa, 
lecturer in physics in this University, was told by several 
readers that these passages were often understood in a one- 
sided idealistic sense, an interpretation which I in no wise 
intended. I am greatly obliged to Dr. Lampa for giving 
me this information. Chapters IX. and XV., in which 
subjects touched upon in the second edition are developed 
at greater length, are new additions. 
Unless all indications are deceptive, I no longer occupy, 
as regards my views, anything like so isolated a position 
as I did even a few years ago. In addition to the school 
of Avenarius, there are also younger thinkers, such as 
H. Gomperz, who are approaching my point of view by 
their own paths. The differences that still remain over 
seem to me not irreconcilable. But it would be premature 
to dispute about them yet. " But the question is one in 
which it is peculiarly difficult to make out precisely what 
another man means, and even what one means oneself." 
The author of this delightfully humorous remark was 
W. K. Clifford, the mathematician (on the Nature of 
Things-in-themselves," Lectures^ vol. ii. p. 88), a writer with 
xii THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
an extremely close affinity to myself in the direction of his 
thought. 
VIENNA, November 1901 
PREFACE TO THE FOURTH EDITION 
THE opinion, which is gradually coming to the front, 
that science ought to be confined to the compendious 
representation of the actual, necessarily involves as a 
consequence the elimination of all superfluous assumptions 
which cannot be controlled by experience, and, above all, 
of all assumptions that are metaphysical in Kant's sense. 
If this point of view is kept firmly in mind in that wide field 
of investigation which includes the physical and the 
psychical, we obtain, as our first and most obvious step, the 
conception of the sensations as the common elements of 
all possible'physical and psychical experiences, which merely 
consist in the different kinds of ways in which these 
elements are combined, or in their dependence on one 
another. A whole series of troublesome pseudo-problems 
at once disappears. The aim of this book is not to put 
forward any system of philosophy, or any comprehensive 
theory of the universe. It is only the consequences of 
this single step, to which any number of others may be 
attached, that are examined here. An attempt is made, 
not to solve all problems, but to reach an epistemological 
position which shall prepare the way for the co-operation 
of special departments of research, that are widely removed 
A UTHORS PREFA CES xiii 
from one another, in the solution of important problems of 
detail. 
It is from this point of view that the accounts of special 
investigations, which are given here, should be regarded. 
If there is no essential difference between the physical and 
the psychical, we shall hope to trace the same exact 
connexion, which we seek in everything that is physical, in 
the relations between the physical and the psychical also. 
We then expect to find, corresponding to all the details 
which physiological analysis can discover in the sensa- 
tions, as many details of physical nerve-process. I have 
tried to describe this relation, so far as I have been able 
to do so, 
expressions of extravagant praise and of equally extra- 
vagant blame, have come to my ears. I hope that what 
I have just said, by moderating both, may promote a sober 
judgment. When, about thirty-five years ago, I succeeded, 
by overcoming my own prejudices, in firmly establishing 
my present position and in setting myself free from the 
greatest intellectual discomfort of my life, I attained 
thereby to a certain satisfaction. At that time I was only 
acquainted with Kant and Herbart. To-day I see that a 
whole host of philosophers positivists, critical empiricists, 
adherents of the philosophy of immanence, and certain 
isolated scientists as well have all, without any know- 
ledge of one another's work, entered upon paths which, in 
spite of all their individual differences, converge almost 
towards one point. If, in these circumstances, I cannot 
rate very high the value of my individual labours, I may 
nevertheless be permitted to believe that I have not merely 
pursued a subjective phantom, but have contributed 
xiv THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
towards the attainment of a goal at which many others 
besides myself have been aiming. It would of course be 
absurd, where ideas are concerned of which the leading 
threads reach back to antiquity, to set up any claims to 
priority. 
Dr. Josef Pollak and Dr. Wolfgang Pauli, lecturers in the 
Faculty of Medicine in the University of Vienna, have been 
so extremely kind as to read the proofs, for which I thank 
them most heartily. 
VIENNA, November 1902 
CONTENTS 
CHAP. PAGE 
I. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS : ANTIMETAPHYSICAL . i 
II. on PRECONCEIVED OPINIONS . . . .38 
III. MY RELATION TO RICHARD AVENARIUS AND OTHER 
THINKERS ...... 46 
IV. THE CHIEF POINTS OF VIEW FOR THE INVESTIGA- 
TION OF THE SENSES . . . -57 
V. PHYSICS AND BIOLOGY : CAUSALITY AND TELEOLOGY 83 
VI. THE SPACE-SENSATIONS OF THE EYE . . .102 
VII. FURTHER INVESTIGATION OF SPACE-SENSATIONS . 122 
VIII. THE WILL ...... 171 
IX. BlOLOGICO - TELEOLOGICAL CONSIDERATIONS AS TO 
SPACE . . . . . .181 
X. THE RELATIONS OF THE SIGHT-SENSATIONS TO onE 
ANOTHER AND TO OTHER PSYCHICAL ELEMENTS 195 
XI. SENSATION, MEMORY AND ASSOCIATION . . 235 
XII. THE SENSATION OF TIME .... 245 
XIII. THE SENSATIONS OF TONE .... 262 
XIV. INFLUENCE OF THE PRECEDING INVESTIGATIONS on 
OUR CONCEPTION OF PHYSICS . . . 310 
XV. HOW MY VIEWS HAVE BEEN RECEIVED . . 354 
INDEX OF SUBJECTS ..... 373 
INDEX OF NAMES ..... 377 
I. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS: 
ANTIMETAPHYSICAL. 
i. 
THE great results achieved by physical science in 
modem times results not restricted to its own 
sphere but embracing that of other sciences which em- 
ploy its help have brought it about that physical ways 
of thinking and physical modes of procedure enjoy on 
all hands unwonted prominence, and that the greatest 
expectations are associated with their application. In 
keeping with this drift of modern inquiry, the physiology of 
the senses, gradually abandoning the method of investigat- 
ing sensations in themselves followed by men like Goethe, 
Schopenhauer, and others, but with greatest success by 
Johannes Miiller, has also assumed an almost exclusively 
physical character. This tendency must appear to us as 
not altogether appropriate, when we reflect that physics, 
despite its considerable development, nevertheless con- 
stitutes but a portion of a larger collective body of know- 
ledge, and that it is unable, with its limited intellectual 
implements, created for limited and special purposes, to 
exhaust all the subject-matter in question. Without 
renouncing the support of physics, it is possible for 
the physiology of the senses, not only to pursue its own 
2 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
course of development, but also to afford to physical science 
itself powerful assistance. The following simple con- 
siderations will serve to illustrate this relation between 
the two. 
2. 
Colors, sounds, temperatures, pressures, spaces, times, 
and so forth, are connected with one another in manifold 
ways ; and with them are associated dispositions of mind, 
feelings, and volitions. Out of this fabric, that which is 
relatively more fixed and permanent stands prominently 
forth, engraves itself on the memory, and expresses itself in 
language. Relatively greater permanency is exhibited, first, 
by certain complexes of colors, sounds, pressures, and so 
forth, functionally connected in time and space, which 
therefore receive special names, and are called bodies. 
Absolutely permanent such complexes are not. 
My table is now brightly, now dimly lighted. Its 
temperature varies. It may receive an ink stain. one of 
its legs may be broken. It may be repaired, polished, and 
replaced part by part. But, for me, it remains the table at 
which I daily write. 
My friend may put on a different coat. His countenance 
may assume a serious or a cheerful expression. His 
complexion, under the effects of light or emotion, may 
change. His shape may be altered by motion, or be 
definitely changed. Yet the number of the permanent 
features presented, compared with the number of the 
gradual alterations, is always so great, that the latter may 
be overlooked. It is the same friend with whom I take my 
daily walk. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 3 
My coat may receive a stain, a tear. My very manner 
of expressing this shows that we are concerned here with 
a sum-total of permanency, to which the new element is 
added and from which that which is lacking is subsequently 
taken away. 
Our greater* intimacy with this sum-total of permanency, 
and the preponderance of its importance for me as con- 
trasted with the changeable element, impel us to the partly 
instinctive, partly voluntary and conscious economy of 
mental presentation and designation, as expressed in 
ordinary thought and speech. That which is presented in 
a single image receives a single designation, a single name. 
Further, that complex of memories, moods, and feelings, 
joined to a particular body (the human body), which is 
called the " I " or "Ego," manifests itself as relatively 
permanent. I may be engaged upon this or that subject, 
I may be quiet and cheerful, excited and ill-humored. 
Yet, pathological cases apart, enough durable features 
remain to identify the ego. Of course, the ego also is only 
of relative permanency. 
The apparent permanency of the ego consists chiefly 
in the single fact of its continuity, in the slowness of its 
changes. The many thoughts and plans of yesterday that 
are continued to-day, and of which our environment in 
waking hours incessantly reminds us (whence in dreams the 
ego can be very indistinct, doubled, or entirely wanting), 
and the little habits that are unconsciously and involuntarily 
kept up for long periods of time, constitute the groundwork 
of the ego. There can hardly be greater differences in the 
egos of different people, than occur in the course of years 
in one person. When I recall to-day my early youth, I 
4 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
should take the boy that I then was, with the exception of 
a few individual features, for a different person, were it not 
for the existence of the chain of memories. Many an 
article that I myself penned twenty years ago impresses 
me now as something quite foreign to myself. The very 
gradual character of the changes of the body also contributes 
to the stability of the ego, but in a much less degree than 
people imagine. Such things are much less analysed and 
noticed than the intellectual and the moral ego. Personally, 
people know themselves very poorly. 1 When I wrote these 
lines in 1886, Ribot's admirable little book, The Diseases 
of Personality (second edition, Paris, 1888, Chicago, 1895), 
was unknown to me. Ribot ascribes the principal r61e in 
preserving the continuity of the ego to the general sensibility. 
Generally, I am in perfect accord with his views. 2 
The ego is as little absolutely permanent as are bodies. 
That which we so much dread in death, the annihilation 
of our permanency, actually occurs in life in abundant 
measure. That which is most valued by us, remains 
preserved in countless copies, or, in cases of exceptional 
1 once, when a young man, I noticed in the street the profile of a face 
that was very displeasing and repulsive to me. I was not a little taken 
aback when a moment afterwards I found that it was my own face which, 
in passing by a shop where mirrors were sold, I had perceived reflected 
from two mirrors that were inclined at the proper angle to each other. 
Not long ago, after a trying railway journey by night, when I was 
very tired, I got into an omnibus, just as another man appeared at the 
other end. ' ' What a shabby pedagogue that is, that has just entered," 
thought I. It was myself: opposite me hung a large mirror. The 
physiognomy of my class, accordingly, was better known to me than 
my own. 
2 Cp. Hume, Treatise on Human Nature, Vol. I. part iv., p. 6 ; 
Gruithuisen, Beitragc zur Physiognosie und Eautognosie, Munich, 
1812, pp. 37-58. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 5 
excellence, is even preserved of itself. In the best human 
being, however, there are individual traits, the loss of which 
neither he himself nor others need regret. Indeed, at 
times, death, viewed as a liberation from individuality, may 
even become a pleasant thought. Such reflections of 
course do not make physiological death any the easier to 
bear. 
After a first survey has been obtained, by the formation 
of the substance-concepts "body" and "ego" (matter and 
soul), the will is impelled to a more exact examination of 
the changes that take place in these relatively permanent 
existences. The element of change in bodies and the ego, 
is in fact, exactly what moves the will T to this examination. 
Here the component parts of the complex are first exhibited 
as its properties. A fruit is sweet ; but it can also be 
bitter. Also, other fruits may be sweet. The red color 
we are seeking is found in many bodies. The neighbor- 
hood of some bodies is pleasant; that of others, 
unpleasant. Thus, gradually, different complexes are 
found to be made up of common elements. The visible, 
the audible, the tangible, are separated from bodies. The 
visible is analysed into colors and into form. In the 
manifoldness of the colors, again, though here fewer in 
number, other component parts are discerned such as 
the primary colors, and so forth. The complexes are 
disintegrated into elements, 2 that is to say, into their 
ultimate component parts, which hitherto we have been 
1 Not to be taken in the metaphysical sense. 
2 If this process be regarded as an abstraction, the elements, as we 
shall see, do not thereby lose anything of their importance. Cp. the 
subsequent discussion of concepts in Chapter XIV. 
6 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
unable to subdivide any further. The nature of these 
elements need not be discussed at present ; it is possible 
that future investigations may throw light on it. We 
need not here be disturbed by the fact that it is easier for 
the scientist to study relations of relations of these 
elements than the direct relations between them. 
The useful habit of designating such relatively permanent 
compounds by single names, and of apprehending them by 
single thoughts, without going to the trouble each time of 
an analysis of their component parts, is apt to come into 
strange conflict with the tendency to isolate the component 
parts. The vague image which we have of a given per- 
manent complex, being an image which does not perceptibly 
change when one or another of the component parts is taken 
away, seems to be something which exists in itself. Inas- 
much as it is possible to take away singly every constituent 
part without destroying the capacity of the image to stand 
for the totality and to be recognised again, it is imagined 
that it is possible to subtract all the parts and to have 
something still remaining. Thus naturally arises the philo- 
sophical notion, at first impressive, but subsequently re- 
cognized as monstrous, of a "thing-in-itself," different from 
its "appearance," and unknowable. 1 
r Thing, body, matter, are nothing apart from the combi- 
lations of the elements, the colors, sounds, and so forth 
Cp. W. Schuppe's polemic against Ueberweg, printed in Brasch's 
Welt-iind Lebensanschauung Ueber-wegs, Leipzig, 1889; F.J. Schmidt, 
Das Aergernis der Philosophic: eine Kantstudie, Berlin, 1897. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 7 
nothing apart from their so-called attributes. That 
protean pseudo-philosophical problem of the single thing 
with its many attributes, arises wholly from a misinter- 
pretation of the fact, that summary comprehension and 
precise analysis, although both are provisionally justifiable 
and for many purposes profitable, cannot be carried on 
simultaneously. A body is one and unchangeable only so 
long as it is unnecessary to consider its details. Thus 
both the earth and a billiard-ball are spheres, if we are 
willing to neglect all deviations from the spherical form, and 
if greater precision is not necessary. But when we are 
obliged to carry on investigations in orography or micro- 
scopy, both bodies cease to be spheres. 
Man is pre-eminently endowed with the power of volun- 
tarily and consciously determining his own point of view. 
He can at one time disregard the most salient features of 
an object, and immediately thereafter give attention to its 
smallest details ; now consider a stationary current, without 
a thought of its contents (whether heat, electricity or fluidity), 
and then measure the width of a Fraunhofer line in the 
spectrum ; he can rise at will to the most general abstrac- 
tions or bury himself in the minutest particulars. Animals 
possess this capacity in a far less degree. They do not 
assume a point of view, but are usually forced to it by their 
sense-impressions. The baby that does not know its father 
with his hat on, the dog that is perplexed at the new coat 
of its master, have both succumbed in this conflict of 
points of view. Who has not been worsted in similar 
8 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
plights ? Even the man of philosophy at times succumbs, 
as the grotesque problem, above referred to, shows. 
In this last case, the circumstances appear to furnish 
a real ground of justification. Colors, sounds, and the 
odors of bodies are evanescent. But their tangibility, as 
a sort of constant nucleus, not readily susceptible of 
annihilation, remains behind; appearing as the vehicle 
of the more fugitive properties attached to it. Habit, 
thus, keeps our thought firmly attached to this central 
nucleus, even when we have begun to recognize that seeing 
hearing, smelling, and touching are intimately akin in 
character. A further consideration is, that owing to the 
singularly extensive development of mechanical physics a 
kind of higher reality is ascribed to the spatial and to the 
temporal than to colors, sounds, and odors ; agreeably to 
which, the temporal and spatial links of colors, sounds, 
and odors appear to be more real than the colors, sounds 
and odors themselves. The physiology of the senses, 
however, demonstrates, that spaces and times may just as 
appropriately be called sensations as colors and sounds. 
But of this later. 
Not only the relation of bodies to the ego, but the ego 
itself also, gives rise to similar pseudo- problems, the 
character of which may be briefly indicated as follows : 
Let us denote the above-mentioned elements by the 
letters A B C . . ., K L M . . '., /.*. Let those 
complexes of colors, sounds, and so forth, commonly 
called bodies, be denoted, for the sake of clearness, by 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 9 
ABC. . . ; the complex, known as our own body, which 
is a part of the former complexes distinguished by certain 
peculiarities, may be called K L M . . . ; the complex 
composed of volitions, memory-images, and the rest, we 
shall represent by a /3 7 ... Usually, now, the complex 
a /5 7 . . . K L M . . ., as making up the ego, is opposed 
to the complex ABC. . ., as making up the world of 
physical objects ; sometimes also, a /3 y ... is viewed as 
ego, and-ATZJ/. . .ABC. ..as world of physical' 
objects. Now, at first blush, ABC. . . appears inde- 
pendent of the ego, and opposed to it as a separate exist- 
ence. But this independence is only relative, and gives 
way upon closer inspection. Much, it is true, may change 
in the complex a j8 y . . . without much perceptible change 
being induced in ABC-. . . ; and vice versa. But many 
changes in a (3 y ... do pass, by way of changes in 
K L M . . ., to ABC. . .; and vice versa. (As, for 
example, when powerful ideas burst forth into acts, or when 
our environment induces noticeable changes in our body.) 
At the same time the group K L M . . . appears to be more 
intimately connected with a /3 y . . . and with ABC. . ., 
than the latter with one another ; and their relations find 
their expression in common thought and speech. 
Precisely viewed, however, it appears that the group 
A B C ... is always codetermined by K L M. A cube 
when seen close at hand, looks large ; when seen at a 
distance, small ; its appearance to the right eye differs from 
its appearance to the left ; sometimes it appears double ; 
with closed eyes it is invisible. The properties of one and 
the same body, therefore, appear modified by our own 
body; they appear conditioned by it. But where, now, 
lo THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
is that same body, which appears so different? All that can 
be said is, that with different KL M different ABC. . . 
are associated. 1 
A common and popular way of thinking and speaking 
is to contrast " appearance " with " reality." A pencil 
held in front of us in the air is seen by us as straight; 
dip it into the water, and we see it crooked. In the latter 
case we say that the pencil appears crooked, but is in 
reality straight. But what justifies us in declaring one 
fact rather than another to be the reality, and degrading 
the other to the level of appearance ? In both cases we 
have to do with facts which present us with different com- 
binations of the elements, combinations which in the two 
cases are differently conditioned. Precisely because of 
its environment the pencil dipped in water is optically 
crooked; but it is tactually and metrically straight. An 
image in a concave or flat mirror is only visible, whereas 
under other and ordinary circumstances a tangible body 
as well corresponds to the visible image. A bright surface 
1 A long time ago (in the Vierteljahrsschrift fur Psychiatric^ Leipzig 
and Neuwied, 1868, art. " Ueber die Abhangigkeit der Netzhautstellen 
von einander") I enunciated this thought as follows : The expression 
" sense-illusion" proves that we are not yet fully conscious, or at least 
have not yet deemed it necessary to incorporate the fact into our 
ordinary language, that the senses represent things neither "wrongly nor 
correctly. All that can be truly said of the sense-organs is, that, under 
different circumstances they produce different sensations and perceptions. 
As these "circumstances," now, are extremely various in character, 
being partly external (inherent in the objects), partly internal (inherent 
in the sensory organs), and partly interior (having their activity in the 
central organs), it can sometimes appear, when we only notice the 
external circumstances, as if the organ acted differently under the 
same conditions. And it is customary to call the unusual effects, 
deceptions or illusions. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS n 
is brighter beside a dark surface than beside one brighter 
than itself. To be sure, our expectation is deceived when, 
not paying sufficient attention to the conditions, and sub- 
stituting for one another different cases of the combination, 
we fall into the natural error of expecting what we are 
accustomed to, although the case may be an unusual one. 
The facts are not to blame for that. In these cases, to 
speak of "appearance" may have a practical meaning, 
but cannot have a scientific meaning. Similarly, the 
question which is often asked, whether the world is real 
or whether we merely dream it, is devoid of all scientific 
meaning. Even the wildest dream is a fact as much as 
any other. If our dreams were more regular, more con- 
nected, more stable, they would also have more practical 
importance for us. In our waking hours the relations of 
the elements to one another are immensely amplified in 
comparison with what they were in our dreams. We 
recognize the dream for what it is. When the process 
is reversed, the field of psychic vision is narrowed; the 
contrast is almost entirely lacking. Where there is no 
contrast, the distinction between dream and waking, 
between appearance and reality, is quite otiose and 
worthless. 
The popular notion of an antithesis between appearance 
and reality has exercised a very powerful influence on 
scientific and philosophical thought. We see this, for 
example, in Plato's pregnant and poetical fiction of the 
Cave, in which, with our backs turned towards the fire, 
we observe merely the shadows of what passes (Reptiblic, 
vii. i). But this conception was not thought out to its 
final consequences, with the result that it has had an 
12 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
unfortunate influence on our ideas about the universe. 
The universe, of which nevertheless we are a part, became 
completely separated from us, and was removed an 
infinite distance away. Similarly, many a young man, 
hearing for the first time of the refraction of stellar light, 
has thought that doubt was cast on the whole of astronomy, 
whereas nothing is required but an easily effected and 
unimportant correction to put everything right again. 
6. 
We see an object having a point S. If we touch S, 
that is, bring it into connexion with our body, we receive 
a prick. We can see S, without feeling the prick. But 
as soon as we feel the prick we find S on the skin. The 
visible point, therefore, is a permanent nucleus, to which 
the prick is annexed, according to circumstances, as some- 
thing accidental. From the frequency of analogous 
occurrences we ultimately accustom ourselves to regard 
all properties of bodies as "effects" proceeding from 
permanent nuclei and conveyed to the ego through the 
medium of the body; which effects we call sensations. 
By this operation, however, these nuclei are deprived of 
their entire sensory content, and converted into mere 
mental symbols. The assertion, then, is correct that the 
world consists only of our sensations. In which case we 
have knowledge only of sensations, and the assumption 
of the nuclei referred to, or of a reciprocal action between 
them, from which sensations proceed, turns out to be quite 
idle and superfluous. Such a view can only suit with a half- 
hearted realism or a half-hearted philosophical criticism. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 13 
Ordinarily the complex a j3 y ... AT Z .A/" ... is con- 
trasted as ego with the complex ABC... At first only those 
elements of A B C . . . that more strongly alter a [3 y . . ., 
as a prick, a pain, are wont to be thought of as comprised 
in the ego. Afterwards, however, through observations 
of the kind just referred to, it appears that the right to 
annex ABC. . . to the ego nowhere ceases. In con- 
formity with this view the ego can be so extended as 
ultimately to embrace the entire world. 1 The ego is not 
sharply marked off, its limits are very indefinite and 
arbitrarily displaceable. only by failing to observe this 
fact, and by unconsciously narrowing those limits, while 
at the same time we enlarge them, arise, in the conflict 
of points of view, the metaphysical difficulties met with 
in this connexion. 
As soon as we have perceived that the supposed unities 
"body" and "ego" are only makeshifts, designed for 
provisional orientation and for definite practical ends (so 
that we may take hold of bodies, protect ourselves against 
pain, and so forth), we find ourselves obliged, in many 
1 When I say that the table, the tree, and so forth, are my sensations, 
the statement, as contrasted with the mode of representation of the 
ordinary man, involves a real extension of my ego. on the emotional 
side also such extensions occur, as in the case of the virtuoso, who 
possesses as perfect a mastery of his instrument as he does of his own 
body; or in the case of the skilful orator, on whom the eyes of the 
audience are all converged, and who is controlling the thoughts of all ; 
or in that of the able politician who is deftly guiding his party ; and so 
on. In conditions of depression, on the other hand, such as nervous people 
often endure, the ego contracts and shrinks. A wall seems to separate 
it from the world. 
14 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
more advanced scientific investigations, to abandon them as 
insufficient and inappropriate. The antithesis between ego 
and world, between sensation (appearance) and thing, then 
vanishes, and we have simply to deal with the connexion of 
the elements a$y . . . A J? C . . . KL M . . ., of which 
this antithesis was only a partially appropriate and imperfect 
expression. This connexion is nothing more or less than 
the combination of the above-mentioned elements with 
other similar elements (time and space). Science has 
simply to accept this connexion, and to get its bearings in 
it, without at once wanting to explain its existence. 

on a superficial examination the complex a /3 y . . . 
appears to be made up of much more evanescent elements 
than ABC... and K L M . . ., in which last the 
elements seem to be connected with greater stability and in 
a more permanent manner (being joined to solid nuclei as 
it were). Although on closer inspection the elements of 
all complexes prove to be homogeneous, yet even when this 
has been recognized, the earlier notion of an antithesis of 
body and spirit easily slips in again. The philosophical 
spiritualist is often sensible of the difficulty of imparting the 
needed solidity to his mind-created world of bodies ; the 
materialist is at a loss when required to endow the world of 
matter with sensation. The monistic point of view, which 
reflexion has evolved, is easily clouded by our older and 
more powerful instinctive notions. 
8. 
The difficulty referred to is particularly felt when we 
consider the following case. In the complex ABC. . ., 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 15 
which we have called the world of matter, we find as parts, 
not only our own body K L M . . ., but also the bodies of 
other persons (or animals) K' L' M' . . ., K" L' M" . . ., 
to which, by analogy, we imagine other a' $' y' . . ., 
a" (3" y" . . ., annexed, similar to a /3 y . . . So long as 
we deal with K r Z' M' . . ., we find ourselves in a thor- 
oughly familiar province which is at every point accessible^ 
to our senses. When, however, we inquire after the sensa- \ 
tions or feelings belonging to the body K' U M' . . ., we 
no longer find these in the province of sense : we add them 
in thought. Not only is the domain which we now enter 
far less familiar to us, but the transition into it is also 
relatively unsafe. We have the feeling as if we were plung- 
ing into an abyss. 1 Persons who adopt this way of thinking 
only, will never thoroughly rid themselves of that sense of 
insecurity, which is a very fertile source of illusory problems. 
But we are not restricted to this course. Let us consider, 
first, the reciprocal relations of the elements of the complex 
ABC. . ., without regarding K L M . . . (our body). 
1 When I first came to Vienna from the country, as a boy of four or 
five years, and was taken by my father upon the walls of the city's 
fortifications, I was very much surprised to see people below in the 
moat, and could not understand how, from my point of view, they 
could have got there ; for the thought of another way of descent never 
occurred to me. I remarked the same astonishment, once afterwards, 
in the case of a three-year-old boy of my own, while walking on the walls 
of Prague. I recall this feeling every time I occupy myself with the 
reflexion of the text, and I frankly confess that this accidental experi- 
ence of mine helped to confirm my opinion upon this point, which I 
have now long held. Our habit of always following the same path, 
whether materially or psychically, tends greatly to confuse our field of 
survey. A child, on the piercing of the wall of a house in which he 
has long dwelt, may experience a veritable enlargement of his world- 
view, and in the same manner a slight scientific hint may often afford 
great enlightenment. 
16 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
All physical investigations are of this sort. A white ball 
falls upon a bell ; a sound is heard. The ball turns yellow 
before a sodium lamp, red before a lithium lamp. Here 
the elements (ABC. . . ) appear to be connected only 
with one another and to be independent of our body 
(K L M . . . ). But if we take santonine, the ball again 
turns yellow. If we press one eye to the side, we see two 
balls. If we close our eyes entirely, there is no ball there 
at all. If we sever the auditory nerve, no sound is heard. 
The elements ABC.. ., therefore, are not only con- 
nected with one another, but also with K L M. To this 
extent, and to this extent only> do we call ABC,., 
sensations^ and regard A B C as belonging to the ego. In 
what follows, wherever the reader finds the terms " Sensa- 
tion," " Sensation-complex," used alongside of or instead of 
the expressions " element," " complex of elements," it must 
be borne in mind that it is only in the connexion and 
relation in question, only in their functional dependence, 
that the elements are sensations. In another functional 
relation they are at the same time physical objects. We 
only use the additional term "sensations" to describe the 
elements, because most people are much more familiar 
with the elements in question as sensations (colors, sounds, 
pressures, spaces, times, etc.), while according to the 
popular conception it is particles of mass that are con- 
sidered as physical elements, to which the elements, in the 
sense here used, are attached as "properties " or "effects." * 
1 A treatment of this fundamental point, identical in essentials, but 
cast in a form which will be perhaps more acceptable to scientists, will 
be found in my Erkenntnis und Irrtum, Leipzig, 1905 (2nd edition, 
Leipzig, 1906.) 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 17 
In this way, accordingly, we do not find the gap between 
bodies and sensations above described, between what is 
without and what is within, between the material world and 
the spiritual world. 1 All elements A B C . . ., K L M . . ., 
constitute a single coherent mass only, in which, when any 
one element is disturbed, all is put in motion ; except that 
a disturbance in K L M . . . has a more extensive and 
profound action than one in A B C ... A magnet in our 
neighborhood disturbs the particles of iron near it; a 
falling boulder shakes the earth \ but the severing of a nerve 
sets in motion the whole system of elements.- Quite 
involuntarily does this relation of things suggest the picture 
of a viscous mass, at certain places (as in the ego) more 
firmly coherent than in others. I have often made use of 
this image in lectures. 
Thus the great gulf between physical and psychological 
research persists only when we acquiesce in our habitual 
stereotyped conceptions. A color is a physical object as 
soon as we consider its dependence, for instance, upon its 
luminous source, upon other colors, upon temperatures, 
upon spaces, and so forth. When we consider, however, its 
dependence upon the retina (the elements KL M . . .), 
it is a psychological object, a sensation. Not the subject- 
1 Compare my Grundlinien der Lehre von den Bewegungsempfindim- 
gen, Leipzig, Engelmann, 1875, p. 54. I there, for the first time, 
stated my view shortly, but definitely, in these words : " Appearance 
may be subdivided into elements, which, in so far as they are connected 
with certain processes of our bodies, and can be regarded as conditioned 
by these processes, we call sensations." 
B 
i8 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
matter, but the direction of our investigation, is different in 
the two domains. (Cp. also Chapter II., pp. 43, 44.) 
Both in reasoning from the observation of the bodies 
of other men or animals, to the sensations which they 
possess, as well as in investigating the influence of our 
own body upon our own sensations, we have to complete 
observed facts by analogy. This is accomplished with 
much greater ease and certainty, when it relates, say, only 
to nervous processes, which cannot be fully observed in 
our own bodies that is, when it is carried out in the more 
familiar ..physical domain than when it is extended to 
the psychical domain, to the sensations and thoughts of 
other people. Otherwise there is no essential difference. 
10. 
The considerations just advanced, expressed as they have 
been in an abstract form, will gain in strength and vividness 
if we consider the concrete facts from which they flow. 
Thus, I lie upon my sofa. . If I close my right eye, the 
picture represented in the accompanying cut is presented 
to my left eye. In a frame formed by the ridge of my 
eyebrow, by my nose, and by my moustache, appears a 
part of my body, so far as visible, with its environment. 1 
My body differs from other human bodies beyond the 
fact that every intense motor idea is immediately ex- 
pressed by a movement of it, and that, if it is touched, 
more striking changes are determined than if other bodies 
1 A discussion of the binocular field of vision, with its peculiar 
stereoscopic features, is omitted here, for although familiar to all, it is 
not as easy to describe, and cannot be represented by a single plane 
drawing. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 19 
are touched by the circumstance, that it is only seen 
piecemeal, and, especially, is seen without a head. If I 
Fig. x. 
observe an element A within my field of vision, and 
investigate its connexion with another element B within 
the same field, I step out of the domain of physics into 
that of physiology or psychology, provided B, to use the 
20 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
apposite expression of a friend l of mine made upon seeing 
this drawing, passes through my skin. Reflexions like 
that for the field of vision may be made with regard to the 
province of touch and the perceptual domains of the other 
senses. 2 
ii. 
Reference has already been made to the different 
character of the groups of elements denoted by A B C . . . 
and a /3 y ... As a matter of fact, when we see a green 
tree before us, or remember a green tree, that is, represent 
a green tree to ourselves, we are perfectly aware of the 
difference of the two cases. The represented tree has a 
much less determinate, a much more changeable form ; 
its green is much paler and more evanescent ; and, what 
is of especial note, it plainly appears in a different domain. 
A movement that we will to execute is never more than a 
represented movement, and appears in a different domain 
from that of the executed movement, which always takes 
place when the image is vivid enough. Now the statement 
1 J. Popper of Vienna. 
2 It was about 1870 that the idea of this drawing was suggested to 
me by an amusing chance. A certain Mr L., now long dead, whose 
many eccentricities were redeemed by his truly amiable character, 
compelled me to read one of C. F. Krause's writings, in which the 
following occurs : 
" Problem : To carry out the self-inspection of the Ego. 
Solution : It is carried out immediately." 
In order to illustrate in a humorous manner this philosophical " much 
ado about nothing," and at the same time to shew how the self- 
inspection of the Ego could be really "carried out," I embarked on the 
above drawing. Mr L.'s society was most instructive and stimulating 
to me, owing to the naivety with which he gave utterance to philo- 
sophical notions that are apt to be carefully passed over in silence or 
involved in obscurity. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 21 
that the elements A and a appear in different domains, 
means, if we go to the bottom of it, simply this, that these 
elements are united with different other elements. Thus 
far, therefore, the fundamental constituents of A B C . . ., 
a (3 y . . . would seem to be the same (colors, sounds, 
spaces, times, motor sensations . . .), and only the 
character of their connexion different. 
Ordinarily pleasure and pain are regarded as different 
from sensations. Yet not only tactual sensations, but all 
other kinds of sensations, may pass gradually into pleasure 
and pain. Pleasure and pain also may be justly termed 
sensations. only they are not so well analysed and so 
familiar, nor, perhaps, limited to so few organs as the 
common sensations. In fact, sensations of pleasure and 
pain, however faint they may be, really constitute an 
essential part of the content of all so-called emotions. 
Any additional element that emerges into consciousness 
when we are under the influence of emotions may be 
described as more or less diffused and not sharply local- 
ized sensations. William James, 1 and after him Theodule 
Ribot, 2 have investigated the physiological mechanism of 
the emotions : they hold that what is essential is purposive 
tendencies of the body to action tendencies which cor- 
respond to circumstances and are expressed in the organism. 
only a part of these emerges into consciousness. We 
are sad because we shed tears, and not vice versa^ 
says James. And Ribot justly observes that a cause of 
the backward state of our knowledge of the emotions is 
1 W. James, Psychology ', New York, 1890, II., p. 442. 
2 Th. Ribot, La psychologic des sentiments, 1896. (English trans- 
lation, The Psychology of 'the Emotions > 1897.) 
22 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
that we have always confined our observation to so much 
of these physiological processes as emerges into conscious- 
ness. At the same time he goes too far when he main- 
tains that everything psychical is merely " surajoute" to 
the physical, and that it is only the physical that produces 
effects. For us this distinction is non-existent. 
Thus, perceptions, presentations, volitions, and emotions, 
in short the whole inner and outer world, are put together, in 
combinations of varying evanescence and permanence, out 
of a small number of homogeneous elements. Usually, these 
elements are called sensations. But as vestiges of a one- 
sided theory inhere in that term, we prefer to speak simply of 
elements, as we have already done. The aim of all research 
is to ascertain the mode of connexion of these elements. 1 
If it proves impossible to solve the problem by assuming one 
set of such elements, then more than one will have to be 
assumed. But for the questions under discussion it would be 
improper to begin by making complicated assumptions in 
advarice. 
12. 
That in this complex of elements, which fundamentally 
is only one, the boundaries of bodies and of the ego do 
not admit of being established in a manner definite and 
sufficient for all cases, has already been remarked. To 
bring together elements that are most intimately connected 
with pleasure and pain into one ideal mental-economical 
1 Compare the note at the conclusion of my treatise, Die Geschichte 
^lnd die Wurzel des Satzes der Erhaltung der Arbeit, Prague, Calve, 
1 872. {History and Root of the Principle, of the Conservation of Energy. 
Translated and annotated by P. E. B. Jourdain, Chicago, Open Court 
Publishing Co., 1911.) 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 23 
unity, the ego ; this is a task of the highest importance 
for the intellect working in the service of the pain-avoiding, 
pleasure-seeking will. The delimitation of the ego, there- 
fore, is instinctively effected, is rendered familiar, and 
possibly becomes fixed through heredity. Owing to their 
high practical importance, not only for the individual, but 
for the entire species, the composites " ego " and " body " 
instinctively make good their claims, and assert themselves 
with elementary force. In special cases, however, in which 
practical ends are not concerned, but where knowledge 
is an end in itself, the delimitation in question may prove 
to be insufficient, obstructive, and untenable. 1 
The primary fact is not the ego, but the elements 
(sensations). What was said on p. 21 as to the term 
" sensation " must be borne in mind. The elements 
constitute the I. 7 have the sensation green, signifies 
that the element green occurs in a given complex of other 
elements (sensations, memories). When 7 cease to have 
the sensation green, when 7 die, then the elements no 
1 Similarly, class-consciousness, class-prejudice, the feeling of nation- 
ality, and even the narrowest-minded local patriotism may have a high 
importance, jor certain purposes. But such attitudes will not be 
shared by the broad-minded investigator, at least not in moments of 
research. All such egoistic views are adequate only for practical 
purposes. Of course, even the investigator may succumb to habit. 
Trifling pedantries and nonsensical discussions ; the cunning appro- 
priation of others' thoughts, with perfidious silence as to the sources ; 
when the word of recognition must be given, the difficulty of swallow- 
ing one's defeat, and the too common eagerness at the same time to set 
the opponent's achievement in a false light : all this abundantly shows 
that the scientist and scholar have also the battle of existence to fight, 
that the ways even of science still lead to the mouth, and that the 
pure impulse towards knowledge is still an ideal in our present social 
conditions. 
24 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
longer occur in the ordinary, familiar association. That 
is all. only an ideal mental-economical unity, not a real 
unity, has ceased to exist. The ego is not a definite, 
unalterable, sharply - bounded unity. None of these 
attributes are important ; for all vary even within the 
sphere of individual life; in fact their alteration is even 
sought after by the individual. Continuity alone is 
important. This view accords admirably with the position 
which Weismann has reached by biological investigations. 
(" Zur Frage der Unsterblichkeit der Einzelligen," Biolog. 
Centralbl.^ Vol. IV., Nos. 21, 22 ; compare especially 
pages 654 and 655, where the scission of the individual 
into two equal halves is spoken of.) But continuity is 
only a means of preparing and conserving what is con- 
tained in the ego. This content, and not the ego, is the 
principal thing. This content, however, is not confined 
to the individual. With the exception of some insignificant 
and valueless personal memories, it remains preserved in 
others even after the death of the individual. The elements 
that make up the consciousness of a given individual are 
firmly connected with one another, but with those of 
another individual they are only feebly connected, and 
the connexion is only casually apparent. Contents of 
consciousness, however, that are of universal significance, 
break through these limits of the individual, and, attached 
of course to individuals again, can enjoy a continued exist- 
ence of an impersonal, superpersonal kind, independently 
of the personality by means of which they were developed. 
To contribute to this is the greatest happiness of the artist, 
the scientist, the inventor, the social reformer, etc. 
The ego must be given up. It is partly the perception 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 25 
of this fact, partly the fear of it, that has given rise to the 
many extravagances of pessimism and optimism, and to 
numerous religious, ascetic, and philosophical absurdities. 
In the long run we shall not be able to close our eyes to 
this simple truth, which is the immediate outcome of 
psychological analysis. We shall then no longer place so 
high a value upon the ego, which even during the in- 
dividual life greatly changes, and which, in sleep or during 
absorption in some idea, just in our very happiest 
moments, may be partially or wholly absent. We shall 
then be willing to renounce individual immortality, 1 and 
not place more value upon the subsidiary elements than 
upon the principal ones. In this way we shall arrive at 
a freer and more enlightened view of life, which will 
preclude the disregard of other egos and the over- 
estimation of our own. The ethical ideal founded on 
this view of life will be equally far removed from the 
ideal of the ascetic, which is not biologically tenable for 
whoever practises it, and vanishes at once with his dis- 
appearance, and from the ideal of an overweening 
Nietzschean "superman," who cannot, and I hope will 
not be tolerated by his fellow-men. 2 
If a knowledge of the connexion of the elements (sensa- 
tions) does not suffice us, and we ask, Who possesses this 
connexion of sensations, Who experiences it? then we 
have succumbed to the old habit of subsuming every 
1 In wishing to preserve our personal memories beyond death, we 
are behaving like the astute Eskimo, who refused with thanks the gift 
of immortality without his seals and walruses. 
2 However far the distance is from theoretical understanding to 
practical conduct, still the latter cannot in the long run resist the 
former. 
26 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
element (every sensation) under some unanalysed complex, 
and we are falling back imperceptibly upon an older, 
lower, and more limited point of view. It is often pointed 
out, that a psychical experience which is not the experience 
of a determinate subject is unthinkable, and it is held that 
in this way the essential part played by the unity of con- 
sciousness has been demonstrated. But the Ego-conscious- 
ness can be of many different degrees and composed of a 
multiplicity of chance memories. one might just as well 
say that a physical process which does not take place in 
some environment or other, or at least somewhere in the 
universe, is unthinkable. In both cases, in order to make 
a beginning with our investigation, we must be allowed to 
abstract from the environment, which, as regards its influ- 
ence, may be very different in different cases, and in special 
cases may shrink to a minimum. Consider the sensations 
of the lower animals, to which a subject with definite 
features can hardly be ascribed. It is out of sensations 
that the subject is built up, and, once built up, no doubt 
the subject reacts in turn on the sensations. 
The habit of treating the unanalysed ego complex as an 
indiscernible unity frequently assumes in science remark- 
able forms. First, the nervous system is separated from 
the body as the seat of the sensations. In the nervous 
system again, the brain is selected as the organ best fitted 
for this end, and finally, to save the supposed psychical 
unity, a point is sought in the brain as the seat of the soul. 
But such crude conceptions are hardly fit even to fore- 
shadow the roughest outlines of what future research will 
do for the connexion of the physical and the psychical. 
The fact that the different organs and parts of the nervous 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 27 
system are physically connected with, and can be readily 
excited by, one another, is probably at the bottom of the 
notion of " psychical unity." 
I once heard the question seriously discussed, "How 
the perception of a large tree could find room in the little 
head of a man?" Now, although this "problem" is no 
problem, yet it renders us vividly sensible of the absurdity 
that can be committed by thinking sensations spatially into 
the brain. When I speak of the sensations of another 
person, those sensations are, of course, not exhibited in 
my optical or physical space ; they are mentally added, and 
I conceive them causally, not spatially, attached to the 
brain observed, or rather, functionally presented. When I 
speak of my own sensations, these sensations do not exist 
spatially in my head, but rather my "head" shares with 
them the same spatial field, as was explained above. 
(Compare the remarks on Fig. i on pp. 17-19 above.) 1 
The unity of consciousness is not an argument in point. 
1 As early as the writings of Johannes Miiller, we can already find a 
tendency towards views of this kind, although his metaphysical bias 
prevents him from carrying them to their logical conclusion. But 
Hering (Hermann's Handb^tch der Physiologic, Vol. III., p. 345) has 
the following characteristic passage: "The material of which visual 
objects consists is the visual sensations. The setting sun, as a visual 
object, is a flat, circular disk, which consists of yellowish-red color, 
that is to say of a visual sensation. We may therefore describe it 
directly as a circular, yellowish-red sensation. This sensation we have 
in the very place where the sun appears to us." I must confess that, so 
far as the experiments go which I have had occasion to make in con- 
versation, most people, who have not come to close quarters with 
these questions by serious thinking, will pronounce this way of looking 
at the matter to be mere hair-splitting. Of course, what is chiefly 
responsible for their indignation is the common confusion between 
sensible and conceptual space. But anyone who takes his stand as I 
do on the economic function of science, according to which nothing is 
28 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Since the apparent antithesis between the real world and 
the world given through the senses lies entirely in our 
mode of view, and no actual gulf exists between them, a 
complicated and variously interconnected content of con- 
sciousness is no more difficult to understand than is the 
complicated interconnexion of the world. 
If we regard the ego as a real unity, we become involved 
in the following dilemma : either we must set over against 
the ego a world of unknowable entities (which would be 
quite idle and purposeless), or we must regard the whole 
world, the egos of other people included, as comprised in 
our own ego (a proposition to which it is difficult to yield 
serious assent). 
But if we take the ego simply as a practical unity, put 
together for purposes of provisional survey, or as a more 
strongly^cohering group of elements, less strongly connected 
with other groups of this kind, questions like those above 
discussed will not arise, and research will have an unob- 
structed future. 
In his philosophical notes Lichtenberg says : " We 
important except what can be observed or is a datum for us, and 
everything hypothetical, metaphysical and superfluous, is to be 
eliminated, must reach the same conclusion. I think that a similar 
standpoint is to be ascribed to Avenarius, for in his Der menschliche 
Weltbegriff, p. 76, the following passages occur: "The brain is not 
the dwelling-place, seat or producer of thought ; it is not the instru- 
ment or organ, it is not the vehicle or substratum, etc., of thought." 
"Thought is not an indweller or command-giver, it is not a second 
half or aspect, etc., nor is it a product; it is not even a physiological 
function of the brain, nor is it a state of the brain at all. " I am not 
able or willing to subscribe to all that Avenarius says or to any inter- 
pretation of what he says, but still his conception seems to me to 
approximate very nearly to my own. The method which he terms, 
"The exclusion of introjection," is only a particular form of the 
elimination of the metaphysical. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 29 
become conscious of certain presentations that are not 
dependent upon us ; of others that we at least think 
are dependent upon us. Where is the border-line? We 
know only the existence of our sensations, presentations, 
and thoughts. We should say, // thinks, just as we 
say, // lightens. It is going too far to say cogito, if we 
translate cogito by / think. The assumption, or postula- 
tion, of the ego is a mere practical necessity." Though the 
method by which Lichtenberg arrived at this result is some- 
what different from ours, we must nevertheless give our full 
assent to his conclusion. 
Bodies do not produce sensations, but complexes 
of elements (complexes of sensations) make up bodies. 
If, to the physicist, bodies appear the real, abiding 
existences, whilst the " elements " are regarded merely as 
their evanescent, transitory appearance, the physicist for- 
gets, in the assumption cf such a view, that all bodies are 
but thought-symbols for complexes of elements (complexes 
of sensations). Here, too, the elements in question form 
the real, immediate, and ultimate foundation, which it is 
the task of physiologico-physical research to investigate. 
By the recognition of this fact, many points of physiology 
and physics assume more distinct and more economical 
forms, and many spurious problems are disposed of. 
For us, therefore, the world does not consist of 
mysterious entities, which by their interaction with 
another, equally mysterious entity, the ego, produce 
sensations, which alone are accessible. For us, colors, 
sounds, spaces, times, . . . are provisionally the ultimate 
3 o THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
elements, whose given connexion it is our business to 
investigate. 1 It is precisely in this that the exploration of 
1 I have always felt it as a stroke of special good fortune, that early in 
life, at about the age of fifteen, I lighted, in the library of my father, on 
a copy of Kant's Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics. The book 
made at the time a powerful and ineffaceable impression upon me, the 
like of which I never afterwards experienced in any of my philosophical 
reading. Some two or three years later the superfluity of the r61e 
played by "the thing in itself" abruptly dawned upon me. on a 
bright summer day in the open air, the world with my ego suddenly 
appeared to me as one coherent mass of sensations, only more strongly 
coherent in the ego. Although the actual working out of this thought 
did not occur until a later period, yet this moment was decisive for my 
whole view. I had still to struggle long and hard before I was able to 
retain the new conception in my special subject. With the valuable 
parts of physical theories we necessarily absorb a good dose of false 
metaphysics, which it is very difficult to sift out from what deserves to 
be preserved, especially when those theories have become very familiar 
to us. At times, too, the traditional, instinctive views would arise 
with great power and place impediments in my way. only by alternate 
studies in physics and in the physiology of the senses, and by historico- 
physical investigations (since about 1863), and after having endeavored 
in vain to settle the conflict by a physico-psychological monadology 
(in my lectures on psycho-physics, in the Zeitschrift fiir praktische 
Heilkunde, Vienna, 1863, p. 364), have I attained to any considerable 
stability in my views. I make no pretensions to the title of philosopher. 
I only seek to adopt in physics a point of view that need not be changed 
the moment our glance is carried over into the domain of another 
science ; for, ultimately, all must form one whole. The molecular 
physics of to-day certainly does not meet this requirement. What I 
say I have probably not been the first to say. I also do not wish to 
offer this exposition of mine as a special achievement. It is rather my 
belief that every one will be led to a similar view, who makes a 
careful survey of any extensive body of knowledge. Avenarius, with 
whose works I became acquainted in 1883, approaches my point of view 
(Philosophic als Denken der Welt nach dem Princip des kleinsten Kraft- 
masses^ 1876). Also Hering, in his paper on Memory {Almanack der 
Wiener Akademie, 1870, p. 258 ; English translation, O. C. Pub. Co., 
Chicago, 4th edition, enlarged, 1913), and J. Popper in his beautiful 
book, Das Rchte zu leben und die Pflicht zu sterben (Leipzig, 1878, p. 
62), have advanced allied thoughts. Compare also my paper Ueber 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 31 
reality consists. In this investigation we must not allow 
ourselves to be impeded by such abridgments and 
delimitations as body, ego, matter, spirit, etc., which have 
been formed for special, practical purposes and with 
wholly provisional and limited ends in view. on the 
contrary, the fittest forms of thought must be created in and 
by that research itself, just as is done in every special science. 
In place of the traditional, instinctive ways oif,4<hought, a 
freer, fresher view, conforming to developed experience, and 
reaching out beyond the requirements of practical life, must 
be substituted throughout. 
14. 
Science always has its origin in the adaptation of thought to 
some definite field of experience. The results of the adapta- 
tion are thought-elements, which are able to represent the 
whole field. The outcome, of course, is different, according 
to the character and extent of the field. If the field of 
experience is enlarged, or if several fields heretofore discon- 
nected are united, the traditional, familiar thought-elements 
no longer suffice for the extended field. In the struggle of 
acquired habit with the effort after adaptation, problems 
arise, which disappear when the adaptation is perfected, to 
make room for others which have arisen meanwhile. 
die okonomische Natur der physikalischen Forschung {Almanack der 
Wiener A kademie, 1882, p. 179, note ; English translation in my Popular 
Scientific Lectures, Chicago, 1894). Finally let me also refer here to 
the introduction to W. Preyer's Reine Empfindungshhre, to Riehl's 
Freiburger Antrittsrede, p. 40, and to R. Wahle's Gehirn und 
Bewusstsein, 1884. My views were indicated briefly in 1872 and 1875, 
and not expounded at length until 1882 and 1883. I should probably 
have much additional matter to cite as more or less allied to this line 
of thought, if my knowledge of the literature were more extensive. 
32 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
To the physicist, qua physicist, the idea of "body" is 
productive of a real facilitation of view, and is not the 
cause of disturbance. So, also, the person with purely 
practical aims, is materially supported by the idea of the 
/ or ego. For, unquestionably, every form of thought that 
has been designedly or undesignedly constructed for a 
given purpose, possesses for that purpose a permanent 
value. When, however, physics and psychology meet, the 
ideas held in the one domain prove to be untenable in the 
other. From the attempt at mutual adaptation arise the 
various atomic and monadistic theories which, however, 
never attain their end. If we regard sensations, in the 
sense above defined (p. 13), as the elements of the world, 
the problems referred to appear to be disposed of in all 
essentials, and the first and most important adaptation to 
be consequently effected. This fundamental view (without 
any pretension to being a philosophy for all eternity) can 
at present be adhered to in all fields of experience ; it is 
consequently the one that accommodates itself with the 
least expenditure of energy, that is, more economically 
than any other, to the present temporary collective state 
of knowledge Furthermore, in the consciousness of its 
purely economical function, this fundamental view is 
eminently tolerant. It does not obtrude itself into fields 
in which the current conceptions are still adequate. It 
is also ever ready, upon subsequent extensions of the 
field of experience, to give way before a better con- 
ception. 
The presentations and conceptions of the average man 
of the world are formed and dominated, not by the full 
and pure desire for knowledge as an end in itself, but by 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 33 
the struggle to adapt himself favourably to the conditions 
of life. Consequently they are less exact, but at the same 
time also they are preserved from the monstrosities which 
easily result from a one-sided and impassioned pursuit 
of a scientific or philosophical point of view. The unpre- 
judiced man of normal psychological development takes the 
elements which we have called A B C . . . to be spatially 
contiguous and external to the elements K L M . . ., 
and he holds this view immediately ', and not by any process 
of psychological projection or logical inference or construc- 
tion ; even were such a process to exist, he would certainly 
not be conscious of it. He sees, then, an "external 
world "ABC... different from his body K L M . . . 
and existing outside it. As he does not observe at first 
the dependence of the A B Cs . . . on the K L M's . . . 
(which are always repeating themselves in the same way 
and consequently receive little attention), but is always 
dwelling upon the fixed connexion of the A B Cs . . . 
with one another, there appears to him a world of things 
independent of his Ego. This Ego is formed by the 
observation of the special properties of the particular thing 
K L M . . . with which pain, pleasure, feeling, will, etc., 
are intimately connected. Further, he notices things 
K' L' M', K" L" M", which behave in a manner perfectly 
analogous to K L M, and whose behaviour he thoroughly 
understands as soon as he has thought of analogous feel- 
ings, sensations, etc., as attached to them in the same way 
as he observed these feelings, sensations, etc., to be 
attached to himself. The analogy impelling him to this 
result is the same as determines him, when he has 
observed that a wire possesses all the properties of a 
34 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
conductor charged with an electric current, except one 
which has not yet been directly demonstrated, to conclude 
that the wire possesses this one property as well. Thus, 
since he does not perceive the sensations of his fellow- 
men or of animals but only supplies them by analogy, 
while he infers from the behaviour of his fellow-men that 
they are in the same position over against himself, he is 
led to ascribe to the sensations, memories, etc., a particular 
ABC...KLM...viz. different nature, always 
differently conceived according to the degree of civilization 
he has reached ; but this process, as was shown above, is un- 
necessary, and in science leads into a maze of error, although 
the falsification is of small significance for practical life. 
These factors, determining as they do the intellectual 
outlook of the plain man, make their appearance alter- 
nately in him according to the requirements of practical 
life for the time being, and persist in a state of nearly 
stable equilibrium. The scientific conception of the world, 
however, puts the emphasis now upon one, now upon the 
other factor, makes sometimes one and sometimes the 
other its starting-point, and, in its struggle for greater pre- 
cision, unity and consistency, tries, so far as seems possible, 
to thrust into the background all but the most indispensable 
conceptions. In this way dualistic and monistic systems arise. 
The plain man is familiar with blindness and deafness, 
and knows from his everyday experience that the look of 
things is influenced by his senses ; but it never occurs to 
him to regard the whole world as the creation of his senses. 
He would find an idealistic system, or such a monstrosity as 
solipsism, intolerable in practice. 
It may easily become a disturbing element in unpre- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
35 
judiced scientific theorizing when a conception which is 
adapted to a particular and strictly limited purpose is 
promoted in advance to be the foundation of all investiga- 
tion. This happens, for example, when all experiences are 
regarded as " effects " of an external world extending into 
consciousness. This conception gives us a tangle of meta- 
physical difficulties which it seems impossible to unravel. 
But the spectre vanishes at once when we look at the 
matter as it were in a mathematical light, and make it clear 
to ourselves that all that is valuable to us is the' discovery 
of functional relations^ and that what we want to know is 
merely the dependence of experiences on one another. It 
then becomes obvious that the reference to unknown funda- 
mental variables which are not given (things-in-themselves) 
is purely fictitious and superfluous. But even when we 
allow this fiction, uneconomical though it be, to stand at 
first, we can still easily distinguish different classes of the 
mutual dependence of the elements of " the facts of con- 
sciousness " ; and this alone is important for us. 
ABC . . . . KLM . . . 
a/3 7 . . . 
K' L' M' . . . 
a'/3' 7 ' . . 
K" L" M" . . . 
a" /3V 
The system of the elements is indicated in the above 
scheme. Within the space surrounded by a single line lie 
the elements which belong to the sensible world, the 
elements whose regular connexion and peculiar dependence 
on one another represent both physical (lifeless) bodies and 
the bodies of men, animals and plants. All these elements, 
again, stand in a relation of quite peculiar dependence to 
36 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
certain of the elements K L M the nerves of our body, 
namely by which the facts of sense-physiology are 
expressed. The space surrounded by a double line con- 
tains the elements belonging to the higher psychic life, 
memory-images and presentations, including those which 
we form of the psychic life of our fellow-men. These may 
be distinguished by accents. These presentations, again, 
are connected with one another in a different way (associa- 
tion, fancy) from the sensational elements A B C . .'. 
K L M, but it cannot be doubted that they are very closely 
allied to the latter, and that in the last resort their behaviour 
is determined by A B C . . . K L M (the totality of the 
physical world), and especially by our body and nervous 
system. The presentations a! (3 f y r of the contents of the 
consciousness of our fellow-men play for us the part of 
intermediate substitutions, by means of which the behaviour 
of our fellow-men, the functional relation of K' L' M' to 
A B C becomes intelligible, in so far as in and for itself 
(physically) it would remain unexplained. 
It is therefore important for us to recognize that in all 
questions in this connexion, which can be intelligibly asked 
and which can interest us, everything turns on taking into 
consideration different ultimate variables and different 
relations of dependence. That is the main point. Nothing 
will be changed in the actual facts or in the functional 
relations, whether we regard all the data as contents of con- 
sciousness, or as partially so, or as completely physical. 1 
1 Cf. J. Petzoldt's excellent paper " Solipsismus auf praktischem 
Gebiet" ( Vierteljahrsschriftfiirwissentschaftliche Philosophic, XXXV. , 
3> P- 339) Schuppe, " Der Solipsismus" (Zeitschr fUr immanente 
Philosophie, Vol. III., p. 327). 
J 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 37 
The biological task of science is to provide the fully 
developed human individual with as perfect a. means of 
orientating himself as possible. No other scientific ideal 
can be realized, and any other must be meaningless. 
The philosophical point of view of the average man if 
that term may be applied to his naive realism has a claim 
to the highest consideration. It has arisen in the process of 
immeasurable time without the intentional assistance of man. 
It is a product of nature, and is preserved by nature. Every- 
thing that philosophy has accomplished though we may 
admit the biological justification of every advance, nay, of 
every error is, as compared with it, but an insignificant 
and ephemeral product of art. The fact is, every thinker, 
every philosopher, the moment he is forced to abandon his 
one-sided intellectual occupation by practical necessity, 
immediately returns to the general point of view of man- 
kind. Professor X., who theoretically believes himself to 
be a solipsist, is certainly not one in practice when he has 
to thank a Minister of State for a decoration conferred upon 
him, or when he lectures to an audience. The Pyrrhonist 
who is cudgelled in Moliere's Le Manage Forc'e^ does not go 
on saying " II me semble que vous me battez," but takes 
his beating as really received. 
Nor is it the purpose of these " introductory remarks " to 
discredit the standpoint of the plain man. The task which 
we have set ourselves is simply to show why and for what 
purpose we hold that standpoint during most of our lives, 
and why and for what purpose we are provisionally obliged 
to abandon it. No point of view has absolute, permanent 
validity. Each has importance only for some given end. 
II. on PRECONCEIVED OPINIONS 
i. 
THE physicist has frequent occasion to observe how 
greatly our knowledge of some field of research may 
be hampered, when, instead of the unprejudiced investiga- 
tion of that field for its own sake, views are transferred to it 
which have been formed in some other department of 
knowledge. Far more serious is the confusion which arises 
from such transference of preconceived opinions from the 
field of physics to that of psychology. Let us illustrate this 
by a few examples. 
A physicist observes the inverted image on the retina of 
an excised eye, and puts to himself very naturally the 
question, How does a point situated low down in space 
come to be reflected on the upper part of the retina ? He 
answers this question by the aid of studies in dioptrics. If, 
now, this question, which is perfectly legitimate in the 
province of physics, be transferred to the domain of 
psychology, only obscurity will be produced. The question 
why we see inverted retinal images the right way up, has no 
meaning as a psychological problem. The light-sensations 
of the separate spots of the retina are connected with space- 
sensations from the very outset, and we give the name 
" above " to those positions in space that correspond to the 
parts of the retina situated lower down. To the subject 
having the sensation such a question cannot present itself. 
38 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 39 
It is the same with the well-known theory of external 
projection. The problem of the physicist is, to find the 
luminous object-point corresponding to a point on the 
retinal image, by prolonging the ray that passes through the 
point on the image and the centre of the eye. For the 
subject having the sensation this problem does not exist, as 
the light sensations are connected from the beginning with 
determinate space-sensations. The entire theory of the 
psychological origin of the external world by the projection 
of sensations outwards is founded solely on a mistaken 
application of physical points of view. Our sensations of 
sight and touch are bound up with various different sensa- 
tions of space ; that is to say, they exist by the side of one 
another and outside one another, exist, in other words, in a 
spatial field, in which our body fills but a part. The table, 
the house, the tree, lie thus self-evidently outside my body. 
A projection-problem never presents itself, is neither 
consciously nor unconsciously solved. 
A physicist (Mariotte) discovers that a certain spot on 
the retina is blind. The physicist is accustomed to 
correlate with every spatial point a point on the retinal 
image, and with every point on the image a sensation. 
Hence the question arises, What do we see at the points 
corresponding to the blind spot, and how is the gap filled 
out ? When the illegitimate form of putting the question in 
physical terms is eliminated from the psychological inquiry, 
it will be found that no problem exists at all here. We see 
nothing at the blind spots, the gap in the image is not filled 
out, or rather, the gap is not felt, for the simple reason that 
a defect of light-sensation can no more be noticed at a spot 
blind from the beginning than the blindness, say, of 
40 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
the skin of the back can cause a gap in the visual 
field. 
I have intentionally chosen simple and obvious examples, 
as they can best make clear what unnecessary confusion is 
caused by the thoughtless transference of a conception or 
mode of thought, which is valid and serviceable in one field, 
into another quite different field. 
In the work of a celebrated German ethnographer I 
recently read the following sentence : " This tribe has 
become deeply degraded through the practice of canni- 
balism." By its side lay the book of an English inquirer 
who deals with the same subject. The latter simply puts 
the question why certain South-Sea Islanders are cannibals, 
finds out in the course of his inquiries that our own 
ancestors also were once cannibals, and comes to under- 
stand the position the Hindus take in the matter a point 
of view that occurred once to my five-year-old boy who 
while eating a piece of meat stopped, suddenly shocked, 
and cried out, " We are cannibals to the animals ! " 
" Thou shalt not eat human beings " is a very praiseworthy 
maxim ; but in the mouth of the ethnographer it destroys 
that mild and sublime glow of freedom from prepossession 
by which we delight to recognize the true inquirer. But a 
step further, and we shall say, " Man must not be descended 
from monkeys," <k The earth ought not to rotate," "Matter 
ought not to fill space continuously," " Energy must be 
constant," and so on. I believe that our procedure differs 
from that just characterized only in degree and not in kind, 
when we claim absolute validity for views reached in the 
field of physics, and transfer them to the field of psychology 
without having first tested their applicability. In such cases 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 41 
we succumb to dogma, if not, like our scholastic forefathers, 
to dogma forced upon us from without, yet to that which 
we have created ourselves. And what result of research is 
there that could not become a dogma by long habit ? The 
very skill which we have acquired to deal with constantly 
recurring intellectual situations deprives us of the freshness 
and open-mindedness which we so greatly need in new 
situations. 
After these general remarks, I may perhaps be able 
to explain my position with regard to the dualism of the 
physical and the psychical. This dualism is to my mind 
artificial and unnecessary. 
In the investigation of purely physical processes we 
generally employ concepts of so abstract a character 
that as a rule we think only cursorily, or not at all, 
of the sensations (elements) that lie at their base. For 
example, when I ascertain the fact that an electric current 
having the intensity of i ampere develops icj cubic 
centimetres of oxyhydrogen gas at o C. and 760 mm. 
mercury-pressure in a minute, I am readily disposed to 
attribute to the objects defined a reality wholly inde- 
pendent of my sensations. But I am obliged, in order 
to arrive at what I have defined, to conduct the current, 
for the existence of which my sensations are my only 
warrant, through a circular wire having a definite radius, 
so that the current, the intensity of terrestrial magnetism 
being given, shall turn the magnetic needle a certain 
angular distance out of the meridian. The determina- 
tion of the magnetic intensity, of the volume of the 
42 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
oxyhydrogen gas, etc., is no less intricate. The whole 
statement is based upon an almost unending series of 
sensations, particularly if we take into consideration the 
adjustment of the apparatus, which must precede the 
actual experiment. Now it can easily happen to the 
physicist who does not study the psychology of his 
operations, that he does not (to reverse a well-known 
saying) see the trees for the wood, that he overlooks 
the sensory elements at the foundation of his work. 
Now I maintain that every physical concept means 
nothing but a certain definite kind of connexion of the 
sensory elements which I have denoted by A B C. . . . 
These elements elements in the sense that no further 
resolution has as yet been made of them are the 
simplest materials out of which the physical, and also 
the psychological, world is built up. 
Physiological research also may be of a purely physical 
character. I can follow the course of a physical process 
as it propagates itself through a sensitive nerve to the 
central organ ; I can thence trace it by various paths to 
the muscles, whose contraction produces new physical 
changes in the environment. In so doing I am precluded 
from thinking of any sensation felt by the man or animal 
under observation ; what I am investigating is a purely 
physical object. Very much is lacking, it is true, to our 
complete comprehension of the details of this process, 
and the assurance that everything depends on "the 
motion of molecules " can neither console me nor deceive 
me with respect to my ignorance. 
Long prior to the development of a scientific psychology 
people had nevertheless perceived that the behaviour of 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 43 
an animal under physical influences can be predicted 
with much greater accuracy, i.e., can be better under- 
stood, if we attribute to the animal sensations and 
memories like our own. To that which I observe, to my 
sensations, I have to supply mentally the sensations of 
the animal, which are not to be found in the field of 
my own sensations. This antithesis appears even more 
abrupt to the scientific inquirer who is investigating a 
nervous process by the aid of colorless abstract concepts, 
and is required, for example, to add mentally to that 
process the sensation green. This last may actually 
appear as something entirely new and strange, and we 
ask ourselves how it is that this miraculous thing is 
produced from chemical processes, electrical currents, 
and the like. 
Psychological analysis has taught us that this surprise 
is unjustifiable, since the physicist is always operating 
with sensations. The same analysis also shows us that 
the process of mentally supplementing complexes of 
sensations according to analogy by means of elements 
which at the moment are not being observed, or by 
elements which cannot possibly be observed, is one 
which is daily practised by the physicist ; as, for example, 
when he imagines the moon a tangible, inert, heavy 
mass. The totally strange character of the intellectual 
situation above described is therefore an illusion. 
There is also another consideration, a consideration 
confined to my own sensory sphere, which serves to 
dispel the illusion. Before me lies the leaf of a plant. 
44 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
The green (A) of the leaf is connected with a certain 
optical sensation of space (B)> with a sensation of touch 
(C), and with the visibility of the sun or the lamp (Z>). 
If the yellow (JE) of a sodium flame takes the place of 
the sun, the green (A) will pass into brown (F). If the 
chlorophyl granules be removed by alcohol, an operation 
which can be represented, like the preceding one, by 
elements, the green (A) will pass into white (G). All 
these observations are physical observations. But the 
green (A) is also connected with a certain process of my 
retina. There is nothing to prevent me in principle from 
investigating this process in my own eye in exactly the 
same manner as in the previous cases, and from reducing 
it to its elements X Y Z . . . If there are difficulties in 
doing this for my own eye, it can be done with some one 
else's eye, and the gap filled out by analogy, exactly as in 
other physical investigations. Now in its dependence 
upon BCD. . . ., A is a physical element, in its depend- 
ence on X Y Z . . . it is a sensation, and can also be 
considered as a psychical element. The green (A), 
however, is not altered at all in itself, whether we direct 
our attention to the one or to the other form of depend- 
ence. I see, therefore, no opposition of physical and 
psychical, but simple identity as regards these elements. 
In the sensory sphere of my consciousness everything is 
at once physical and psychical (cp. p. 17). 
4- 
The obscurity of this intellectual situation has, I take it, 
arisen solely from the transference of a physical preposses- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 45 
sion to the field of psychology. The physicist says : I 
find everywhere bodies and the motions of bodies only, 
no sensations ; sensations, therefore, must be something 
entirely different from the physical objects I deal with. 
The psychologist accepts the second portion of this 
declaration. For him, as is proper, sensations are the 
primary data ; but to these there corresponds a mysterious 
physical something which, conformably with the pre- 
possession, must be quite different from sensations. But 
what is it that is the really mysterious thing ? Is it the 
Physis or the Psyche ? Or is it perhaps both ? It would 
almost appear so, as it is now the one and now the other 
that appears unattainable and involved in impenetrable 
obscurity. Or are we here being led round in a circle by 
some evil spirit ? > 
I believe that the latter is the case. For me the 
elements A B C ... are immediately and indubitably 
given, and for me they can never afterwards be volatilized 
away by considerations which ultimately are always based 
on their existence. 
The task of specialized investigation in the sensory 
physico-psychical sphere, which has not been made 
superfluous by this general survey, is to ascertain the 
peculiar method of combination of the A B C s. This 
may be expressed symbolically by saying that it is the 
object of special research to find equations of the form 
f(AB C . . .) = o(zero). 
III. MY RELATION TO RICHARD 
AVENARIUS AND OTHER 
THINKERS. 
i. 
I HAVE already alluded to points at which the views 
here advocated are in touch with those of various 
philosophers and philosophically inclined scientists. A 
full enumeration of these points of contact would require 
me to begin with Spinoza. That my starting-point is not 
essentially different from Hume's is of course obvious. I 
differ from Comte in holding that the psychological facts 
are, as sources of knowledge, at least as important as the 
physical facts. My position, moreover, borders closely on 
that of the representatives of the philosophy of immanence. 
This is especially true in the case of Schuppe, with whose 
writings I became acquainted in 1902 ; his Outline of 
Theory of Knoiuledge and Logic, a work which is packed 
with thought and which can be read without a special 
dictionary, struck a particularly sympathetic chord in me. 
In this book I have found scarcely anything to which, 
perhaps with some small modification, I cannot yield a 
hearty assent. To be sure, his conception of the Ego 
constitutes a point of difference between us ; but not a 
point on which it would be hopeless to reach an under- 
standing. As to the views of Avenarius, the affinity 
between them and my own is as great as can possibly be 
46 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 47 
imagined where two writers have undergone a different 
process of development, work in different fields, and are 
completely independent of one another. The agreement 
is somewhat obscured by the great difference of form. 
Avenarius presents us with a scheme, exhaustive indeed 
but highly generalized, which is made more difficult to 
grasp by a strange and unfamiliar terminology. For con- 
structions of this kind I had neither occasion nor vocation, 
neither inclination nor talent; I am a scientist and not 
a philosopher. What I aimed at was merely to attain a 
safe and clear philosophical standpoint, whence practicable 
paths, shrouded in no metaphysical clouds, might be seen 
leading not only into the field of physics but also into that 
of psycho-physiology. With the attainment of this, my 
battle was won. Although my theory is the fruit of long 
years of meditation from earliest youth upwards, yet in its 
brevity it has the form of a mere aperfu, nor shall I be 
offended if it is regarded in that light. I willingly admit 
that in my distaste for an artificial terminology I have 
perhaps fallen into the opposite extreme to that of Avenarius. 
While Avenarius is often not to be understood, or only 
to be understood after much study, my words have often 
enough been misunderstood. one acute critic considers 
that many of my results are results which I ought not to 
have reached (he is therefore in a position to save himself 
the trouble of investigation, since he already knows the 
results to which investigation ought to lead), and proceeds 
to reproach me with being difficult to place, since I use 
ordinary language, and it is consequently impossible to see 
to what "system" I adhere. Thus, first and foremost, 
you have to choose a system ; then within the walls of that 
48 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
system you may think and speak. In this way all kinds 
of current popular views have been comfortably read into 
my words ; I have been accused of idealism, Berkeleyanism, 
even of materialism, and of other " -isms," of all of which 
I believe myself to be innocent. 
The fact is that each of the two methods of exposition 
has its advantages and disadvantages. But the difference 
of form has had a prejudicial effect also on the mutual 
understanding between Avenarius and myself. I recognized 
the affinity between our views at a very early stage, and 
expressed my conviction of it in the Mechanik (1883) and 
in the first edition of this book (1886), although at that 
time I was only able to refer to one of Avenarius' minor 
works (Denken der Welt nach dem Prinzip des kleinsten 
J^ra/f masses), which had appeared in 1876 and had acci- 
dentally come in my way shortly before the publication of 
my Mechanik. It was only in 1888, 1891, and 1894, 
by means of Avenarius' publications, Kritik der reinen 
Erfahrung, Der menschliche Weltbegriff, and his psycho- 
logical articles in the Vierteljahrsschrift, that the similarity 
of our tendencies was fully revealed to me. As to the 
first of these works, however, its somewhat hypermeta- 
phorical terminology prevented me from tasting the full 
rapture of agreement. It is asking rather much of an 
elderly man that to the labour of learning the languages of 
the nations he should add that of learning the language of 
an individual. It was consequently reserved for the 
younger generation to turn the work of Avenarius to 
good use : in this connexion I am glad to be able to refer 
to the writings of H. Cornelius, C. Hauptmann and J. 
Petzoldt, which are in a fair way to bring to light and 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 49 
to develop further the real value of Avenarius' work. 
Avenarius, too, acknowledged on his side the affinity 
between us, and noticed it in the books that appeared 
from 1888 to 1895. Yet with him, too, the conviction of 
a profounder coincidence of view between us seems, as 
I am forced to infer from remarks made by him in the 
past to third persons, only to have been developed 
gradually. The man himself I have never known person- 
ally. Unmistakable efforts are being made to minimize 
his importance, but, in spite of that, acquaintance with 
his works is, I am glad to say, on the increase, 
2. 
I should now like to indicate more particularly those 
points of agreement between us to which I attach import- 
ance. The economy of thought, the economical repre- 
sentation of the actual, this was indicated by me, in 
summary fashion first in 1871 and 1872, as being the 
essential task of science, and in 1882 and 1883 I gave 
considerably enlarged expositions of this idea. As I have 
shewn elsewhere, this conception, which implicitly contains 
and anticipates KirchhofPs notion of "perfectly simple 
description" (1874), was by no means quite new; it can 
be traced back to Adam Smith, and, as P. Volkmann holds, 
in its beginnings even to Newton. We find the same con- 
ception again, with the exception of one feature that does 
not come out clearly, fully developed in Avenarius (1876). 
A broad foundation is laid for the theory in question, 
and light is shed upon it from new sides, if, in conformity 
with the stimulus given by Darwinism, we conceive of all 
50 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
psychical life including science as biological appearance, 
and if we apply to the theory the Darwinian conceptions of 
struggle for existence, of development, and of selection. 
The theory is inseparable from the hypothesis that each 
and every psychical entity is physically founded and 
determined. Now, in his Kritik der reinen Erfahrung, 
Avenarius tries to shew in detail that all theoretical and 
practical activity is determined by change in the central 
nervous system. In doing this he is merely basing him- 
self on the very general assumption that the central organ 
is subject to an impulse of self-preservation, a tendency to 
maintain its equilibrium, not only as a whole, but also in 
its parts. This agrees very well with the conceptions 
developed by Hering as to the behaviour of living sub- 
stance. In holding these views, Avenarius is brought into 
close contact with modern positive research, particularly 
in physiology. In my writings too, opinions of a corre- 
sponding nature, briefly indeed, but definitely expressed, 
appeared as long ago as 1863, and in 1883 I expounded 
these opinions at greater length, though without develop- 
ing a complete system, such as we find in Avenarius. 
But it is to our agreement in the conception of the 
relation between the physical and the psychical that I 
attach the greatest importance. For me this is the main 
point at issue. It was by means of his psychological 
articles that I first became convinced of this coincidence 
between Avenarius and myself. In order to be sure of 
making no mistake, I addressed an inquiry on the subject 
to Dr. Rudolf Wlassak, who I knew would be intimately 
acquainted with Avenarius' standpoint, thanks to his associa- 
tion with him for many years. His reply was as follows : 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 51 
"The conception of the relation of 'the physical' to 
* the psychical ' is identical in Avenarius and Mach. Both 
come to the conclusion that the difference between the 
physical and the psychical consists solely in the difference 
of the relations of dependence, which on the one hand are 
the objects dealt with by Physics (in the widest sense of 
the word), and on the other are the objects dealt with by 
psychology. If I investigate the dependence of one con- 
stituent (A) of an environment on another constituent () 
of an environment, I am studying physics ; if I inquire to 
what extent A is changed by a change in the sense-organs 
or the central nervous system, I am studying psychology. 
Avenarius has accordingly proposed to abolish the terms 
' physical ' and ' psychical ' and in future only to speak of 
physical and psychological dependencies ("Observations," 
Vierteljahrsschrift) xix., p. 18). In Mach's work the same 
view occurs, except that (?) the untenability of the old 
conception of the psychical, and consequently of the proper 
task of psychology, is not demonstrated. 
" This task is performed by the exposure of ' Introjection/ 
or rather of the fallacy in formal logic which underlies 
introjection. Avenarius starts from the fact that naive 
realism, 'the natural view of the world,' stands at the 
beginning of all philosophizing. Within the limits of this 
natural view of the world it is possible for a relative 
delimitation of the complex 'self and the complex 'en- 
vironment ' to be carried out without necessarily involving 
the 'dualism' of 'body' and 'soul,' since, from the 
standpoint of naive realism, the constituents that belong to 
the 'self,' to one's own body, are through and through 
comparable with the constituents of the environment. 
52 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Even when the preliminary survey has advanced to the 
formation of concepts of substance (Mach, Analysts of 
Sensations^ p. 5), this does not mean that a complete and 
essential difference between body and soul is given. The 
final splitting up of the world, originally conceived by naive 
realism as a unity, is really occasioned, according to 
Avenarius, by the interpretation of the utterances of our 
fellow-men. As long as I say, ' the tree does not exist for 
me alone ; it also, as their utterances permit me to assume, 
exists for my fellow-men mthe same way as it exists for me,' 
I am in no wise overstepping the analogy which formal 
logic allows between me and my fellow-men. But I am 
overstepping this analogy, if I say that the tree exists as 
* a copy,' ( a sensation ' or ' a presentation ' in my fellow- 
men, if I introduce or introject the tree ; since I am then 
assuming something for my fellow-men which I cannot dis- 
cover in my own experience, which always shews me the 
constituents of my environment as standing in a definite 
relation to my body, and never as being in my consciousness 
or the like. Inasmuch as introjection is a way of passing 
beyond experience, every attempt to bring it into harmony 
with the facts of experience must become an inexhaustible 
' source of pseudo-problems. This is most clearly seen in 
the different forms which, in the course of the history of 
philosophy, introjection has assumed. The oldest and 
crudest theories of perception exhibited it in its crudest and 
simplest form ; they supposed that copies were detached from 
objects, and that these copies penetrated within the body. 
Now in so far as it is recognized that the constituents of the 
environment are not present inside the body in the same 
way as they are present outside it, to that extent they are 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 53 
bound, the moment they are inside it, to become something 
essentially different from the environment. The root of 
dualism lies in the extension of introjection, in the attempt to 
bring it into harmony with the complex of the environment. 
" It may be doubted whether Avenarius' account of the 
motives for introjection is satisfactory in all cases. He 
holds that introjection is always connected with the ex- 
planation of the * perceptions ' of one's fellow-men. But 
it might well be urged that the fact that one and the same 
constituent of the environment is at one time given in 
sensations as a 'thing,' and at another given as a memory, 
can be sufficient motive for conceiving this constituent as 
being present twice over, namely, first ' materially ' in the 
environment, and secondly in my 'consciousness,' in my 
* soul.' Another point to be considered is, whether dream- 
experiencies cannot equally constitute, at a primitive stage 
of culture, an independent motive for dualism. 1 Avenarius, 
indeed, represents introjection as the presupposition of the 
dualist's interpretation of dream-experiences, but without 
adducing conclusive reasons. But it is not justifiable to 
regard prehistoric animism as the root of dualism, if by 
' animism ' we understand merely the hypothesis that all 
the lifeless constituents of our environment are beings like 
ourselves. As long as deeper-lying physiological reasons 
do not make it impossible, the * natural view of the world ' 
can also provide a foundation for the hypothesis that, in 
the case of the tree, for example, the constituents of its 
environment exist for it in the same sense as they do for 
human beings. In other words : Anyone who held the 
1 According to Tylor, they are in fact one of the strongest motives 
(Mach). 
54 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
view of the psychical common to Avenarius and Mach, 
might, if he were entirely ignorant of physiology, suppose 
that a tree or a stone touches and sees its environment. 
In that case he would still not be a dualist. He only 
becomes a dualist when, in order to explain this touching 
and seeing on the part of the tree or stone, he assumes that 
the constituents of the environment, which the tree and 
stone taste and see, are present over again in the tree as its 
' sensations ' or its ' consciousness/ It is only then that 
the world is duplicated by division into a spiritual part and 
a material part. 
" The discovery of the illegitimacy of introjection throws 
light in two directions. on the one hand it is illuminating 
on the side of theory of knowledge. All problems con- 
nected with the relation of our 'sensations,' 'presenta- 
tions ' and ' contents of consciousness ' to the material 
things, of which the above-mentioned products of intro- 
jection are supposed to be the 'copies,' 'signs,' and so 
forth, are seen to be merely illusory. Instances of such 
pseudo-problems are the problems as to projection which 
we meet in theories of space, the exteriorization of the 
space-sensations, etc. 
" on the other hand, the elimination of introjection implies 
that all psychology which is not physiological is illegitimate. 
When I have recognized that the ' contents of conscious- 
ness,' the 'psychic processes,' which accompany changes 
in the nervous system, are nothing more than constituents 
of my environment which I have introduced into my fellow- 
men and ultimately also into myself, it is impossible for 
me to look for anything in the nervous system except 
physiological processes. All special psychical causality 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 55 
disappears ; all those problems disappear which are con- 
nected with the question whether the intervention of 
psychical forces in the physiological processes of the brain 
is compatible with the principle of the conservation of 
energy. 1 
" When such a phrase is used as ' the continued existence 
of presentations without their being in consciousness ' 
(Mach, Wdrmekhre p. 441), this is, strictly speaking, only 
legitimate as an abbreviated expression for particular 
processes of the central nervous system, and in any case it 
savours strongly of dualistic conceptions." 
The remaining difference between the way in which 
Avenarius puts his views and the way in which I put mine 
can be reduced to elements which are easily grasped. In 
the first place, it was not my intention to give a complete 
exposition of the development of my point of view out 
of the preceding phrases of philosophical reflection about 
the world. In the second place, Avenarius starts from a 
1 I cannot refrain from here expressing my surprise that the principle 
of the conservation of energy has so often been dragged in in connexion 
with the question whether there is a special psychical agent. on the 
assumption that energy is constant, the course of physical processes is 
limited, but not necessarily determined with perfect uniqueness. That 
the principle of conservation of energy is satisfied in all physiological 
cases, merely tells us that the soul neither uses up work nor performs 
it. For all that, the soul may still be a partly determinant factor. 
When the philosopher asks a question which has reference to this case, 
he usually misses the point of the principle of the conservation of 
energy, and the stock reply of the physicist has no intelligible meaning 
in relation to a case so far removed from the scope of his ideas. Cp. 
the references to a similar discussion in Hofler's Psychologic, 1897, 
pp. 58 sqq., note. Apart from the above considerations, the assump- 
tion of a special psychical agent appears to me to be a presupposition 
which is unfortunate and can only do harm by making investigation 
difficult ; it is moreover unnecessary and improbable (Mach). 
56 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
realistic phase ; I, on the other hand, started from an idealist 
phase (p. 30, above, footnote), such as I actually went 
through in my early youth. In that way I might easily have 
talked, for instance, about the elimination of " extrajection " 
(pp. 6, 12-22, 29-35, 43> above). In the third place, it is 
not necessary to attribute so important a role to the inter- 
pretation of our fellow-men by means of introjection in the 
bad sense, until after the new standpoint has been reached \ 
and then it is also not necessary to exclude this introjection 
again. A solitary thinker might reach the new standpoint, 
and even he, as Wlassak observes, might have to rise 
superior to dualistic tendencies. But this standpoint once 
reached, and the varying character of the dependence . of 
the elements once recognized as the essential point, the 
question whether we start from a phase of realism or of 
idealism is of no greater importance for us than a change 
in the fundamental variables of his equations is for the 
mathematician or physicist. 
What Avenarius puts forward, and consequently what I 
also put forward, appears to me to contain scarcely any- 
thing that is not self-evident self-evident at least for every 
man who has shaken himself free from the pressure of " the 
legacy of wild philosophy," as Tylor calls it. Science has 
always required such self-evident propositions as a safe 
foundation upon which to build. When I see the paths 
pursued by different philosophical thinkers converging, and 
especially when I contemplate the close coincidence 
between general philosophical views and the views of 
scientific specialists, I think that I am justified in detecting 
here a hopeful presage of the mutual accommodation of 
the sciences to one another. 
IV. THE CHIEF POINTS OF VIEW 
FOR THE INVESTIGATION OF 
THE SENSES. 
i. 
IN order to get our bearings, we will now try to obtain, 
from the standpoint we have reached, a broad view 
of the special problems that will engage our attention. 
When once the inquiring intellect has formed, through 
adaptation, the habit of connecting two things, A and 
B , in thought, it tries to retain this habit as far as pos- 
sible, even where the circumstances are slightly altered. 
Wherever A appears, B is added in thought. The prin- 
ciple thus expressed, which has its root in an effort for 
economy, and is particularly noticeable in the work of the 
great investigators, may be termed the principle of continuity . 
Every actually observed variation in the connexion of A 
and B which is sufficiently large to be noticed makes itself 
felt as a disturbance of the above-mentioned habit, and 
continues to do so until the habit is sufficiently modified 
to prevent the disturbance being felt. Suppose, for in- 
stance, that we have become accustomed to seeing light 
deflected when it impinges on the boundary between air and 
glass. But these deflections vary noticeably in different 
tiases, and the habit formed by observing some cases 
cannot be transferred undisturbed to new cases, until we 
are able to associate with every particular angle of in- 
cidence (A) a particular angle of refraction (B\ which we 
57 
58 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
are able to do by discovering the so-called law of refraction, 
and by making ourselves familiar with- the rules contained 
in that law. Thus another and modifying principle con- 
fronts that of continuity ; we will call it the principle of 
sufficient determination, or sufficient differentiation. 
The joint action of the two principles may be very well 
illustrated by a further analysis of the example cited. In 
order to deal with the phenomena exhibited in the change 
of color of light, the idea of the law of refraction must be 
retained, but with every particular color a particular index 
of refraction must be associated. We soon perceive that 
with every particular temperature also, a particular index of 
refraction must be associated ; and so on. 
In the end, this process leads to temporary contentment and 
satisfaction, the two things A and B being conceived as so con- 
nected that to every change of the one that can be observed at 
any moment there corresponds an appropriate change of the 
other. It may happen that both A and B are conceived as 
complexes of components, and that to every particular com- 
ponent ofAa. particular component of B corresponds. This 
occurs, for example, when B is a spectrum, and A the cor- 
responding sample of a compound to be tested, in which case 
to every component part of the spectrum one of the com- 
ponents of the matter volatilized before the spectroscope is 
correlated, independently of the others. only through com- 
plete familiarity with this relation can the principle of sufficient 
determination be satisfied. 
2. 
Suppose, now, that we are considering a color-sensation 
B, not in its dependence on A, the heated matter tested, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 59 
but in its dependence on the elements of the retinal process, 
N. By doing this we change, not the kind, but only the direc- 
tion of our point of view. None of the preceding observations 
lose their force, and the principles to be followed remain the 
same. And this holds good, of course, of all sensations. 
Now, sensation may be analysed in itself, immediately, 
that is, psychologically (which was the course adopted by 
Johannes Millie r), or the physical (physiological) processes 
correlated with it may be investigated according to the 
methods of physics (the course usually preferred by the 
modern school of physiologists), or, finally, the connexion 
of psychologically observable data with the corresponding 
physical (physiological) processes may be followed up a 
mode of procedure which will carry us farthest, since in this 
method observation is directed to all sides, and one investi- 
gation serves to support the other. We shall endeavor to 
attain this last-named end wherever it appears practicable. 
This being our object, then, it is evident that the principle 
of continuity and that of sufficient determination can be satis- 
fied only on the condition that with the same B (this or that 
sensation) we always associate the same N (the same nerve- 
process) and discover for every observable change of B a cor- 
responding change of N. \iB is psychologically analysable 
into a number of independent components, then we shall rest 
satisfied only on the discovery, in N, of equivalent components 
corresponding to these. If, on the other hand, properties or 
aspects have to be noticed in B which cannot appear in isola- 
tion, as, for instance, pitch and intensity in tones, we shall 
have to expect the same state of things in N. In a word, 
for all psychically observable details of B we have to seek 
the correlated physical details of N. 
60 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
I do not of course maintain that a (psychologically) 
simple sensation cannot also be conditioned by very 
complicated circumstances. For the circumstances would 
hang together like the links of a chain and would not issue 
in a sensation, unless the chain extended to the nerve. 
But since the sensation may also appear in the form of a 
hallucination, namely when no physically conditioned 
circumstances are present outside the body, we see that a 
certain nervous process, as the final link in the chain, is 
the essential and immediate condition of the sensation. 
Now we cannot think of this immediate condition as 
being varied without conceiving of the sensation as being 
varied, and vice versa. For the connexion between this final 
link and the sensation we will regard the principle which 
we have laid down as valid. 
We may thus establish a guiding principle for the 
investigation of the sensations. This may be termed the 
principle of the complete parallelism of the psychical and 
physical. According to our fundamental conception, which 
recognizes no gulf between the two provinces (the 
psychical and the physical), this principle is almost a matter 
of course ; but we may also enunciate it, as I did years ago, 
without the help of this fundamental conception, as a 
heuristic principle of research. 1 
The principle of which I am here making use goes further 
than the widespread general belief that a physical entity cor- 
responds to every psychical entity and vice versa ; it is much 
1 Compare ifiy paper, Ueber die Wirkung der raumlichen Vertheilung 
des Lichtreizes aufdie Netzhaut (Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akadamie, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 61 
more specialized. The general belief in question has been 
proved to be correct in many cases, and may be held to be pro- 
bably correct in all cases ; it constitutes moreover the neces- 
sary presupposition of all exact research. At the same time 
the view here advocated is different from Fechner's concep- 
tion of the physical and psychical as two different aspects 
of one and the same reality. In the first place, our view 
has no metaphysical background, but corresponds only 
to the generalized expression of experiences. Again, we 
refuse to distinguish two different aspects of an unknown 
tertium quid ; the elements given in experience, whose con- 
nexion we are investigating, are always the same, and 
are of only one nature, though they appear, according to 
the nature of the connexion, at one moment as physical 
and at another as psychical elements. 1 I have been asked 
whether the parallelism between psychical and physical is 
not meaningless and a mere tautology, if the psychical and 
physical are not regarded as essentially different. The 
question arises from a misunderstanding of the analysis 
which I have given above. When I see a green leaf (an 
Vol. LIL, 1865) ; further Reichert's und Dtibois' Archiv, 1865, p. 634, 
and Grundlinien der Lehre von den Bewegimgsempfindungen (Leipzig, 
Engelmann, 1875, p. 63). The principle is also implicitly contained in 
an article of mine in Fichte's Zeitschrift filr Philosophic (Vol. XLVI., 
1865, p. 5), which is printed also in my Popular Scientific Lectures , 
Chicago, Open Court Publishing Co. 
1 For the various aspects of the problem of parallelism, see C. 
Stumpf's address to the Psychological Congress at Munich (Munich, 
1897); G. Heymans, "Zur Parallelismusfrage," Zeitschrift filr 
Psychologie der Sinnesorgane, Vol. XVII. ; O. Kiilpe, Ueber die Bezie- 
hung z-wischen kb'rpcrlichen und seelischen Vorgangen, Zeitschrift fur 
Hypnotismus, Vol. VII., J. von Kries, Uber die materiellen Grund- 
lagen der Bewiisstseinserscheimmgen^ Freiburg im Breisgau, 1898; C. 
Hauptmann, Die Metaphysik in der Psychologie ', Dresden, 1893. 
62 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
event which is conditioned by certain brain-processes) the 
leaf is of course different in its form and color from the 
forms, colors, etc., which I discover in investigating a 
brain, although all forms, colors, etc., are of like nature 
in themselves, being in themselves neither psychical nor 
physical. The leaf which I see, considered as dependent 
on the brain-process, is something psychical, while this 
brain-process itself represents, in the connexion of its 
elements, something physical. And the principle of 
parallelism holds good for the dependence of the former 
immediately given group of elements on the latter group, 
which is only ascertained by means of a physical 
investigation which may be extremely complicated (cp. 
p. 44). 
I have perhaps stated the principle in rather too abstract 
a form. A few concrete examples may now help to explain 
it. Wherever I have a sensation of space, whether through 
the sensation of sight or through that of touch, or in 
any other way, I am obliged to assume the presence of 
a nerve-process of the same kind in all cases. For all 
time-sensations, also, I must suppose like nerve-processes. 
If I see figures which are the same in size and shape 
but differently colored, I seek, in connexion with the 
different color-sensations, certain identical space-sensations 
and corresponding identical nerve - processes. If two 
figures are similar (that is, if they yield partly identical 
space-sensations) then the corresponding nerve-processes 
also contain partly identical components. If two different 
melodies have the same rhythm, then, side by side with 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 63 
the different tone-sensations there exists in both cases an 
identical time-sensation with identical corresponding nerve- 
processes. If two melodies of different pitch are identical, 
then the tone-sensations as well as their physiological con- 
ditions, have, in spite of the different pitch, identical 
constituents. If the seemingly limitless multiplicity of 
color-sensations is susceptible of being reduced, by psycho- 
logical analysis (self-observation), to six elements (funda- 
mental sensations), a like simplification may be expected 
for the system of nerve-processes. If our system of space- 
sensations appears in the character of a threefold manifold, 
the system of the correlated nerve-processes will likewise 
present itself as such. 
This principle has, moreover, always been more or less 
consciously, more or less consistently, followed. 
For example, when Helmholtz 1 assumes for every tone- 
sensation a special nerve-fibre (with its appurtenant nerve- 
process), when he resolves clangs, or compound sounds, 
into tone - sensations, when he reduces the affinity of 
compound tones to the presence of like tone-sensations 
(and nerve-processes), we have in this method of procedure a 
practical illustration of our principle. It is only the applica- 
tion that is not complete, as will be later shown. Brewster, 2 
1 Helmholtz, Die Lehre von den Tonempfimkingen, Brunswick, 
Vieweg, 1863. English translation by Alex. J. Ellis, London, 
Longmans, Green, & Co., 2nd edition, 1885. 
2 Brewster, A Treatise on Optics, London, 1831. Brewster regarded 
the red, yellow, and blue light as extending over the whole solar 
spectrum, though distributed there with varying intensity, so that, 
to the eye, red appears at both ends (the red and the violet), yellow 
in the middle, and blue at the end of greater refrangibility, 
64 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
guided by a psychological but defective analysis of color- 
sensations, and by imperfect physical experiments, 1 was 
led to the view that, corresponding to the three sensations, 
red, yellow, and blue, there existed likewise physically 
only three kinds of light, and that, therefore, Newton's 
assumption of an unlimited number of kinds of light, with 
a continuous series of refractive indices, was erroneous. 
Brewster might easily fall into the error of regarding green 
as a compound sensation. But had he reflected that color- 
sensations may occur entirely without physical light, he 
would have confined his conclusions to the nerve-process 
and left untouched Newton's assumptions in the province of 
physics, which are as well founded as his own. Thomas 
Young corrected this error, at least in principle. He 
perceived that an unlimited number of kinds of physical 
light with a continuous series of refractive indices (and wave- 
lengths) was compatible with a small number of color- 
sensations and nerve-processes, that a discrete number of 
color-sensations did answer to the continuum of deflexions 
in the prism (to the continuum of the space-sensations). 
But even Young did not apply the principle with full 
consciousness or strict consistency, wholly apart from the 
fact that he allowed himself to be misled, in his psycho- 
logical analysis, by physical prejudices. Even he first 
assumed, as fundamental sensations, red, yellow, and blue, 
for which he later substituted red, green, and violet 
misled, as Alfred Mayer, of Hoboken, has admirably 
1 Brewster believed that he was able to alter by absorption the 
nuances of the spectrum colors regarded by Newton as simple 
a result which, if correct, would really destroy the Newtonian con- 
ception. He experimented, however, as Helmholtz (Physiological 
Optics) has shown, with an impure spectrum. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 65 
shown, 1 by a physical error of Wollaston's. The direction 
in which the theory of color- sensation, which has reached a 
high degree of perfection through Hering, has still to be 
modified, was pointed out by me many years ago in 
another place. 
6. 
Here I will merely state shortly what I have to say 
concerning the treatment of the theory of color-sensation. 
We frequently meet with the assertion, in recent works, that 
1 Philosophical Magazine, February 1876, p. in. Wollaston was 
the first to notice (1802) the dark lines of the spectrum, later named 
after Fraunhofer, and believed that he saw his narrow spectrum divided 
by the strongest of these lines into a red, a green, and a violet part. 
He regarded these lines as the dividing lines of the physical colors. 
Young took up this conception, and substituted for his fundamental 
sensations red, yellow, and blue, the colors red, green, and violet. 
Thus, in his first conception, Young regarded green as a composite 
sensation, in his second, both green and violet as simple. The question- 
able results which psychological analysis may thus yield, are well 
calculated to destroy belief in its usefulness in general. But we must 
not forget that there is no principle in the application of which error is 
excluded. Here, too, practice must determine. The circumstance 
that the physical conditions of sensation almost always give rise to 
composite sensations, and that the components of sensation seldom 
make their appearance separately, renders psychological analysis very 
difficult. Thus, green is a simple sensation ; a given pigment or 
spectrum-green, however, will as a rule excite also a concomitant 
yellow or blue sensation, and thus favor the erroneous idea (based 
upon the results of pigment-mixing) that the sensation of green is 
compounded of yellow and blue. Careful physical study, therefore, is 
also an indispensable requisite of psychological analysis. on the other 
hand, physical observation must not be overestimated. The mere 
observation that a yellow and blue pigment mixed, yield a green pig- 
ment, cannot by itself determine us to see yellow and blue in green, 
unless one or the other color is actually contained in it. Certainly no 
one sees yellow and blue in white, although, as a fact, spectrum-yellow 
and spectrum-blue mixed give white. 
B 
66 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
the six fundamental color-sensations, white, black, red, 
green, yellow, blue, which Hering adopted, were first 
proposed by Leonardo da Vinci, and later by Mach and 
Aubert. From the very first it seemed to me highly 
probable, in view of the conceptions prevalent at this time, 
that the assertion was founded upon an error, as far as 
Leonardo da Vinci was concerned. Let us hear what he 
himself says in his Book of Painting (Nos. 254 and 255 in 
the translation of Heinrich Ludwig, Quellenschriften zur 
Kunstgeschichte, Vienna, Braumiiller, 1882, Vol. XVIII. ). 
" 254. Of simple colors there are six. The first of these 
is white, although philosophers admit neither white nor 
black into the number of colors, since the one is the cause 
of color, the other of its absence. But, inasmuch as the 
painter cannot do without them, we shall include these two 
also among the other colors and say that white in this 
classification is the first among the simple colors, yellow 
the second, green the third, blue the fourth, red the fifth, 
black the sixth. And the white we will let represent the 
light, without which one can see no color, the yellow the 
earth, the green the water, blue the air, red fire, and black 
the darkness which is above the element of fire, because in 
that place there is no matter or solid substance upon which 
the sunbeams can exert their force, and which as a result 
they might illumine." "255. Blue and green are not 
simple colors by themselves. For blue is composed of 
light and darkness, as, the blue of the air, which is made 
up of the most perfect black and perfectly pure white." 
" Green is composed of a simple and a composite color, 
namely, of yellow and blue." This will suffice to show that 
Leonardo da Vinci is concerned partly with observations 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 67 
concerning pigments, partly with conceptions of natural 
philosophy, but not with the subject of fundamental color- 
sensations. The many remarkable and subtle scientific 
observations of all sorts which are contained in Leonardo 
da Vinci's book lead to the conviction that the artists, and 
among them especially he himself, were the true forerunners 
of the great scientists who came soon afterwards, These 
men were obliged to understand nature in order to reproduce 
it agreeably; they observed themselves and others in the 
interest of pure pleasure. Yet Leonardo was far from being 
the author of all the discoveries and inventions which 
Groth, for example (Leonardo da Vinci ah Ingenieur und 
Philosophy Berlin, 1874), ascribes to him. 1 My own 
scattered remarks concerning the theory of color-sensations 
were perfectly clear. I assumed the fundamental sensations 
white, black, red, yellow, green, blue, and six different 
corrresponding (chemical) processes (not nerve-fibres) in 
the retina. (Compare Reicherfs und Dubois 1 Archiv^ 1865, 
P' 633, et seq.) As a physicist, I was of course familiar 
with the relation of the complementary colors. My con- 
ception, however, was that the two complementary processes 
together excited a new the white process. (Loc. cit. t 
p. 634.) I gladly acknowledge the great advantages of 
Hering's theory. They consist for me in the following. 
First, the black process is regarded as a reaction against the 
white process ; I can appreciate all the better the facilita- 
tion involved in this, as it was just the relation of black 
and white that for me presented the greatest difficulty. 
Further, red and green, as also yellow and blue, are 
1 Marie Herzfeld, Leonardo da Vinci, Auswahl aus den veroffent- 
lichten Handschriften^ Leipzig, 1904. 
68 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
regarded as antagonistic processes which do not produce 
a new process, but mutually annihilate each other. Ac- 
cording to this conception white is not subsequently 
produced but is already present beforehand, and still 
survives on the annihilation of a color by the comple- 
mentary color. The only point that still dissatisfies me 
in Hering's theory is that it is difficult to perceive why 
the two opposed processes of black and white may be 
simultaneously produced and simultaneously felt, while 
such is not the case with red-green and blue-yellow. 
This objection has been partly removed by a further 
development of Hering's theory. 1 The full explanation of 
this relation lies undoubtedly in 
the proof, which W. Pauli has 
provided, that certain processes 
l n colloidal and in living sub- 
b stances can be reversed by opposite 
processes along the same path, or 
"homodromously," as in A, while other processes can only 
be reversed by opposite processes along a different path, 
or " heterodromously," as in J2. 2 I myself shewed long 
ago that certain sensations are related to one another as 
positive and negative magnitudes (e.g., red and green), 
while others do not stand in this relation (e.g., white and 
black). 3 Now all difficulties are reconciled if we suppose 
1 Zur Lehre vom Lichtsinne, Vienna, 1878, p. 122. Cp. also my 
paper, previously cited, in the Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akademie, 
Vol. LIL, 1865, October. 
2 W. Pauli, Der Kolliodah Zustand und die Vorgange in der 
lebendigen Substanz, Brunswick, Vieweg, 1902, pp. 22, 30. 
3 Grundlinicn der Lehre von den Bewegungsempfindungen, 1895, 
PP- 57 , sqq. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 69 
with Pauli that the opposed processes as assumed by Hering, 
which correspond to the first pair, are homodromous, and 
that the processes underlying the second pair are hetero- 
dromous. 1 
The examples adduced will suffice to explain the signifi- 
cance of the above-enunciated principle of inquiry, and at 
the same time to show that this principle is not entirely 
new. In formulating the principle, years ago, I had no 
other object than that of making quite clear to my 
own mind a truth which I had long instinctively felt. 
It seemed to me a simple and natural, nay, an almost 
self-evident supposition, that similarity must be founded on 
a partial likeness or identity, and that consequently, where 
sensations were similar, we had to look for their common 
identical constituents and for the corresponding common 
physiological processes. I wish, however, to make it quite 
clear to the reader that this view by no means meets with 
universal agreement. We constantly find it maintained in 
philosophical books that similarity may be observed without 
there being any question at all of such identical con- 
stituents. Thus a physiologist 2 can speak as follows of the 
principle under discussion : "The application of this prin- 
ciple to the above problems leads him (Mach) to ask. what 
is the physiological factor that corresponds to the qualities 
thus postulated ? Now it seems to me that, of all axioms 
1 A recent exposition of Hering's views will be found in Graefe- 
Saemisch's Ilandbuck der ges. Aitgenheilkunde, Leipzig, 1905^ 
Vol. III. 
2 J. Von Kries, Ueber die materiellen Grmidlagen der Bewusst- 
seinserscheinu-hgcn^ Freiburg im Breisgau, 1898. 
70 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
and principles, none is more doubtful, none is exposed to 
greater misunderstandings than is this principle. If it is 
nothing more than a periphrasis for the so-called principle 
of parallelism, then it cannot be considered either new or 
particularly fruitful, and it does not deserve the importance 
that is attached to it. If, on the other hand, it is intended 
to mean that a definite element or constituent of a 
physiological event must correspond to everything which 
we can distinguish as having some sort of psychological 
unity, to every relation, to every form, in a word to 
everything that we can denote by a general concep- 
tion, then this formulation can only be characterized 
as dubious and misleading." And I am taken as 
holding that the principle in question (with the re- 
servation made on p. 59) must be understood in this 
last "dubious and misleading" sense. I must leave it 
entirely to the reader to choose whether he will 
accompany me any further and enter with me on that 
preliminary stage of inquiry which is clearly denned by 
means of our principle, or whether, bowing to the authority 
of my opponents, he will turn back and satisfy himself 
merely with considering the difficulties which confront 
him. If he chooses the former alternative, he will, 
I hope, discover, that when simpler cases have been 
disposed of, the difficulties in cases of deeper-lying 
abstract similarity no longer appear in such a formidable 
light as before. All I will add at present is, that in these 
more] complicated cases of similarity the similarity arises 
not from the presence of one common element, but from a 
common system of elements, as I shall explain at length 
in connexion with conceptual thinking (Cf. Chap. XIV.). 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 71 
8. 
As we recognize no real gulf between the physical and 
the psychical, it is a matter of course that, in the study 
of the sense-organs, general physical as well as special 
biological observations may be employed. Much that 
appears to us difficult of comprehension when we draw a 
parallel between a sense-organ and a physical apparatus, 
is rendered quite obvious in the light of the theory of 
evolution, simply by assuming that we are concerned with 
a living organism with particular memories, particular 
habits and manners, which owe their origin to a long and 
eventful race-history. The sense-organs themselves are a 
fragment of soul ; they themselves do part of the psychical 
work, and hand over the completed result to conscious- 
ness. I will here briefly put together what I have to say 
on this subject. 
The idea of applying the theory of evolution to physio- 
logy in general, and to the physiology of the senses in 
particular, was advanced, prior to Darwin, by Spencer 
(1855). It received an immense impetus through Darwin's 
book The expression of the Emotions. Later, P. R. 
Schuster (1879) discussed the question whether there were 
" inherited ideas " in the Darwinian sense. I, too, expressed 
myself in favor of the application of the idea of evolution 
to the theory of the sense-organs (Sitzungsberichte der 
Wiener Akademie, October 1866). one of the finest 
and most instructive discussions, in the way of a psycho- 
logico-physiological application of the theory of evolution, 
72 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
is to be found in the Academic Anniversary Address of 
Hering, on Memory as a General Function of Organized 
Matter ; 1870 (English translation, Open Court Publishing 
Company, Chicago, 1913). As a fact, memory and here- 
dity almost coincide in one concept if we reflect that 
organisms, which were part of the parent-body, emigrate 
and become the basis of new individuals. Heredity is 
rendered almost as intelligible to us by this thought as, 
for example, is the fact that Americans speak English, or 
that their state-institutions resemble the English in many 
respects, etc. The problem involved in the fact that 
organisms possess memory, a property which is apparently 
lacking to inorganic matter, is, of course, not affected by 
these considerations, but still exists (cp. Chapters V., XL). 
If we want to avoid criticizing Hering's theory unfairly, we 
must observe that he uses the conception of memory in a 
rather broad sense. He perceived the affinity between the 
lasting traces imprinted on organisms by their racial history, 
and the more evanescent impressions which the individual 
life leaves behind it in consciousness. He recognizes that 
the spontaneous reappearance, in response to a slight 
stimulus, of a process which has once been set up, is 
essentially the same event, whether it can be observed 
within the narrow framework of consciousness or not. 
The perception of this common feature in a long series of 
phenomena is an essential step in advance, even though 
this fundamental feature itself still remains unexplained. 1 
Recently Weismann (Ueber die Dauer des Lebens, 1882) 
has conceived death as a phenomenon of heredity. This 
admirable book, also, has a very stimulating effect. The 
1 R. Semon, Die Mneme, Leipzig, 1904. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 73 
difficulty which might be found in the fact that a character- 
istic should be inherited which can make its appearance in 
the parent-organism only after the process of inheritance is 
ended, lies probably only in the manner of statement. 
It disappears when we consider that the power of the 
somatic cells to multiply can increase, as Weismann shows, 
at the cost of the increase of the germ-cells. Accordingly, 
we may say that greater length of life on the part of the 
cell-society and lessened propagation are two phenomena 
of adaptation which mutually condition each other. While 
a Gymnasium student, I heard it stated that plants from 
the Southern Hemisphere bloom in our latitudes, when it 
is spring in their native place. I recall clearly the mental 
shock which this communication caused me. If it is true, 
we may actually say that plants have a sort of memory, 
even though it be admitted that the chief point involved 
is the periodicity of the phenomena of life. The so-called 
reflex movements of animals may be explained in a natural 
manner as phenomena of memory outside the organ of 
consciousness. I was a witness of a very remarkable 
phenomenon of this kind in 1865, I think with Rollett, 
who was experimenting with pigeons whose brains had 
been removed. These birds drink whenever their feet are 
placed in a cold liquid, whether the liquid is water, 
mercury, or sulphuric acid. Now since a bird must 
ordinarily wet its feet when it seeks to quench its thirst, 
the view arises quite naturally that we have here a habit 
adapted to an end, which is conditioned by the mode of 
life and fixed by inheritance, and which, even when con- 
sciousness is eliminated, takes place with the precision of 
clockwork on the application of the stimulus appropriate 
74 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
to its excitation. Goltz, in his wonderful book Die Ner- 
vencentren des Frosches, 1869, and in later writings, has 
described many phenomena of the sort. I will take this 
opportunity of mentioning some further observations which 
I recall with a great deal of pleasure. In the autumn 
vacation of 1873, m Y ntt l e DOV brought me a sparrow a 
few days old, which had fallen from its nest, and wanted 
to bring it up. But the matter was not so easy. The 
little creature could not be induced to swallow, and would 
certainly soon have succumbed to the indignities that 
would have been unavoidable in feeding it by force. I 
then fell into the following train of thought : "Whether or 
not the Darwinian theory is correct, the new-born child 
would certainly perish if it had not the specially formed 
organs and inherited impulse to suck, which are brought 
into activity quite automatically and mechanically by the 
appropriate stimulus. Something similar (in another form) 
must exist likewise in the case of the bird." I exerted 
myself to discover the appropriate stimulus. A small 
insect was stuck upon a sharp stick and swung rapidly 
about the head of the bird. Immediately the bird opened 
its bill, beat its wings, and eagerly devoured the proffered 
food. I had thus discovered the right stimulus for setting 
the impulse and the automatic movement free. The 
creature grew perceptibly stronger and greedier, it began 
to snatch at the food, and once seized an insect that had 
accidentally fallen from the stick to the table ; from that 
time on it ate, without ceremony, of itself. In proportion 
as its intellect and memory developed, a smaller portion of 
the stimulus was required. on reaching .independence, 
the creature took on, little by little, all the characteristic 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 75 
ways of sparrows, which it certainly had not learnt by 
itself. By day, with its intellect awake, it was very 
trustful and friendly. In the evening, other phenomena 
were regularly exhibited. It grew timid. It always 
sought out the highest places in the room, and would 
become quiet only when it was prevented by the ceiling 
from going higher. Here again we have an inherited 
habit adapted to an end. on the coming of darkness, 
its demeanour changed totally. When approached, it 
ruffled its feathers, began to hiss, and showed every 
appearance of terror and real physical fear of ghosts. Nor 
is this fear without its reasons and its purpose in a 
creature which, under normal circumstances, may at any 
moment be devoured by some monster. 
This last observation strengthened me in an opinion 
already formed, that my children's terror of ghosts did 
not have its source in nursery tales, which were carefully 
excluded from them, but was innate. one of my children 
would regard with anxiety an arm-chair, which stood in the 
shadow ; another carefully avoided, in the evening, a coal- 
scuttle by the stove, especially when this stood with the lid 
open, looking like gaping jaws. The fear of ghosts is the 
true mother of religions. Neither scientific analysis nor 
the careful historical criticism of a David Strauss, as applied 
to myths, which, for the strong intellect, are refuted even 
before they are invented, will all at once do away with and 
banish these things. A motive which has so long answered, 
and in a measure still answers, to actual economic needs 
(fear of something worse, hope of something better), will 
long continue to exist in mysterious and uncontrollable in- 
stinctive trains of thought. Just as the birds on uninhabited 
7 6 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
islands (according to Darwin) learn the fear of man only after 
the lapse of generations, so we shall unlearn, only after many 
generations, that useless habit known as the creeping of flesh. 
Every presentation of Faust may teach us the extent to which 
we are still in secret sympathy with the conceptions of the 
age of witchcraft. The exact knowledge of nature and of the 
conditions of this life gradually becomes more useful to man 
than fear of the unknown. And in time the most impor- 
tant thing of all for him is to be on his guard against his 
fellow-men who want to oppress him violently or abuse him 
treacherously by misleading his understanding and emotions. 
I will here relate one other curious observation, for the 
knowledge of which I am indebted to my father (an 
enthusiastic Darwinian and in the latter part of his life a 
landed proprietor in Carniola). My father occupied him- 
self much with silk-culture, raised the yama-mai in the open 
oak-woods, etc. The ordinary mulberry silkworm has, for 
many generations, been raised indoors, and has consequently 
become exceedingly helpless and dependent. When the 
time for passing into the chrysalitic state arrives, it is the 
custom to give the creatures bundles of straw, upon which 
they spin their cocoons. Now it one day occurred to my 
father not to prepare the usual bundles of straw for a 
colony of silk-worms. The result was that the majority of 
the worms perished, and only a small portion, the geniuses 
(those with the greatest power of adaptation) spun their 
cocoons. Whether, as my sister believes she has observed, 
the experiences of one generation are utilized, in noticeable 
degree, in the very next generation, is a question which 
probably requires to be left to further investigation. The 
experiments made by C. Lloyd Morgan (Comparative 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 77 
Psychology, London, 1894) with young chickens, ducks, 
etc., shew that, at any rate in the case of the higher animals, 
scarcely anything is innate but the reflexes. The newly- 
hatched chick at once begins to peck with great assurance 
at everything that it sees ; but it has to learn what is suit- 
able to pick up by its individual experience. The simpler 
the organism, the smaller the part played by individual 
memory. From all these remarkable phenomena we need 
derive no mysticism of the Unconscious. A memory 
reaching beyond the individual (in the broader sense 
defined above) renders them intelligible. A psychology in 
the Spencer-Darwinian sense, founded upon the theory of 
evolution, but supported by detailed positive investigation, 
would yield richer results than all previous speculation has 
done. These observations and reflections had long been 
made and written down when Schneider's valuable work, 
Der thierische Wille, Leipzig, 1880, which contains many 
that are similar, made its appearance. I agree with the 
details of Schneider's discussions (in so far as they have 
not been made problematical by Lloyd Morgan's experi- 
ments) almost throughout, although his fundamental con- 
ceptions in the realms of natural science with regard to 
the relation of sensation and physical process, the signifi- 
cance of the survival of species, etc., are essentially different 
from mine, and although I hold, for instance, the distinction 
between sensation-impulses and perception-impulses to be 
quite superfluous. An important revolution in our views 
on heredity may perhaps be produced by Weismann's work, 
Ueber die Vererbung, Jena, 1883 (English translation, Essays 
on Heredity and Kindred Biological Problems, Oxford, The 
Clarendon Press, 1889). Weismann regards the inheritance 
78 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
of traits acquired by use as highly improbable, and finds in 
chance variation of the germ-elements and in the selection 
of the germ-elements the most important factors. Whatever 
attitude we adopt towards Weismann's theories, the dis 
cussion initiated by him must contribute to the elucidation 
of these questions. No one will refuse to recognize the 
almost mathematical acuteness and depth of the way in 
which he states the problem, and it cannot be denied that 
his arguments have much force. He makes, for instance, 
the extremely suggestive remark that it is impossible that 
the peculiar and unusual forms of sexless ants, which must 
apparently be referred to use and adaptation, and which 
moreover deviate so remarkably from the forms of ants 
that are capable of propagation, should be produced by 
inheritance of characteristics acquired by use. 1 That the 
germ-elements themselves may be altered by external in- 
fluences appears to be clearly shewn by the formation 
of new races, which maintain themselves as such, trans- 
mit their racial traits by inheritance, and are themselves, 
again, capable of transformation, under other circum- 
stances. Accordingly, some influence must certainly be 
exerted on the germ-plasm by the body which envelops it 
(as Weismann himself admits). Thus an influence of the 
individual life upon its descendents can certainly not be 
entirely excluded, even although a direct transmission to 
the descendents of the results of use in the individual can 
(according to Weismann) no longer be expected. In 
entertaining the notion that the germ-elements vary acci- 
1 But perhaps the powerful mandibles of the sexless ants are the 
original acquisition of the species, and merely appear in an atrophied 
form in the individuals to whom propagation of the race is confined. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 79 
dentally, we must bear in mind that chance is not a principle 
of action. When periodic circumstances of different kinds 
and different periodicities coincide in accordance with 
definite causal laws, the circumstances overlap in such a 
way that in any particular case it is impossible to see that 
any law is involved. But the law reveals itself with the 
lapse of a long enough time, and permits us to calculate on 
certain average values or probabilities of effects. 1 Without 
some such principle of action, chance or probability is 
meaningless. And what principle of action can be con- 
ceived as exercising more influence on the variation of the 
germ-elements than the body of the parent ? Personally I 
cannot understand how it is possible that the species should 
succumb to the influence of varying circumstances, and yet 
that these circumstances should not affect the individual. 
Moreover, I am certain that I myself vary with every 
thought, every memory, every experience ; all these factors 
undoubtedly change my whole physical behaviour. 2 
Although it is scarcely necessary, I should like to add 
explicitly that I regard the theory of evolution, in whatever 
form, as a working scientific hypothesis, capable of being 
modified and of being made more precise, which is valuable 
in so far as it facilitates the provisional understanding of 
what is given in experience. I have been a witness of the 
powerful impetus which Darwin's work gave in my time 
not merely to biology, but to all scientific enquiry, and it 
is not likely that I should underestimate the value of the 
theory of evolution. But I would not quarrel with anyone 
1 Vorlesungen ilber Psychophysik, Zeitschrift fur prakt. Heilkunde, 
pp. 148, 168, 169, Vienna, 1863. 
2 Popular Scientific Lectures, Chicago, Open Court Publishing Co. 
8o THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
who should rate its value very low. As long ago as 1883 
and 1886 I dwelt on the necessity of advancing by means 
of more precise conceptions obtained by the study of 
biological facts for their own sakes. 1 Thus I am by no 
means committed to a refusal to understand investigations 
such as those of Driesch. But whether Driesch's criticism 
of my attitude towards the theory of evolution is justified, 2 
I leave to anyone to decide who, even after this criticism, 
still cares to be at the pains of reading my works. 
10. 
Teleological conceptions, as aids to investigation, are not 
to be shunned. It is true, our comprehension of the facts 
of reality is not enhanced by referring them to an unknown 
World-Purpose, itself problematical, or to the equally 
problematical purpose of a living being. Nevertheless, 
the question as to the value that a given function has for 
the existence of an organism, or as to what are its actual 
contributions to the preservation of the organism, may be 
of great assistance in the comprehension of this function 
itself. 3 Of course we must not suppose, on this account, 
1 Cp. Popular Scientific Lectures, and Analyse der Empfindungen^ 
1886, pp. 34, sqq. 
2 Driesch, Die organisatorischen Regulationen, pp. 165, sqq., 1901. 
3 Such teleological conceptions have often been useful and instructive 
to me. The remark, for example, that a visible object under varying 
intensity of illumination can be recognized as the same only when the 
sensation excited depends on the ratio of the illumination-intensities of 
object and surroundings, makes intelligible a whole train of organic 
properties of the eye. (Cp. Hering in Graefe-Saemisch's Handbrich der 
Augenheilkunde, Vol. III., Ch. 12, pp. 13, sqq.) In this way we under- 
stand also, how the organism, in the interest of its survival, was obliged 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 81 
as many Darwinians have done, that we have " mechanically 
explained " a function, when we discover that it is necessary 
for the survival of the species. Darwin himself is doubt- 
less quite free from this short-sighted conception. By 
what physical means a function is developed, still remains 
a physical problem ; while the how and why of an organism's 
voluntary adaptation continues to be a psychological pro- 
blem. The preservation of the species is only one, though 
an actual and very valuable, point of departure for inquiry, 
but it is by no means the last and the highest. Species 
to adjust itself to the requirement mentioned and to adapt itself to feel 
the ratios of light-intensity. The so-called law of Weber, or the funda- 
mental psycho-physical formula of Fechner, thus appears not as some- 
thing fundamental, but as the explicable result of organic adjustments. 
The belief in the universal validity of this law is, naturally, herewith 
relinquished. I have given the arguments on this point in various 
papers. (Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akademie, Vol. LI I., 1865 ; 
Vierteljahrsschrijt fur Psychiatric^ Neuwied and Leipzig, 1868; 
Sitzimgsberichte der Wiener Akademie, Vol. LVIL, 1868). In the 
last-named paper, proceeding from the postulate of the parallelism 
between the psychical and the physical, or, as I then expressed myself, 
from the proportionality between stimulus and sensation, I abandoned 
the metrical formula of Fechner (the logarithmic law), and brought 
forward another conception of the fundamental formula, the validity of 
which for light-sensation I never disputed. This is apparent beyond 
all doubt from the way in which that paper is worked out. Thus one 
cannot say, as Hering has done, that I everywhere take the psycho- 
physical law as my foundation, if by this is understood the metrical 
formula. How could I have maintained the proportionality between 
stimulus and sensation at the same time with the logarithmic depend- 
ence? It was sufficient for me to render my meaning clear; to 
criticize and contest Fechner's law in detail, I had, for many obvious 
reasons, no need. Strictly speaking I consider the expression "pro- 
portionality " also to be inappropriate, since there can be no question 
of an actual measurement of the sensations ; all that can be done is to 
characterize them exactly and make an inventory of them by numerical 
means. Cp. what I have said about the characterization of states of 
heat (Prinzipien der Warmelehre, p. 56). 
F 
82 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
have certainly been destroyed, and new ones have as 
certainly arisen. The pleasure-seeking and pain-avoiding 
will, 1 therefore, is directed perforce beyond the preservation 
of the species. It preserves the species when it is advan- 
tageous to do so, and destroys it when its survival is no 
longer advantageous. Were it directed merely to the 
preservation of the species, it would move aimlessly about 
in a vicious circle, deceiving both itself and all individuals. 
This would be the biological counterpart of the notorious 
"perpetual motion" of physics. The same absurdity is 
committed by the statesman who regards the state as an 
end in itself. 
1 Schopenhauer's conception of the relation between Will and Force 
can quite well be adopted without seeing anything metaphysical in 
either. 
V. PHYSICS AND BIOLOGY. 
CAUSALITY AND TELEOLOGY. 
IT often happens that the development of two different 
fields of science goes on side by side for long 
periods, without either of them exercising an influence on 
the other. on occasion, again, they may come into closer 
contact, when it is noticed that unexpected light is thrown 
on the doctrines of the one by the doctrines of the other. 
In that case a natural tendency may even be manifested 
to allow the first field to be completely absorbed in the 
second. 1 But the period of buoyant hope, the period of 
over-estimation of this relation which is supposed to 
explain everything, is quickly followed by a period of 
disillusionment, when the two fields in question are once 
more separated, and each pursues its own aims, putting 
its own special questions and applying its own peculiar 
methods. But on both of them the temporary contact 
leaves abiding traces behind. Apart from the positive 
addition to knowledge, which is not to be despised, the 
temporary relation between them brings about a trans- 
formation of our conceptions, clarifying them and permitting 
of their application over a wider field than that for which 
they were originally formed. 
1 Cp. W. Pauli, Physikalische-chemische Methods* in der Medizin^ 
Vienna, 1900, where an allied, but more narrowly limited, question 
is dealt with. 
83 
84 THE ANALYSIS 'OF SENSATIONS 
2. 
We are living at present in such a period of complicated 
cross-relations, and the consequent fermentation of ideas 
gives rise to very remarkable phenomena. While many 
physicists are concerned to purify physical conceptions by 
psychological, logical and mathematical methods, other 
physicists, mistrustful of this tendency, and more philo- 
sophical than the philosophers themselves, are coming 
forward as advocates of the old metaphysical conceptions 
which the philosophers have already largely abandoned. 
Philosophers, psychologists, biologists, and chemists, all 
make the most widely extended applications of the principle 
of energy and of other physical conceptions, with a freedom 
which the physicist would hardly venture to use in his 
own field. We may almost say that the customary roles 
of the special departments have been interchanged. The 
success of this movement may be partly positive and 
partly negative, but in any case the result of it will be a 
more precise determination of our conceptions, a more 
accurate delimitation of the sphere to which they apply, 
and a clearer idea of the difference and the affinity between 
the methods of the departments in question. 
We are here concerned in particular with the relations 
between the physical and biological fields in the broadest 
sense. The distinction between effective causes and final 
causes, or ends, dates from Aristotle. It has been 
generally assumed that physical phenomena are throughout 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 85 
determined by effective causes, and biological phenomena 
by final causes. The acceleration of a body, for example, 
is determined solely by the effective causes, by the 
circumstances of the movement, such as the presence of 
other gravitating magnetic or electrical bodies. Up to the 
present we are not able to deduce the development of a 
growing animal, or the development of a plant in its peculiar 
determinate forms, or the instinctive actions of an animal, 
from effective causes alone ; but such facts as these can 
be at any rate partially understood when we take into 
consideration the purpose of self-preservation under the 
particular circumstances of the organism's life. Whatever 
theoretical reservations we may make as to the application 
to biology of the conception of purpose, it would certainly 
be perverse, in a field where the "causality" theory still 
affords such imperfect explanations, to refuse to make use 
of the clues which a consideration of purpose puts into our 
hands. I do not know what it is that compels the cater- 
pillar of the hawk-moth to spin a cocoon with a bristly 
flap opening outwards, but I see that such a cocoon exactly 
corresponds to the purpose of preserving the caterpillar's 
existence. I am far from being able to understand 
" causally " the numerous remarkable phenomena, described 
and studied by Reimarus and Autenrieth, of the develop- 
ment and instinctive action of animals ; but I understand 
them in the light of the purpose of preserving the animal's 
existence in the particular conditions of life involved. 
These phenomena consequently merit attention ; they 
become fused in the picture which we form of the life of 
the organism as ineffaceable constituents ; and it is only 
through them that that picture can be rounded out into a 
86 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
united and connected whole. But it is only quite recently, 
and particularly through the investigations of Sachs in 
the physiology of plants and, in animal physiology, through 
the work of Loeb on geotropism, heliotropism, stereo- 
tropism, etc., that the relations between growth and 
instinct have been really explained in such a way that we 
can begin to conceive these relations also as "causal." 
History testifies in a manner that cannot be gainsaid to 
the utility of the conception of purpose in biological 
research. Consider only Kepler's investigation of the 
eye. It was impossible for him, in view of the purpose of 
the eye, namely clear vision at different distances, to doubt 
the existence of accommodation; but it was not until 150 
years later that the processes which effect the accommo- 
dation were really discovered. Harvey discovered the 
circulation of the blood in the course of an attempt to 
make clear to himself the problematical purpose of the 
position of the valves of the heart and veins. 
Even when a department of facts has been completely 
explained teleologically, the need to understand it " causally " 
still persists. The belief in the completely different nature 
of the two departments we are considering, in virtue of 
which one is to be understood only in a causal sense and 
the other only in a teleological sense, is not justified. A 
complex of physical facts is something simple, or at any 
rate in many cases can, at will, be experimentally represented 
in such a simple form that the immediate relations between 
its parts become visible. Now supposing that we have 
done sufficient work in this department to have enabled us 
to acquire, as regards the nature of these relations, con- 
ceptions which we think correspond to the facts universally, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 87 
then we are logically bound to expect that any particular 
fact which may present itself will correspond to these con- 
ceptions. But this implies no necessity in nature. 1 It is in 
this that " causal " understanding consists. A biological 
factual complex, on the other hand, is compounded in such 
a way that the immediate relations between its parts cannot 
be taken in at a glance. Accordingly we are satisfied if we 
are able to represent as being connected with one another 
prominent parts of the complex which are not immediately 
connected. But the intellect which has been trained to 
familiarity with the simpler causal relation finds, in the 
absence of the intermediate links, difficulties which it tries 
to remove as best it can, either by trying to discover these 
iniermediate links, or by grasping at the hypothesis of a 
quite new kind of connecting relations. The latter alter- 
native is unnecessary, if we regard our knowledge as 
imperfect and provisional, and reflect that in the department 
of physics absolutely analogous cases arise. The scientists 
of antiquity, indeed, did not draw this precise distinction 
between the two departments. Aristotle, for example, con- 
ceives heavy bodies as seeking out their position; Hero 
thinks that, from motives of economy, nature conducts light 
by the shortest paths and in the shortest times. These 
inquirers thus set up no such definite boundary between 
the physical and the biological. Moreover, by an imper- 
ceptible modification in our thought, we can formulate 
every teleological question in such a way as completely to 
exclude the conception of purpose. The eye sees clearly 
at different distances ; the apparatus of dioptrical vision 
1 Prinzipien der Wcirmelehre, 2nd edition, Leipzig, 1900, pp. 434, 
457- 
88 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
must therefore be capable of change ; in what does this 
change consist? The valves of the heart and veins all 
open in the same direction ; this being so, the circulation 
of the blood can only take place in one direction. Is this 
the fact ? The modern theory of evolution has made this 
sober method of thought its own. Even in the very ad- 
vanced parts of physics, on the other hand, we come across 
considerations having a great affinity with those of the 
biological sciences. The investigation, for example, of the 
possibility, under certain conditions, of stationary vibrations 
(i.e., vibrations which can maintain themselves) has for some 
time past been in an advanced state. It is only quite 
recent work, however, which has made clear the manner in 
which they arise. 1 We explain the movement of light along 
the shortest paths by means of a selection of the affective 
paths. At present the conceptions used by chemists are 
even closer to those of the biologist. According to these 
conceptions all possible combinations are formed by the 
resolution of elements ; but combinations which cannot be 
resolved, and have greater power of resistance to new attacks, 
get the better of the others and survive. It thus would 
appear that there is as yet no necessity to assume a funda- 
mental difference between teleological and causal methods 
of investigation. The former is simply a provisional 
method. 
5- 
To confirm this conclusion in greater detail, let us return 
1 Cp. W. C. L. van Schaik, Ueber die Tonerregung in Labialpfeifen. 
Rotterdam, 1891 ; V. Hensen, Annalen der Physik, 4th Series, Vol. 
III., p. 719, 1900. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 89 
to the various conceptions of causality. The old traditional 
conception of causality is of something perfectly rigid : a 
dose of effect follows on a dose of cause. A sort of 
primitive, pharmaceutical conception of the universe is ex- 
pressed in this view, as in the doctrine of the four elements. 
The very word " cause " makes this clear. The connections 
of nature are seldom so simple, that in any given case we 
can point to one cause and one effect. I therefore long ago 
proposed to replace the conception of cause by the mathe- 
matical conception of function, that is to say, by the con- 
ception of the dependence of phenomena on one another, 
or, more accurately, the dependence of the characteristics of 
phenomena on one another. 1 This conception is capable 
of any extension or limitation that may be desired, accord- 
ing to what is required by the facts under investigation. 
Perhaps, therefore, great importance need not be attached 
to the objections that have been raised against it. 2 Consider, 
as a simple example, the relation of gravitating masses. If 
a mass B comes into opposition to a mass A, a movement 
of A towards B follows. This is the old formula. But, if 
1 Die Geschichte und die Wurzel des Satzes der Erhaltung der Arbeit, 
Prague, Calve, 1872. (English translation, History and Root of the 
Principle of the Conservation of Energy, by P. E B. Jourdain, 
Chicago, Open Court Publishing Co., 1911.) 
2 Such objections have been raised by Kiilpe in his Ueber die 
Beziehungen zwischen kbrperlichen und seelischen Vorgdngen (Zeitschrift 
fur Hypnotismus, Vol. VII., p. 97), also by Cossman in his Empirische 
Teleologie, Stuttgart, 1899, p. 22. I do not think that my view differs 
so greatly from Cossman's that an understanding is impossible. If he 
had considered the matter further, he would have seen that I substituted 
the notion of function for the old notion of causality, and that the 
notion of function is sufficient also for those cases which he has in view. 
I have no further objection to make to his " Empirical teleology." Cp. 
also C. Ilauptmann Die Metaphysik in der Physiologic, Dresden, 1893. 
go THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
we consider the matter more accurately, we see that the 
masses A B C D. . . determine mutual accelerations in 
one another, accelerations which, therefore, are given as 
soon as the masses are posited. The accelerations allow us 
to infer the velocities which will be attained at some future 
moment. Hence also the positions of A B C D. . . are 
determined for every moment. But the physical measure- 
ment of time is based in its turn upon a measurement of 
space, namely the rotation of the earth. We are thus ulti- 
mately left with a mutual dependence of positions on one 
another. Thus, even in this simplest case, the old formula 
is incapable of embracing the multiplicity of the relations 
that exist in nature. Similarly in other cases everything is 
resolved into relations of mutual dependence, 1 as to the 
form of which nothing of course can be said beforehand, 
since this is a question which can only be settled by special- 
ized inquiry. With a relation of mutual dependence change 
is only possible when some group of the related elements 
can be regarded as an independent variable. Consequently, 
though it may be possible to complete in detail the picture 
of the world in a scientifically determined manner when a 
sufficient part of the world is given, yet science cannot tell 
us what the total result of the world process will be. 
Given a well-defined mechanical system (defined, say, 
by central forces), with its positions and velocities, its con- 
figuration is determined as a function of time. We know 
its configuration for any time we like before and after the 
time of commencement, and can thus prophesy both back- 
wards and forwards. This can only happen in both cases 
when no disturbance intervenes from outside, when, that is 
1 Cp. Erkenntnis und Irrttim (1905), p. 274. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 91 
to say, the system can be regarded as in a certain sense a 
closed system. We cannot, indeed, regard any system as 
being completely isolated from the rest of the world, inas- 
much as the determination of time, and consequently also 
that of the velocities, presupposes dependence on a para- 
meter which is determined by the path traversed by some 
body, such as a planet, lying outside the system. The 
actual dependence, even though it be not an immediate 
dependence of all processes on the position of one body, 
guarantees to us the interconnection of the whole world. 
Analogous considerations hold for any physical system, 
Fig. i b. 
even when it is not conceived as a mechanical system also. 
All accurately and clearly recognized relations may be re- 
garded as mutual relations of simultaneity. 
Let us consider, by way of contrast, the popular concep- 
tion of cause and effect. Let 5 in Fig. i, b, represent the sun, 
which illumines a body ^placed in any medium whatever. 
Then the sun, or the heat of the sun, is the cause of a rise 
in temperature in the body K. The rise follows regularly 
on the illumination of K. on the other hand, the body 
K) or the change in its temperature, cannot be regarded 
as the cause of the change in the sun's temperature, as 
would actually be the case if S and K stood alone in an 
immediate relation to one another. The two changes 
would then be simultaneous, and would mutually determine 
one another. The reason that this is not so is to be sought 
92 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
in the intermediate links, the elements, A B, of the 
medium, which determine changes not only in K^ but also 
in other elements, and in their turn are determined by 
these latter. Thus K stands in relations of mutual deter- 
mination with innumerable elements, and only a vanishing 
portion of the light it reflects finds its way back to the 
sun. It is in analogous circumstances that we must 
look for the reason why a body K throws an image upon 
the retina N^ and sets up a visual sensation E, from which 
a memory remains behind, although the memory does not 
restore either the retina N or the whole body K. The 
principal advantage for me of the notion of function over 
that of cause lies in the fact that the former forces us to 
greater accuracy of expression, and that it is free from the 
incompleteness, indefmiteness and one-sidedness of the. 
latter. The notion of cause is, in fact, a primitive and 
provisional way out of a difficulty. Every modern man of 
science must, I think, feel this, when, for instance, he 
glances at J. S. Mill's discussion of the methods of experi- 
mental inquiry. If he were to try to apply these methods 
he would never get beyond the most rudimentary results. 
The range of spatial and temporal functional relations 
within which our conjectures operate, may be one of which 
the limits lie very far apart : starting from the present we may 
try to prophesy into the distant future or past, and we may 
make fortunate guesses. But, the greater the distance, the 
less secure must the basis of our reasoning be. It is there- 
fore, without prejudice to the greatness of Newton's concep- 
tion of action at a distance, a very important step in advance 
that modern physics, wherever it can, requires that due con- 
sideration should be paid to spatial and temporal continuity. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 93 
6. 
It might seem from what has been said that, both in 
physics and biology, the notion of function was all that we 
wanted, and that this notion would prove equal to all 
requirements. We need not be alarmed by the great 
difference in point of view displayed by the two sciences. 
Quite closely related groups of physical phenomena, as for 
example frictional electricity and galvanic electricity, look 
so different that at first sight it might seem impossible to 
expect that the two should be capable of reduction to the 
same fundamental facts. The magnetic and chemical 
phenomena, which are scarcely observable in the case of 
frictional electricity, and could only with difficulty have been 
discovered there at all, are extremely prominent in galvanic 
electricity ; whereas, contrariwise, it is only in the case of the 
former that ponderomotive phenomena and phenomena of 
tension present themselves easily and unsought for. Now 
it is well known that each of these two studies supplements 
and throws great light on the other ; so much so that we 
have reached the point of discovering the chemical nature 
of frictional electricity by means of galvanic electricity. 
An analogous relation also holds between physics and 
biology. Both contain the same fundamental facts; but 
many sides of these facts come to light only in one of 
them, while many other sides are only noticeable in the 
other, so that physics, standing side by side with biology, 
can afford help to and throw light upon biology, and vice 
versa. No one can deny that the application of physics 
to biology has accomplished much ; but against these 
94 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
achievements we have to set other cases in which it was 
reserved for biology to bring to light new physical facts 
(galvanism, PfefTer's cells, etc.). Physics will accomplish 
much more in biology, if only she will submit to have 
additions made to her by the latter. 
If anyone familiar with the physical sciences alone were 
to turn to the study of biology, and thereupon were to 
suppose that an animal grows special organs which it finds 
ready to be applied to some useful purpose at a later stage 
of its life, or that it can perform instinctive actions which it 
cannot have learnt and which can only inure to the advan- 
tage of future members of the race, or that it adapts its 
coloration to its environment in order to avoid possible 
future enemies, on such suppositions he would in fact 
easily arrive at the assumption that quite peculiar factors 
were here at work. one excellent reason why this mysteri- 
ous operation of the future at a distance cannot be com- 
pared with any physical relation, is that the operation does 
not take place exactly and without exception, since many 
organisms prepare themselves for a later stage of their life, 
but are destroyed before attaining it. It is impossible to 
regard something which is not determined for ourselves, or 
is only partially determined, namely the uncertain past or 
the uncertain future, as being the determining factor in a 
present process which is going on before our eyes. But 
when we reflect that the processes in the life of generations 
return periodically, we see that the conception of a par- 
ticular stage of life as being in the future and operating at 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 95 
a distance is an arbitrary and hazardous conception, and 
that the stage of life in question can also be regarded as a 
process in the past, as something given which has left its 
traces behind. In this way the element of the unfamiliar 
and incomprehensible is greatly decreased. What we then 
have is not a possible future which might produce an effect, 
but a past which certainly has recurred countless times, 
and which certainly has produced an effect. 
As an example of our contention that Physics is capable 
of co-operating fruitfully in the solution of what are appar- 
ently specifically biological problems, we have only to 
remember the remarkable progress made by experimental 
embryology and the mechanism of development with its 
physico-chemical methods. 1 We have another very remark- 
able fact in O. Wiener's demonstration of the probable 
connexion between color-photography and color-adaptation 
in nature. 2 By means of stationary light-waves stratification 
may be formed in a medium that is sensitive to light, and 
then the incident light may be reflected back as an inter- 
ference-color ; but there is yet another way in which a 
coloration corresponding to the illumination may arise. 
Of materials that are sensitive to light, there are some 
which can take on almost any hue. When such materials 
are exposed to a colored illumination, they retain the color 
of the illumination, because they do not absorb the rays 
of the same color as themselves, and consequently the 
light is incapable of producing any further change in 
1 Cp. W. Roux, Vortrdge und Aufsatze iiber Entivickelungsmechanik 
der Organismen, Leipzig, W. Engelmann, 1905. 
2 O. Wiener, " Farbenphotographie und Farbenanpassung in der 
Natur," Wiedemann's AnnaZen, Vol. LV., 1895, p. 225. 
96 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
them. According to Poulton's observations l it is probable 
that many of the adaptive colors of chrysalises arise in this 
manner. Thus in such cases we do not need to look far 
afield from the means that produce the effect, in order to 
find the " purpose " that is attained. Avoiding all rashness 
of statement, we may say that the equilibrium is determined 
by the circumstances under which it is attained. 
8. 
The conceptions of " effective cause " and of " purpose " 
both have their origin in animistic views, as is quite clearly 
seen from the scientific attitude of antiquity. The savage, 
no doubt, does not puzzle his head by reflecting on his own 
movements, which seem to him quite spontaneous, natural 
and self-evident. But as soon as he perceives unexpected 
and striking movements in nature, he instinctively interprets 
these movements on the analogy of his own. In this way 
the distinction between his own and someone else's volition 
begins to dawn upon him. 2 Gradually the similarities and 
differences between physical and biological processes stand 
1 Poulton, The Colors of Animals, London, 1890. 
-I once set a Holtz electrical machine going for the benefit of one of 
my boys when he was about three years old. He was delighted by the 
dancing sparks. But when I let go the machine and it went on rotating 
by itself, he started back in terror and apparently thought it was alive : 
"It goes by itself!" he exclaimed, in startled and anxious tones. 
Perhaps it is the same with dogs when they run barking after every 
moving cart. (For another plausible explanation, which does not 
agree with this view, see Zell, Sinddie Tiere unvernunftig? Kosmos- 
verlag, p. 38. ) I remember that when I was about three years old I 
was frightened when the elastic seed-capsule of a plant of garden- 
balsam opened on being pressed, and pinched my finger. It seemed 
to me alive, like an animal. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 97 
out alternately with ever greater clearness against the back- 
ground of the fundamental scheme of volitional action. 
Where volitional action is conscious, cause and purpose 
still coincide. As regards physical processes, their great 
simplicity and their susceptibility to calculation cause the 
animistic conception to fade gradually away. Through 
a series of rigid forms the conception of cause merges by 
degrees into the conceptions of dependence and function. 
It is only for the phenomena of organic life, which offer 
less resistance to the animistic view, that the conception 
of purpose, the notion of an activity that is conscious of its 
end, is still maintained ; and where conscious purposive 
action cannot be ascribed to the organism itself, some 
higher entity that strives towards a goal (Nature, or the 
like) is assumed as watching over the organism and guiding 
its activities. 
Animism, or anthropomorphism, is not an epistomological 
fallacy ; if it were, every analogy would be such a fallacy. 
The fallacy lies merely in the application of this view to 
cases in which the premises for it are lacking or are not 
sufficient. Nature, in producing man, has created a pro- 
fusion of analogies between lower, and doubtless also 
between higher, stages of evolution. 
When any process which is completely determined by 
the circumstances of the moment, and which remains 
limited to itself without further consequences, occurs in 
an inorganic, or even in an organic, body, we should 
scarcely speak of a purpose, as, for instance, when a 
sensation of light or a muscular contraction is excited by 
a stimulus. But when the hungry frog snaps at the fly 
which it sees, and swallows and digests it, we naturally 
98 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
adopt the notion of purposive action. Purposiveness only 
comes in when the organic functions are resolved into 
one another, when they are seen as interconnected, as not 
limited to the immediate, as proceeding by way of detours. 
In the sphere of the organic a much larger section of the 
world-process is manifested ; we are aware of the influence 
of a wider spatial and temporal environment. That is why 
the organic is more difficult to understand. Real under- 
standing is attained when, and only when, we have suc- 
ceeded in resolving the complex into its immediately 
connected parts. Accordingly, the peculiar characteristics 
of the organic must be regarded only as provisional clues. 
The perusal of recent biological writings (Driesch, Reinke, 
etc.), though perhaps they are opposed to my own 
tendencies, only confirms me in this view. And if teleo- 
logical investigation can only be provisional, the same is 
true of historical investigation also, since all historical 
research needs to be supplemented by causal explanation, 
a point which is very properly emphasized in Loeb's 
biological works, and in K. Menger's writings on economics. 
Every organism together with its parts is subject to the 
laws of physics. Hence the legitimate attempt gradually 
to conceive of an organism as something physical, and to 
establish the consideration of it in a "causal" point of 
view as alone valid. But whenever we try to do this we 
are always brought face to face with the peculiar character- 
istics of the organic, for which no analogy can be found in 
the physical phenomena of "lifeless" nature, so far as they 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 99 
have been investigated at present. Every organism is a 
system that is able to maintain its peculiar properties, its 
chemical composition, its temperature and so forth, in the 
face of external influences, and which manifests a state of 
dynamic equilibrium of considerable stability. 1 By an 
expenditure of energy the organism is able to draw more 
energy to itself from its environment, and thus to replace 
the loss of energy by an equal or a greater amount. 2 A 
steam-engine which should fetch its coal itself and heat 
itself, is only a feeble and artificial image of an organism. 
The organism possesses these properties even in its minuter 
parts ; it regenerates itself from these parts ; that is to say, 
it grows and propagates itself. Physics therefore still has 
much that is new to learn from a study of the organic 
before it is in a position to control the organic. 3 
The best physical image of a living process is still 
afforded by a conflagration, or some similar process, which 
automatically transfers itself to the environment. A con- 
flagration keeps itself going, produces its own combustion- 
temperature, brings neighbouring bodies up to that tempera- 
ture and thereby drags them into the process, assimilates 
and grows, expands and propagates itself. Nay, animal 
life itself is nothing but combustion in complicated cir- 
cumstances .4 
10. 
Let us compare our volitional action with some reflex 
1 Hering, Vorgdnge in der lebendigen Substanz, Lotos, Prague, 1888. 
2 Hirth, Energetische Epigenesis, Munich, 1898, pp. x., xi. 
3 Hering, Zur Theorie der Nerventatigkeit, Leipzig, 1899. 
4 Cf. Ostwald, Naturphilo sophie, and the work of Roux cited on 
p. 95, above. 
TOO THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
movement which we have observed in ourselves, and which 
causes us surprise when it occurs, or with the reflex move- 
ment of an animal. In the two latter cases we can detect 
an inclination to regard the whole process as physically 
determined by the momentary circumstances of the 
organism. Now what we call volition is nothing more 
than the totality of those conditions of a movement which 
enter partly into consciousness and are connected with a 
prevision of the result. If we analyse these conditions, so 
far as they enter into consciousness, we find nothing more 
than memory-traces of former experiences and their inter- 
connection (association). It seems that the preservation 
of such traces and their associations is a fundamental 
function of elementary organisms, even though, in the case 
of such organisms, we are no longer able to speak of 
consciousness or of any arrangement in a system of 
memories. 
If we may take memory and association, in Hering's 
wider sense, to be fundamental properties of elementary 
organisms, then adaptation would become intelligible. 1 
Favourable combinations occur more often than in the 
ratio of compound probability, and remain associated. 
The presence of food, the feeling of satiety, and swallowing 
movements remain interconnected. The fact that phylo- 
genesis is repeated in ontogenesis in an abbreviated form, 
would constitute a parallel to the well-known phenomenon 
by which thoughts return by preference along the paths 
which they have once taken, similar thoughts under similar 
conditions evoking similar thoughts. We do not indeed 
1 Hering, Ueber das Gcdachtnis als allegemeine runktion der organi- 
sierten Materie, Vienna, 1870. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 101 
know what are the physical counterparts to memory and 
association. All the explanations that have been attempted 
are very much forced. In this respect it seems as if- there 
were almost no analogy between the organic and the in- 
organic. It is possible, however, that, in the physiology 
of the senses, psychological observation on the one side 
and physical observation on the other, may make such 
progress that they will ultimately come into contact, and 
that in this way new facts may be brought to light. 1 The 
result of this investigation will not be a dualism, but rather 
a science which, embracing both the organic and the 
inorganic, shall interpret the facts that are common to the 
two departments. 
1 I first tentatively suggested this notion, though still in terms of 
Fechner's theories, in the Kompendiiim der Physikfur Mediziner, 
1863, p. 234. 
VI. THE SPACE SENSATIONS OF 
THE EYE. 
i. 
tree with its hard, rough, grey trunk, its many 
-L branches swayed by the wind, its smooth, soft, 
shining leaves, appears to us at first a single, indivisible 
whole. In like manner, we regard the sweet, round, yellow 
fruit, the warm, bright fire, with its manifold moving 
tongues, as a single thing. one name designates the 
whole, one word draws forth from the depths of oblivion 
all the associated memories at once, as if they were strung 
upon a single thread. 
The reflexion of the tree, the fruit, or the fire in a mirror 
is visible, but not tangible. When we turn our glance 
away or close our eyes, we can touch the tree, taste the 
fruit, feel the fire, but we cannot see them. Thus the 
apparently indivisible thing separates into parts, which are 
not only attached to one another but also to other condi- 
tions. The visible is separable from the tangible, from 
that which may be tasted, etc. 
What is merely visible also appears at first sight to be a 
single thing. But we may see a round, yellow fruit together 
with a yellow, star-shaped blossom. A second fruit may be 
just as round as the first, but is green or red. Two things 
may be alike in color but unlike in form ; they may be 
different in color but like in form. Thus sensations of 
102 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 103 
sight are separable into color-sensations and space -sensa- 
tions, which are different from one another even though 
they cannot be represented in isolation from another. 
2. 
Color-sensation, into the details of which we shall not 
enter here, is essentially a sensation of favorable or un- 
favorable chemical conditions of life. In the process of 
adaptation to these conditions, color-sensation has probably 
been developed and modified. 1 Light introduces organic 
1 Compare Grant Allen, The Color-Sense, London, Triibner & Co., 
1879. The attempt of H. Magnus to show a considerable develop- 
ment of the color-sense within historical times, cannot, I think, be 
regarded as felicitous. Immediately after the appearance of the 
writings of Magnus, I corresponded with a philologist, Prof. F. Polle 
of Dresden, on this subject, and both of us soon came to the conclusion 
that the views of Magnus could not hold their own before the critical 
examination either of natural science or of philology. As each of us 
left the publication of the results of our discussion to the other, these 
were never made public. Meantime, however, the matter has been 
disposed of by E. Krause, and in detail by A. Marty. I shall take the 
liberty of adding only a few brief remarks. From defects of termin- 
ology we cannot infer the absence of corresponding qualities of sensation. 
Terms, even to-day, are always indistinct, hazy, defective, and few in 
number, where there is no necessity for sharp discrimination. The 
color-terminology of the countryman of to-day, and his terminology of 
sensations in general, is no more developed than that of the Greek 
poets. The peasants of the Marchfeld say, for example, as I have 
often proved by personal experience, that salt is "sour," because the 
expression "salty" is not familiar to them. The terminology of 
colors must not be looked for in the poets, but in technical works. 
And, furthermore, as my colleague Benndorf has remarked, we must 
not take an enumeration of vase -pigments for an enumeration of all 
colors, as does Magnus. When we consider the polychromy of the 
ancient Egyptians and Pompeiians, when we take into account the 
fact that these decorations can scarcely have been produced by the 
104 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
life. The green chlorophyll and the (complementary) red 
haemoglobin play a prominent part in the chemical pro- 
cesses of the plant-body and in the chemical reactions of 
the animal body. The two substances present themselves 
to us in the most varied modifications of tint. The dis- 
covery of the visual purple, and observations in photography 
and photo-chemistry, allow us to conceive visual processes 
also as chemical processes. The r61e which color plays in 
analytical chemistry, in spectrum-analysis, in crystallography, 
is well known. It suggests a new conception for the so- 
called vibrations of light, according to which they should 
be regarded, not as mechanical, but as chemical vibrations, 
as successive union and separation, as an oscillatory process 
of the same sort that takes place, though only in one direc- 
tion, in photo-chemical phenomena. This conception, 
which is substantially supported by recent investigations in 
anomalous dispersion, accords with the electro-magnetic 
color-blind, when we note that Pompeii was buried in ashes only 
seventy years after Vergil's death, whilst Vergil on this theory is sup- 
posed to have been nearly color-blind, the untenability of the whole 
conception is sufficiently apparent. The question has lately been taken 
up again, with recourse to fuller authorities, by W. Schultz (Das 
Farbenempjind^lngs system der Hellenen, Leipzig, 1904). Applications 
of the Darwinian theory are also to be made with caution in another 
direction. We like to picture to ourselves a condition in which the 
color-sense is lacking, or in which little color-sense exists, as preceding 
another in which the color-sense is highly developed. For the beginner 
it is natural to proceed from the simple to the complex. But this is 
not necessarily the path of Nature. The color-sense exists, and it is 
probably variable. But whether it is being enriched or impoverished 
who can tell? Is it not possible that, with the awakening of intelli- 
gence and the use of artificial contrivance, the whole development will 
be shifted to the intellect, which certainly is chiefly called into play 
from this point on, and that the development of the lower organs of 
man will be relegated to second place ? 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 105 
theory of light. In the case of electrolysis, in fact, chemistry 
yields the most intelligible conception of the electric current 
by regarding the two components of the electrolyte as pass- 
ing through each other in opposite directions. It is likely, 
therefore, that in a future theory of colors, many biologico- 
psychological and chemico-physical threads will be united. 
Adaptation to the chemical conditions of life which 
manifest themselves in color, renders locomotion necessary 
to a far greater extent than adaptation to those which mani- 
fest themselves through taste and smell. At least this is so 
in the case of man, which is here in question, and as to 
which alone a direct and certain judgment is within our 
power. The close association of space-sensation (a 
mechanical factor) with color-sensation (a chemical factor) 
is thus rendered intelligible. We shall now proceed to the 
analysis of optical space-sensations. 
In examining two figures which are alike but differently 
colored (for example, two letters of the same size and shape, 
but of different colors), we recognize 
their sameness of form at the first glance, 
in spite of the difference of color-sensa- 
tion. The sight-perceptions, therefore, 
must contain some identical sensation- 
components. These are the space-sensations which are 
the same in the two cases. 
IB 
io6 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
5- 
We will now investigate the character of the space- 
sensations that physiologically condition the recognition of 
a figure. First, it is clear that this recognition is not the 
result of geometrical considerations which are a matter, 
not of sensation, but of intellect. on the contrary, the 
space-sensations in question serve as the starting-point and 
foundation of all geometry. Two figures may be geometri- 
cally congruent, but physiologically quite different, as is 
Fig. 3- 
shewn by the two adjoined squares (Fig. 3), which could 
never be recognized as the same without mechanical and 
intellectual operations. 1 A few simple experi- 
ments will render us familiar with the relations 
here involved. Look at the spot in Fig. 4. 
Place the same spot twice or several times in 
exactly the same position in a row (Fig. 5) ; the 
result is a peculiar, agreeable impression, and we recog- 
nize at once and without difficulty the identity of all the 
1 Compare my brief paper, Ueber das Sehen von Lagenund Winkeln, 
in the Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akademie, Vol. XLIIL, 1861, p. 215. 
Fig. 4- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 107 
Fig. 5- 
figures. When, however, we turn one spot far enough 
round with respect to the other (Fig. 6), their identity of 
form is not recognizable without intellectual 
assistance. on the other hand, if we 
place two of the spots in positions sym- 
metrical to the median plane of the 
observer (Fig. 7) the relationship of form 
is strikingly apparent. But if the plane 
of symmetry diverges considerably from 
the median plane of the observer, as in 
Fig. 8, the affinity of form is recogniz- 
able only by turning the figure around or by an intellectual 
act. on the other hand, the affinity of form is 
again apparent on contrasting with such a spot 
the same spot rotated through an angle of 180 
in the same plane (Fig. 9). In this case we have 
the so-called centric symmetry. 
If we reduce all the dimensions of the spot 
proportionately, we obtain a geometrically similar 
spot. But as the geometrically congruent is not 
necessarily physiologically (optically) congruent, nor 
the geometrically symmetrical necessarily optically 
symmetrical, analogously the geometrically similar 
is not necessarily optically similar. It is only when 
the two geometrically similar spots are placed beside Fi - 9- 
each other in the same relative positions (Fig. 10), that they 
will also appear optically similar. Turning one of the spots 
io8 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
round destroys the resemblance (Fig. n). If we substitute 
for one of the spots a spot symmetrical to the other in 
respect of the median plane 
of the observer (Fig. 12), a 
symmetrical similarity will be 
produced which has also an 
optical value. The turning 
of one of the figures through 
1 80 in its own plane, pro- 
ducing thereby centrically 
symmetrical similarity, has 
also a physiologico-optical value (Fig. 13). 
6. 
In what, now, does the essential nature of optical similarity, 
as contrasted with geometrical similarity, consist ? In geo- 
metrically similar figures, all homologous distances are 
proportional. But that is an affair of the intellect, not of 
sensation. If we place beside a triangle with the sides 
a, b, , a triangle with the sides 20, 26, 2C, we do not 
recognize this simple relation between the two immediately, 
but intellectually, by measurement. If the similarity is to 
become optically perceptible, the proper position must be 
added. That a simple relation of two objects for the 
intellect does not necessarily condition a similarity of 
sensation, may be perceived by comparing two triangles 
having respectively the sides, a, b, c, and a + m,l> + m, + m. 
The two triangles do not look at all alike. Similarly all 
conic sections do not look alike, although all stand in a 
simple geometric relation to each other ; still less do curves 
of the third order exhibit optical similarity, etc. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 109 
The geometrical similarity of two figures is determined 
by all their homologous lines being proportional or by all 
their homologous angles being equal. But to appear optically 
similar the figures must also 
be similarly situated^ that is 
all their homologous direc- 
tions must be parallel or, as 
we prefer to say, must be the 
same (Fig. 14). The import- 
ance of direction for sensation will be evident upon a careful 
consideration of Fig. 3. It is by identity of direction, 
accordingly, that are determined the identical space-sensa- 
tions which are characteristic of the physiologico-optical 
similarity of the figures. 1 
We may obtain an idea of the physiological significance 
of the direction of a given straight line or curve-element, 
by the following reflexion. Let y^=f(x) be the equation 
of a plane curve. We can read at a glance the course of 
the values of dy\dx on the curve, for they are determined 
1 Some forty years ago, in a society of physicists and physiologists, I 
proposed for discussion the question, why geometrically similar figures 
were also optically similar. I remember quite well the attitude taken 
with regard to this question, which was accounted not only superfluous, 
but even ludicrous. Nevertheless, I am now as strongly convinced as 
I was then that this question involves the whole problem of form-vision. 
That a problem cannot be solved which is not recognized as such is 
clear. In this non-recognition, however, is manifested, in my opinion, 
that one-sided mathematico-physical direction of thought, which alone 
accounts for the opposition, from so many sides and extending over so 
many years, instead of cheerful acceptance, with which the writings of 
Hering have been received- 
no THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
by its steepness ; and the eye gives us, likewise, qualitative 
information concerning the values of d 2 yjdx 2 t for they are 
characterized by the curvature. The question naturally 
presents itself, why can we not arrive at as immediate 
conclusions concerning the values d 3 y/dx 3 , d 4 y/dx\ etc. 
The answer is easy. What we see is of course not the 
differential coefficients, which are an intellectual affair, but 
only the direction of the curve-elements, and the deviation 
of the direction of one curve-element from that of another. 
In fine, since we are immediately cognisant of the 
similarity of figures lying in similar positions, and are also 
able to distinguish at once the special case of congruity, 
therefore our space-sensations yield us information con- 
cerning identity or difference of directions and equality or 
inequality of dimensions. 
8. 
It is a priori extremely probable that sensations of space 
are connected in some way with the motor apparatus of 
the eye. Without entering into particulars, we may observe, 
first, that the whole apparatus of the eye, and especially the 
motor apparatus, is symmetrical with respect to the median 
plane of the head. Hence, symmetrical movements of 
looking will be connected with like or approximately like 
space-sensations. Children constantly confound the letters 
b and d, p and q. Adults, too, do not readily notice a 
change from left to right, unless some special points of 
apprehension for sensev or intellect make it noticeable. 
The symmetry of the motor apparatus of the eye is very 
perfect. The like excitation of its symmetrical organs 
would, by itself, scarcely account for the distinction of 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS in 
right and left. But the whole human body, especially the 
brain, is affected with a slight asymmetry, which leads, 
for example, to the preference of one (generally the right) 
hand, in motor functions. And this leads, again, to a 
further and better development of the motor functions of 
the right side, and to a modification of the attendant 
sensations. After the space-sensations of the eye have 
become associated, through writing, with the motor sensa- 
tions of the right hand, a confusion of those vertically 
symmetrical figures with which the art and habit of writing 
are concerned no longer ensues. This association may 
even become so strong that the memories follow only the 
accustomed tracks, and we read, for example, the reflexion 
of written words in a mirror only with the greatest difficulty. 
The confusion of right and left still occurs, however, with 
regard to figures which have no motor, but only a purely 
optical (for example, ornamental) interest. A noticeable 
difference between right and left must be felt, moreover, 
by animals, as in many predicaments they have no other 
means of finding their way. How similar, moreover, are 
the sensations connected with symmetrical motor functions 
is easily remarked by the attentive observer. If, for 
example, because my right hand happens to be engaged, 
I grasp a micrometer-screw or a key with my left hand, 
I am certain (unless I reflect beforehand) to turn it in 
the wrong direction, that is, I always perform the move- 
ment which is symmetrical to the usual movement, con- 
fusing the two because of the similarity of the sensation. 
The observations of Heidenhain regarding the reflected 
writing of persons hypnotized on one side should also be 
cited in this connexion. 
H2 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
The idea that the distinction between right and left 
depends upon an asymmetry, and possibly in the last 
resort upon a chemical difference, is one which has been 
present to me from my earliest years. I gave expression 
to it in the first lectures I ever delivered, in 1861. Since 
then this idea has forced itself upon me again and again. 
I learned by chance from a retired army-officer that on dark 
nights or in snow-storms, when external landmarks are 
absent, troops will move approximately in a circle of large 
radius so that they almost return to their point of departure, 
though all the time they are under the impression that 
they are marching straight forward. An analogous pheno- 
menon is narrated in Tolstoi's story, Master and Servant. 
Probably the only way to understand these phenomena is 
to assume a slight motor asymmetry. They are analogous 
to the way in which a ball with a slight deviation from 
the true cylindrical shape rolls in a circle of large radius. 
This is actually the way in which the matter is regarded 
by F. O. Guldberg, 1 who has carried out detailed researches 
on the phenomena presented in this connexion by human 
beings and animals that have lost their way. Human 
beings and animals that have lost their direction move, 
almost without exception, nearly in circles, of which the 
radii vary according to the species, while the centre lies 
sometimes on the left hand of the individual travelling 
along the circumference, and sometimes on his right, 
1 F. O. Guldberg, " Die Zirkularbewegung," Zeitschrift far Biologic, 
Vol. XXV., p. 419, 1897. Dr W. Pauli drew my attention to this 
article in conversation. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 113 
according to the individual and the species. According 
to Guldberg we have here a teleological device to help 
parents to find their hungry young again when they have 
been lost. Experiments on the lower animals, with whom 
this factor is absent, would therefore be interesting. For 
the fest, we should expect, on grounds of general proba- 
bility, to find imperfect symmetry in the lower animals also. 
Again, Loeb's researches " on the Spatial Feeling of 
the Hand," J have taught us, amongst other things, that 
when the eyes are bandaged, a given movement of the 
right hand, if imitated by the left, is always reproduced 
in an exaggerated or a diminished form ; the degree of 
exaggeration or diminution varying with the individual. 
Loeb thinks that the phenomena of regeneration allow us 
to infer that the distinction between right and left is 
specific. I am certain, however, that I personally have 
never regarded it as a merely geometrical and quantitative 
motor difference. 
10. 
With looking upwards and looking downwards, funda- 
mentally different space - sensations are associated, as 
ordinary experience shows. This is, moreover, compre- 
hensible, since the motor apparatus of the eye is asym- 
metrical with respect to a horizontal plane. The direction 
of gravity also is so very decisive and important for the 
motor apparatus of the rest of the body that this fact has 
assuredly also found its expression in the apparatus of the 
eye, which serves the rest. It is well known that the 
1 Loeb, " Ueber den Ftihlraum der Hand," Pflliger's Archiv, Vols, 
XLI. and XLVI. 
H 
H4 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
symmetry of a landscape and of its reflexion in water is 
not felt. The portrait of a familiar personage, when turned 
upside down, is strange aid puzzling to a person who 
does not recognize it intellectually. If we place ourselves 
behind the head of a person lying upon a couch, and 
unreflectingly give ourselves up to the impression which 
the face makes upon us, we shall find that our impression 
is altogether strange, especially when the person speaks. 
The letters b and /, and d and ^, are not confused even 
by children. 
Our previous remarks concerning symmetry, similarity, 
and the rest, naturally apply not only to plane figures, but 
also to those in space. Hence, we have yet a remark to 
add concerning the sensation of space-depth. The sight 
of something at a distance causes different sensations from 
the sight of something near at hand. These sensations 
must not be confused, because of the supreme importance 
of the difference between near and far, both for animals and 
human beings. They cannot be confused, because the 
motor apparatus is asymmetrical with respect to a plane 
perpendicular to the direction from front to rear. It is a 
common experience that a portrait-bust of a person whom 
we know quite well cannot be replaced by the mould 
in which the bust is cast, and this experience is quite 
analogous to the observations consequent upon the inver- 
sion of objects. 
ii. 
If we suppose that identical dimensions and identical 
directions excite identical space-sensations, and that direc- 
tions symmetrical with respect to the median plane of the 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 115 
head excite similar space-sensations, it becomes easy to 
understand the above-mentioned facts. The straight line 
has, in all its elements, the same direction, and everywhere 
excites the same space-sensations. Herein consists its 
aesthetic value. Moreover, straight lines which lie in the 
median plane or are perpendicular to it are brought into 
special relief by the circumstance that, thanks to this 
position of symmetry, they stand in the same relation to 
both of the two halves of the visual apparatus. Every other 
position of the straight line is felt as an obliquity, as a 
deviation from the position of symmetry. 
The repetition of the same space-figure in the same posi- 
tion conditions a repetition of the same space-sensation. 
All lines connecting prominent (noticeable) homologous 
points have the same direction and excite the same sensa- 
tion. Likewise when merely geometrically similar figures 
are placed side by side in the same positions, this relation 
holds. The sameness of the dimensions alone is absent. 
But when the positions are disturbed, this relation, and 
with it, the impression of unity the aesthetic impression 
are also disturbed. 
In a figure symmetrical with respect to the median plane, 
similar space-sensations corresponding to the symmetrical 
directions take the place of the identical space-sensations. 
The right half of the figure stands in the same relation to 
the right half of the visual apparatus as the left half of 
the figure does to the left half of the visual apparatus. 
If we alter the sameness of the dimensions, the sensa- 
tion of symmetrical similarity is still felt. An oblique 
position of the plane of symmetry upsets the whole 
relation. 
n6 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
If we turn a figure through 180, contrasting it with 
itself in its original position, centric symmetry is produced. 
That is, if two pairs of homologous points be connected, 
the connecting lines will cut each other at a point <9, 
through which, as their point of bisection, all lines connect- 
ing homologous points will pass. Moreover, in the case 
of centric symmetry, all lines of connexion between homo- 
logous points have the same direction, a fact which 
produces an agreeable sensation. If the sameness of the 
dimensions is eliminated, there still remains, for sensation, 
centrically symmetrical similarity. 
Regularity appears to have no special physiological value, 
in distinction from symmetry. The value of regularity 
probably lies only in its manifold symmetry, which is 
perceptible in more than one single position. 
12. 
The correctness of these observations will be apparent 
on glancing over the work of Owen Jones A Grammar of 
Ornament^ London, 1865. In almost every plate one 
finds new and different kinds of symmetry as fresh testi- 
mony in favor of the conceptions above advanced. The 
art of decoration, which, like pure instrumental music, aims 
at no ulterior end, but ministers only to pleasure in form 
and color, is the best source of material for our present 
studies. Writing is governed by other considerations than 
that of beauty. Nevertheless, we find among the twenty- 
four large Latin letters ten which are vertically symmetrical 
(A, H, I, M, O, T, V, W, X, Y), five which are horizon- 
tally symmetrical (B, C, D, E, K), three which are centri- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 117 
cally symmetrical (N, S, Z), and only six which are 
unsymmetrical (F, G, L, P, Q, R). 
The study of the evolution of primitive art is extremely 
instructive in connexion with the problems under discussion. 
The character of primitive art is determined, firstly, by 
the natural objects that offer themselves to the imitation 
of the artist j secondly, by the degree of mechanical skill 
attained ; and finally by the effort to make use of repetition 
in its various forms. 1 
I have clearly explained briefly in previous writings the 
aesthetic significance of the above-mentioned facts, to treat 
of which in detail was not part of my plan. I cannot, how- 
ever, refrain from mentioning that this has been done by a 
physicist, the late J. L. Soret of Geneva, in an admirable 
book published in 1892,2 for which the way was prepared 
by a lecture delivered by him at the meeting of the Swiss 
Scientific Association in 1866. Soret's views are connected 
with those of Helmholtz, and he does not seem to be 
acquainted with my theories. He does not go into the 
physiological side of the question, but on the aesthetic side 
his exposition is very copious and illustrated by appropriate 
examples. He discusses the aesthetic effect of symmetry, of 
repetition, of similarity and of continuity, which last he 
regards as a special case of repetition. According to him 
slight deviations from symmetry can more than compensate 
1 Alfred C. Haddon, Evolution in Art, as illustrated by the Life- 
histories of Designs ; London, 1895. 
2 J. L. Soret, Sur les conditions physiques de la perception du bcatt, 
Geneva, 1892. 
n8 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
for the loss in sensual satisfaction by the multiplicity which 
they introduce and by the intellectual aesthetic pleasure 
bound up with that multiplicity. This is illustrated from 
the sculptured ornaments of Gothic cathedrals. This 
intellectual pleasure is also produced by the virtual or 
potential symmetry which we perceive when the human 
figure or some other symmetrical form is placed in an 
asymmetrical position. And he does not merely apply 
these reflexions to optical cases, but extends them to all 
departments, as also has been done by me. He notices 
rhythm, music, movements, dancing, the beauties of Nature, 
and even literature. Particularly interesting are his 
observations on blind people, which the Asylum for the 
Blind at Lausanne gave him the opportunity of carrying out. 
Blind people take pleasure in the periodic repetition of the 
same forms in tangible objects, and have a decided sense 
of formal symmetry. Striking disturbances in symmetry of 
form are unpleasant to them, and sometimes even seem to 
them ludicrous. A blind man, who had been accustomed 
to study a large-scale map of Europe in relief, recognized 
that continent by means of geometrical similarity when he 
found it as part of a larger raised map on a smaller scale. 
The symmetrical organs of touch, the two arms and hands, 
are in fact arranged in an analogous way to the organs of 
sight, so that we need not be surprised at the agreement. 
Even in antiquity this agreement was not without its 
influence upon inquirers, to say nothing of a modern 
thinker like Descartes; it even produced a number of 
unfortunate notions which are partly operative even to-day. 
Soret's chapter on literature seems less successful. True, 
in metre, rhyme, etc., we have phenomena similar to those 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 119 
noticed in the previously treated departments. But when, 
for example, he draws a parallel between the effect of the 
sixfold repetition of the phrase " Que diable allait il faire 
dans cette galere," in Moliere's well-known play, 1 and the 
repetition of an ornamental motive, probably few will agree 
with him. It is certain that the effect of this repetition is 
not produced by the repetition as such, but by the succes- 
sive heightening of a comic contrast, and that consequently 
it is merely intellectual. 
Finally, I should like to draw the attention of the reader 
to an article by Arnold Emch in The Monist for October, 
1900, on "Mathematical Principles of ^Esthetic Forms." 
Emch gives attractive examples of the way in which a 
number of forms arranged in a series co-operate to produce 
an aesthetic impression by observing one and the same 
geometrical principle. He is following out the line of 
thought on which I touched in my lecture of 1871, accord- 
ing to which production in accordance with a fixed rule 
has an aesthetic effect (Popular Scientific Lectures, Chicago, 
Open Court Publishing Co., 1894). But in that place I 
laid stress upon the point, and should like to do so again, 
that the rule, considered as an affair of the intellect, has no 
aesthetic effect in itself, but that the effect depends on the 
repetition, determined by the rule, of one and the same 
sensational motive. 
14. 
Here we must once more point out that the geometrical 
and. the physiological properties of a figure in space are to be 
1 Les Fotirberies de Scapin. 
120 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
sharply distinguished. The physiological properties are 
determined by the geometrical properties coincidently with 
these, but are not determined by these solely. on the 
other hand, physiological properties very probably gave 
the first impulse to geometrical investigations. The 
straight line doubtless first attracted attention not because 
of its being the shortest line between two points, but 
because of its physiological simplicity. The plane likewise 
possesses, in addition to its geometrical properties, a special 
physiologico-optical (aesthetic) value, which causes it to be 
noticed, as will be shown later on. The division of the 
plane and of space by right angles has not only the 
advantage of producing equal parts, but also an additional 
and special symmetry-value. The circumstance that 
congruent and similar geometrical figures can be brought 
into positions where their relationship is physiologically 
felt, led, no doubt, to an earlier investigation of these 
kinds of geometrical relationship than of those that are less 
noticeable, such as affinity, collineation, and others. With- 
out the co-operation of sense-perception and understanding, 
'a scientific geometry is inconceivable. But H. Hankel 
has admirably shewn in his History of Mathematics (Leipzig, 
1874) that in Greek geometry the factor of pure under- 
standing is decidedly dominant, whereas in Indian geometry 
the factor of sense has the upper hand. The Hindus 
make use of the principles of symmetry and similarity (see, 
for example, p. 206 of Hankel's book) with a generality 
which is totally foreign to the Greeks. Hankel's proposal 
to unite the rigor of the Greek method with the perspicuity 
of the Indian in a new mode of presentation is well worthy 
of encouragement. Furthermore, in so doing, we should 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 121 

only be following in the footsteps of Newton and John 
Bernoulli, who, even in mechanics, applied the principle of 
similarity in a still more general manner. The advantages 
that the principle of symmetry affords in the last-named 
department, I have shown at length elsewhere. 1 
1 I have given less complete discussions of the leading thoughts of 
this chapter in the paper already mentioned, Ueberdas Sehen von Lagen 
und Winkeln (1861), further (in Fichte's Zeitschrift fur Philosophic, 
Vol. XLVL, 1865, p. 5, and in The Forms of Liquids, and Symmetry 
(1872) now also published in my Popular Scientific Lectures, translated 
by Thomas J. McCormack, Open Court Publishing Co., Chicago, 1894. 
With regard to the use of the principle of symmetry in mechanics, 
compare my work The Science of Mechanics (1883), translated by 
Thomas J. McCormack, 1893, Open Court Pub. Co., Chicago. 
VII. FURTHER INVESTIGATION OF 
SPACE-SENSATIONS. 1 
i. 
OUR knowledge of spatial vision made important 
advances in the course of the nineteenth century, not 
merely because a gain in positive understanding was 
involved, but also because the prejudices accumulated 
by various philosophers and physicists in this department, 
especially since Descartes, have been finally disposed of, 
and thereby that freedom from preconceptions attained 
which is the first requisite for making positive discoveries. 
Johannes Miiller, 2 created the doctrine of specific 
energies, and also put forward with great lucidity the 
theory of identical retinal positions, which, for the rest, 
can be clearly traced back as far as Ptolemy. 3 on Miiller's 
1 So far as I know, the matter treated in the preceding chapter has 
not yet been discussed, except in three small works of my own, and in 
Soret's book. The considerations of the present chapter, moreover, 
are, for me, founded upon those of the preceding chapter. I indicate 
here the methods by which I have myself reached clear ideas as to the 
sensation of space, without laying the least claim to that which has 
been accomplished by others in this direction, particularly by the theory 
of Hering. The extensive literature of this subject is, moreover, too 
imperfectly known to me for me to give exact references on all points. 
The point of Hering's theory which I regard as the most important I 
will especially notice. 
2 J. Miiller, Vergleichende Physiologic des Gesichtsinnes, 1826; 
Handbuch der Physiologic, Vol., II., 1840. 
3 L'Ottica di Claudio Tolomeo, published by G. Govi, Turin, 1885. 
122 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 123 
theory that the retina has sensations of itself in its own 
activity, "visual space" is, for him, something immediately 
given. My own body also appears in my field of vision. 
All questions of direction can only refer to the relative 
positions of parts of the field of vision. The direc- 
tion of vision depends exclusively on the arrangement 
of the sensitive parts of the retina. All theories as to 
projection, and problems as to why we see things upright, 
disappear. But estimation of the distance of an object 
seen is, for Miiller, still through and through an affair of 
the intellect. 
Wheatstone's 1 discovery of the spectroscope led at once 
to the conviction that in certain circumstances images 
could be seen as simple, and with different degrees of depth 
according to the stereoscopic difference, not only when the 
images fell upon identical parts of the retina, but also when 
they fell upon other parts, provided the difference between 
the parts was not too great. The result of this was to throw 
doubt on the doctrine of identity, and to stimulate the 
formulation of psychological explanations of how we come 
to see things as having depth. Hence arose Briicke's 
theory of successive fixation in spatial vision, which in its 
turn was proved to be untenable by Dove's experiments in 
instantaneous illumination with the stereoscope. 
Panum 2 opposed these theories with arguments of great 
force, and by admirably contrived experiments. Taking his 
stand on the phenomenon of binocular rivalry and the 
prominent part played therein by contours, he came to the 
1 Wheatstone, " Contributions to the Theory of Vision," Philosophical 
Transactions 1838, 1852. 
2 Panum, Untersuchungen liber das Sehen mit zwei Augen, 1858. 
124 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
conclusion that our seeing things as having depth depends 
upon a reciprocal action, or " Synergy/' of the two retinae, 
and that the sensation of depth is an innate specific energy. 
The more similar the two monocular images, and especially 
the contours, are in form, color, and position, the more 
easily do they coalesce into a single binocular image, of 
which the depth is determined by the stereoscopic 
difference. But Panum still maintains that this depth 
corresponds to what is given by means of lines of 
projection. 
It is to Hering * that we owe the most thorough clearing 
away of old prejudices. His starting-point is the view that 
our immediately given visual space must be completely dis- 
tinguished from the conceptual space which we obtain by 
means of experiences of a special kind. He proves by 
decisive experiments that the direction in which we see an 
object is different from the line, the line of vision, or of 
projection,- between the object and the retinal image. 
There are two lines of vision, one for each eye ; but there 
is only one direction of vision, bisecting the angle formed 
by these two lines. We have to think of this direction of 
vision as proceeding from the point of bisection of the 
line connecting the two eyes. In order to exclude all 
reference to geometrical space, we may put it thus : The 
two eyes together see the same relative horizontal and 
perpendicular arrangements that a single eye would see 
if it were situated half-way between the two eyes. Suppose 
that, looking in a horizontal direction and with symmetrical 
1 Hering, Beitrdge zur Physiologic, 1861-1865 ; Archivfar Anatomie 
und Physiologic, 1864, 1865 ; " Der Raumsinn und die Bewegungen des 
Auges," in Hermann's Handbuch der Physiologic, Vol. III., I, 1879. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 125 
convergence, we fix our gaze upon a point on the window- 
pane ; then we see this point in the median plane, but at 
the same time we see behind it in the same plane objects 
lying a long way to one side. In the stereoptical experi- 
ment we still see objects in front of us, even when there is 
only a slight divergence of the axes of the eyes, although the 
directions of projection no longer lead to these objects, or 
at any rate have no longer any physical or physiological 
meaning. Again, the distances which we see do not agree 
with the results of the theory of projection. When, with 
horizontal lines of vision, we stretch vertical threads through 
Miiller's circular horopter, the cylinder thereby produced 
appears to us like a plane. We see not only the image of 
the fixed or "nucleus" point, but also the collective con- 
ception of all the points (the " nucleus-surface ") represented 
in identical, or "corresponding," positions, as a plane lying 
before us at a definite distance. It is impossible to explain 
these and many other analogous facts on the theory of 
projection. Hering reduces spatial vision to a simple 
principle. Identical, or "corresponding," points on the 
retina have identical height and breadth-values ; symmetri- 
cal points on the retina, on the other hand, have identical 
depth-values, and these last increase from the outer edges 
of the retina inwards. When similarity of the monocular 
images in color, shape and position causes them to coalesce 
into a singular binocular image, the binocular image con- 
tains the mean value of the depth-values of the single 
images. Such mean values of the single images play a 
decisive part in general, and in particular as regards the 
directions of vision. These indications must be sufficient 
for us here, since we cannot now discuss in detail the varied 
126 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
contents of the works in which Hering has laid the secure 
foundations on which this chapter is based. 1 The only 
further remark I will make is, that, according to him, the 
two eyes are to be conceived as a single united organ, the 
associated movements of which rest on an innate anatomical 
foundation, a point that had already been brought out 
by Johannes Miiller. 
Biological and psychological 2 research combine to con- 
firm the conclusion that, as regards the intuition of 
space, the nativistic view can a fortiori be maintained. 
The chick has scarcely broken from its shell than it is 
seen to be at home in space and pecking at everything 
that excites its attention. For the new-born human being 
we can at most suppose only a lower degree of maturity, 
but otherwise the conditions must be essentially the same. 
Panum has brought out this point. Spatial intuition 
is therefore present at birth. Whether we shall ever be 
in a position to explain it, in the sort of way attempted 
by Helmholtz, by means of the history of evolution or the 
history of the race, is a separate question. 
Perhaps clues towards the solution of this problem 
may be found in the facts of phylogenetic develop- 
ment and the variation of retinal correspondence 
(investigated by Johannes Miiller 3 ) which takes place 
at the transition between one animal species and 
another. Another promising field for research is pre- 
1 Among the works of younger investigators connected with Hering's 
researches, those of F. Hillebrand are of particular interest for 
psychology. 
2 Stumpf Der psychologische Urspwng der Raumvorstellungen, 1873. 
3 Vergleichende Physiologic des Gesichtssinnes, pp. 106, sqq. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 127 
sented by the pathological anomalies of people who 
squint and the phenomena of adaptation to be observed 
in these cases. 1 
2. 
That space-sensation is connected with motor processes 
has long since ceased to be disputed. Opinions differ only 
as to how this connexion is to be understood. 
If two congruent images of different colors fall in 
succession on the same parts of the retina, they are at once 
recognized as identical figures. We may, therefore, regard 
different space-sensations as connected with different parts 
of the retina. But that these space-sensations are not 
unalterably connected with particular parts of the retina, 
we perceive on moving our eyes freely and voluntarily, 
whereby the objects observed do not change their position 
or form, although their images are displaced on the retina. 
If I look straight before me, fixing my eyes upon an 
object O, an object A, which is re- 
flected on the retina in a, at a certain 
distance below the point of most 
distinct vision, appears to me to be 
situated at a certain height. If I 
, . Fig. 15- 
now raise my eyes, fixing them upon 
B, A retains its former height. It would necessarily appear 
1 Tschermak, ' * Ueber anomale Sehrichtungsgemeinschaft der 
Netzhaute bei Schielenden," Graefe's Archiv, XLVIL, 3, p. 508 ; 
Tschermak, Ueber physiologische und pathologischc Anpass^^ng des 
Auges, Leipzig, 1900; Schlodtmann, " Studien iiber anomale 
Sehrichtungsgemeinschaft bei Schielenden," Graefe's Archiv, 
LI-, 2, 1900. 
128 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
lower down if the position of the image on the retina, or the 
arc 0a, alone determined the space-sensation. I can raise my 
glance as far as A and farther without any change in this 
relation. Thus, the physiological process which conditions 
the voluntary raising of the eye, can entirely or partly take 
the place of the height-sensation, is homogeneous with it, 
or, in brief, algebraically summable with it. If I turn my 
eyeball upward by a slight pressure of the finger, the 
object A actually appears to sink, proportionately to the 
shortening of the arc oa. The same thing happens when, 
by any other unconscious or involuntary process for 
example, through a cramp of the muscles of the eye the 
eyeball is turned upward. According to an experience now 
familiar to oculists for some decades patients with paralysis 
of the rectus externus reach too far to the right in attempt- 
ing to grasp objects at the right. Since they need to exert 
a stronger impulse of the will than persons of sound eyes, 
in order to fix their glance upon an object to the right, 
the thought naturally suggests itself that the will to look 
to the right determines the optical space-sensation "right." 
Some years ago, 1 I put this observation into the form of 
an experiment, which every one can try for himself. Let 
the eyes be turned as Jar as possible towards the left and 
two large lumps of moderately hard putty firmly pressed 
against the right side of each eye-ball. If, now, we attempt 
to glance quickly to the right, we shall succeed only very 
imperfectly, owing to the imperfectly spherical form of the 
eyes, and the objects will suffer a strong displacement to 
the right. Thus the mere will to look to the right imparts 
1 Shortly after finishing my Grundlinien der Lehre von den Beweg- 
ungsempfindungen (1875). 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 129 
to the images at certain points of the retina a larger " right- 
ward value," as we may term it for brevity. The experiment 
is, at first, surprising. It will soon be perceived, however, that 
both facts viz., that by voluntarily turning the eyes to the 
right, objects are not displaced, and that by the forced, in- 
voluntary turning of the eyes to the left, objects are displaced 
to the right together teach the same lesson. My eye, which 
I wish to, and cannot, turn to the right, may be regarded as 
voluntarily turned to the right and compulsorily turned back 
by an external force. Professor W. James l could not get 
the experiment just mentioned to succeed. I have often re- 
peated it, and always found it confirmed. I think that the 
fact is certain, but of course that decides nothing as to its 
correct interpretation. 
3- 
The will to perform movements of the eyes, or the 
innervation to the act, is itself the space-sensation. This 
follows naturally from the preceding consideration. 2 If we 
have a sensation of itching or pricking in a certain spot of 
our skin, by which our attention is sufficiently secured, we 
immediately grasp at the spot with the correct amount of 
movement. In the same manner we turn our eyes with 
the correct amount of exertion towards an object reflected 
on the retina, as soon as this exerts a sufficient stimulus to 
draw our attention. By virtue of organic arrangements 
and long exercise we hit immediately upon the exact 
1 W. James, The Principles of Psychology, II., p. 509. 
2 1 retain the expression which first immediately suggested itself to 
me (1875), with no intention of forestalling future inquiry. Here and in 
what follows I leave it an open question whether innervation is a con- 
sequence of space-sensation, or vice versa. They are certainly closely 
connected. 
130 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
degree of innervation sufficient to enable us to fix our 
eyes upon an object reflected on a certain point of the 
retina. If the eyes are already turned towards the right, 
and we begin to give our attention to an object further to 
the right or the left, a new innervation of the same sort is 
algebraically added to that already present. A disturbance 
of the process arises only when alien, involuntary innerva- 
tions or externally moving forces are added to the innerva- 
tions determined by the will. 
Years ago, while occupied with the questions now under 
discussion, I noticed a peculiar phenomenon, which has 
not yet, so far as I know, 
been described. In a 
very dark room we fix 
our eyes upon a light 
A, and then suddenly 
look at a light lower 
down, B. At this, the 
light A appears to make 
a rapid sweep A A' 
(quickly ended) up- 
wards. The light B, of course, does the same ; but to avoid 
complications, this is not indicated in the diagram. The 
sweep is, of course, an after-image, which enters conscious- 
ness only on completion, or shortly before completion, of the 
glance-movement, but and this is the remarkable point 
with positional values that correspond, not to the later, 
but to the earlier innervations and position of the eye. 
Similar phenomena are often noticed in experiments with 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 131 
Holtz's electrical machine. If the experimenter is surprised 
by a spark during a glance downwards, the spark often 
appears high above the electrodes. If it yields a lasting 
after-image, the image appears, of course, below the 
electrodes. The preceding phenomena answer to the so- 
called personal equation of astronomers, except that they 
are confined to the province of sight. By what organic 
arrangements this relation is determined must be left an 
open question, but it is probably of some value in pre- 
venting confusion of position in movements of the eyes. 1 
For the sake of simplicity we have hitherto regarded 
only the eyes as in motion, and have considered the head 
and the body generally as at rest. If, now, we move the 
head about without intentionally fixing the eyes upon any 
object, the objects seen remain motionless. But at the 
same time another observer may notice that the eyes, like 
frictionless, inert masses, take no 
part in the turning movements. 
Still more noticeable is the pheno. 
menon if we turn with continuous 
motion, actively or passively, about a 
vertical axis, as viewed from above, 
say, in the direction of the hands of a clock. In this case, as 
Breuer has observed, the open or closed eyes turn, about 
ten times to a full revolution of the body, in the opposite 
direction to that of the clock-hands, with a uniform 
motion, and as frequently back again in the opposite 
1 For a different explanation see Lipps, Zcitschrift fur Psychologic 
Tind Physiologic der Sinnesorgane^ Vol. I., p. 60. 
132 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
direction by jerks. The process is represented in the 
diagram of Fig. 17. on O T, the times are laid off as 
abscissae, the angles described in the direction of the 
clock-hands are laid off as ordinates upwards, and the 
angles described in the opposite direction as ordinates 
downwards. Tne curve OA corresponds to the rotation 
of the body, O B B to the relative, and O C C to the 
absolute, rotation of the eyes. No one, on repeating the 
experiment, can avoid the conclusion that we are concerned 
here with an automatic (unconscious) movement of the 
eyes, reflexively excited by the rotation of the body. This 
movement disappears as soon as the passive rotation is no 
longer felt. How it is brought about remains, naturally, to 
be investigated. A simple way of looking at it would be that 
there are two antagonistic organs of innervation, and that the 
stimulus which reaches them both uniformly when the body 
rotates, is answered by one with a uniform stream of 
innervation, while the other delivers its impulse of innerva- 
tion only after the lapse of a certain time, like a rain-gauge 
suddenly tipping up when it is full. For us it suffices, 
provisionally, to know that this automatic, unconscious 
compensational movement of the eye is actually present. 
The compensational wheel-like movement of the eyes, 
which takes place when the head is inclined to one side, is 
well-known. Nagel * has proved that it amounts to from 
one-tenth to one-sixth of the angle of inclination of the 
head. And recently Breuer and Kreidl 2 have made similar 
1 Nagel, " Ueber Kompensatorische Raddrehungen der Augen," Zeit- 
schriftfurPsychologieundPhysiologie der Sinnesorgane, Vol. XII. , p. 338. 
2 Breuer and Kreidl, " Ueber scheinbare Drehung des Gesichtsfeldes 
wahrend der Einwirkung einer Zentrifugalkraft," Pfltiger's Archiv, 
Vol. LXX., p. 494- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 133 
experiments in the rotatory apparatus also, with the follow- 
ing results : 
" We have a sensation, as Purkynie and Mach have 
maintained, of the direction of the acceleration of masses. 
When this direction is changed by the interference of a 
horizontal acceleration affecting the body on one side, a 
wheel-like movement of the eyes is set up and persists as 
long as the interference lasts. It amounts to 0-5 or o'6 of 
the angle of deviation. The rotation of visual space, and 
the appearance of vertical lines as oblique, which takes 
place under such conditions, depend therefore on an actual 
but unconscious rotation of the eyes." 
I must also mention here two papers by Crum Browne J 
on compensating movements of the eyes. 
6. 
The slower unconscious compensating movement of the 
eye (the jerking movement leaves behind it no optical 
impression) is thus the reason why, when the head is turned, 
objects seem to retain their position a fact which is very 
important for orientation. If, now, in turning our head, we 
also voluntarily turn the eyes in the same direction, fixing 
them upon one object after another, we must overcompen- 
sate the automatic, involuntary innervation by the voluntary 
innervation. We need the same innervation as if the whole 
angle turned through were described by the eye alone. In 
1 Crum Brown, " Note on Normal Nystagmus/* Proc. of the Royal 
Society of Edinburgh, 4th Feb. 1895: "The Relation between the 
Movements of the Eye and the Movements of the Head," Robert Boyle 
Lechtre, I3th May 1895. 
134 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
this way is explained why, when we turn about, the whole 
optical space appears to us a continuum and not an aggre- 
gation of fields of vision ; and why, at the same time, the 
optical objects remain stationary. That which we see of 
our own body, in turning, we see, for obvious reasons, 
optically in motion. 
Thus we arrive at the practically valuable conception of 
our body as in motion in a fixed space. We understand 
why it is that, in our numerous turnings and ramblings in 
the streets and in buildings, and in our passive turnings in 
a wagon or in the cabin of a ship, even in the dark, we do 
not lose our sense of direction, though it is true that the 
primary co-ordinates from which we started gradually sink 
unnoticed into unconsciousness, and we soon begin to reckon 
from new objects around us. That peculiar state of con- 
fusion as to locality in which we sometimes find ourselves 
on suddenly awaking at night, where we look about help- 
lessly for the window or the table, is probably due to dreams 
of movement immediately preceding our awaking. 
Similar phenomena to those which manifest themselves on 
the rotation of the body make their appearance in connexion 
with the movements of the body generally. If I move my 
head or my whole body sidewise, I do not lose sight of an 
object on which my eyes rest. The latter seems to continue 
motionless, while the more distant objects undergo a dis- 
placement in the same direction as that of the body, and nearer 
objects a parallactic displacement in the opposite direction. 
The parallactic displacements to which we are accustomed are 
perceived, but do not cause us any disturbance and are cor- 
rectly interpreted. But in the monocular inversion of a Plateau 
wire -net, the parallactic displacements, which in the present 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 135 
case are unusual as regards amount and direction, immediately 
attract the eye, and apparently present to us a revolving object. 1 
7- 
When I turn my head, I not only see that part of it turn- 
ing which I am able to see (as will be immediately under- 
stood from the foregoing) but I also feel it turning. This is 
due to the fact that conditions exist in the province of touch 
which are entirely analogous to those in the province of sight. 2 
'Compare my " Beobachtungen liber monoculare Stereoscopic," 
Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akademie, Vol. LVIII., 1868. 
2 The view that the sense of sight and the sense of touch involve, so 
to speak, the same space-sense as a common element, was advanced 
by Locke and contested by Berkeley. Diderot also (Lettres sur les 
aveugles) is of opinion that the space-sense of the blind is altogether 
different from that of a person who sees. Compare on this point the 
acute remarks of Dr. Th. Loewy ( Common Sensibles. Die Gemeinideen 
des Gesichts- und Tastsinnes nach Locke und Berkeley, Leipzig, 1884), 
with whose results, however, I cannot agree. The circumstance that 
a man blind from birth does not, after being operated upon, in accord- 
ance with the experiment proposed by Molyneux, visually distinguish 
the cubes and spheres with which he is familiar from touch, proves 
to my mind nothing at all against Locke and nothing in favor of 
Berkeley and Diderot. Even persons who see recognize figures 
that are turned upside down only after much practice. The fact 
is that at the first moment of sight all the associations connected 
with the optical process, which may subserve its application intel- 
lectually, are wanting. A further point is that, when optical 
stimuli have been absent for a long period in early youth, the develop- 
ment of the central visual spheres may be arrested, or perhaps 
degeneration may even take place, as has been shewn by Schnabel's 
beautiful observations (" Beitrage zur Lehre von der Schlechtsichtig- 
keit durch Nichtgebrauch der Augen," Berichte des naturwissenschaft- 
lich-medikalischen Vereins in Innsbruck, Vol. XI., p. 32), and by 
Munk's experiments on new-born puppies (Berliner klinische Wochen- 
schrift, 1877, No. 35). Even in the case of people who are not 
actually blind, the visual sphere may be so little developed that a 
special education is required to enable them to turn their sight-sensa- 
136 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
When I reach out my hand to grasp an object, a sensation 
of touch is combined with an innervation. If I look towards 
tions to account. The case of the boy described by S. Heller, the 
Director of the Vienna Institute for the Blind ( Wiener klinische Wochen- 
schrift, 25th April 1901), is probably such a case of partial optical 
idiotism. It is only with great caution, therefore, that conclusions 
should be drawn from the behaviour, after operations, of those born 
blind. Chesselden, for instance, gave an account of an operation 
performed on a man blind from birth, who at first believed that every- 
thing he saw was in contact with his eyes ; from this the false conclusion 
was drawn that the perception of the dimension of depth depends on 
extra-optical experiences. An accident put me in the way of under- 
standing this phenomenon. once when I was walking on a dark 
night in a district with which I was unfamiliar, I was all the time 
afraid of running up against a large black object. This turned out to 
be a hill several kilometres distant, which brought about this pheno- 
menon through my being unable to fix and accommodate my sight, 
in much the same way as people who have been newly operated must 
be unabk to do. If any one is not convinced by his own stereoscopy 
that the dimension of depth also is optically given, he is not likely to 
be convinced by the experiences of truncated people without arms and 
legs, such as Eva Lark andKobelkoff(G. Hirth, Energische Epigenesis, 
1898, p. 165). 
All systems of space-sensation, however different they may be, are 
connected by a common associative link, the movements which they 
serve to guide. If Locke was wrong, how could the blind Saunderson 
have written a geometry intelligible to those who are not blind ? 
Without doubt there are analogies between the sense of space given 
through sight and that given through touch. I have already mentioned 
something of this sort in discussing Soret's work (p. n 8, above), and 
many of these phenomena were known to the Aristotelian school. 
Thus in the Parva Naturalia we find mentioned the experiment by 
which a little ball is felt as double when touched by the index-finger 
and the middle finger placed across it. With me this experiment 
produces an even more striking effect when I cross my fingers and 
move them up and down a little stick ; and when I take two parallel 
sticks, and arranging my fingers in this way. run them between them, 
I feel the two sticks as single. The analogy with seeing the single 
as double and seeing the double as single is here complete. But the 
differences also are so great that the man of normal sight finds it 
difficult to picture to himself a blind man's space-presentation, since 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 137 
the object, a luminous sensation is substituted for the sen- 
sation of touch. Even where objects are not touched, skin- 
sensations may always be perceived when the attention is 
turned to them, and these, combined with changing inner- 
vations, also yield the conception of our body as in motion, 
which quite accords with that acquired by optical means. 
Thus, in active movements, the skin-sensations are 
delocalized, as we may briefly express it. In passive move- 
ments of the body, reflex, unconscious compensatory innerva- 
tions and movements of compensation make their appearance. 
In turning round to the right, for example, my skin-sensations 
are compounded with the same innervations as would be 
combined with the touching of objects in turning to the right. 
I feel myself turning to the right. If I am passively turned 
toward the right, the reflex endeavour arises to compensate 
the turning. I either actually remain stationary and feel 
myself at rest, or I repress the motion toward the left. But 
for this I need to exert the same voluntary innervation as 
for an active turning to the right, which has also the same 
sensation as its result. 
8. 
At the time when my work on the Sensations of Move- 
ment was written, I had not yet attained to a thoroughly 
comprehensive view of the simple relation here described. 
I encountered, consequently, difficulties in the explanation 
of certain phenomena, observed partly by Breuer and 
partly by myself, which are now easy of explanation, and 
he is always introducing his own visual presentations by way of inter- 
pretation. Even so acute a mind as Diderot's can fall on occasion 
into the strange error of denying that the blind can imagine space. 
Cf. Loeb's work; on tactual space (p. 113, above), and Heller's Studien 
zur Blindenpsychologie (Leipzig, 1895). See Chapter IX. 
138 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
which I will briefly notice. If an observer be shut up in 
a closed receptacle, and the receptacle be set in rotation 
toward the right, it will appear to the observer as optically 
in rotation, although every ground of inference for relative 
rotation is wanting. If his eyes perform involuntary com- 
pensatory movements to the left, the images on the retina 
will be displaced, with the result that he has the sensation 
of movement toward the right. If, however, he fixes his 
eyes upon the receptacle, he must voluntarily compensate 
the involuntary movements, and thus again he is conscious 
of movement towards the right. It is plain, therefore, that 
Breuer's explanation of the apparent motion of optical 
vertigo is correct, and also that this movement cannot be 
made to disappear by the voluntary fixation of the eyes. 
The remaining cases of optical vertigo noticed in my work 
may be disposed of in like manner. 1 
In voluntary forward motion or rotation, we have not 
only a sensation of every single successive position of the 
parts of our body, but also the much more simple sensation 
of movement forward or of turning round. As a fact, we 
do not compound the notion of forward movement from 
the notions of the various individual movements of the 
legs, or at least we do not need to do so. There are cases, 
indeed, in which the sensation of forward movement is 
undoubtedly present while that of the movements of the 
legs is equally undoubtedly lacking. This is true, for 
instance, of a railway journey, or even of the thought of 
a journey, and may occur also in recalling a distant place, 
etc. The only possible explanation of this can be that the 
1 Grundlinien der Lehre von den Bewegiingsempfindungen, Leipzig, 
Engelmann, 1875, p. 83. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 139 
will to move forward or to turn about, which furnishes to 
the extremities their motor impulses, impulses which may 
be further modified by particular innervations, is of a com- 
paratively simple nature. The conditions existing here are pro- 
bably similar to, although more complicated than, those con- 
nected with the movements of the eyes, which Hering has so 
felicitously interpreted, and to which we shall presently return. 
We shall scarcely go far wrong if we suppose that the 
comparatively simple motor-sensations J stimulated from 
the labyrinth of the brain stand in the closest connexion 
with the will to move. These motor-sensations may also 
correspond to the feelings of direction which Riehl has 
postulated and investigated, 2 The blind man has them 
equally with the man of normal sight, and they probably 
form an important part of the foundation on which the 
understanding of tactual space reposes. 
I summed up a series of observations on optical sensations 
and motor-sensations in these words : " It looks as if visual 
space would turn into a second space, which is held to be 
immovably stationary, although this second space is char- 
acterized by complete absence of visibility." The space 
which is built up from motor-sensations seems, in fact, to 
be the original space. 3 
At that time I was preoccupied with physical methods 
of thought, and was consequently inclined to believe that 
sensations of progressive acceleration behaved in a manner 
completely analogous to sensations of angular acceleration. 
And in fact every physicist who studies this subject is liable 
1 Bewegungsempfindungen ) p. 124. 
2 Riehl, Der philosophische Kritizismus, Vol. II., p. 143. 
3 Beiuegtingsempfindtingen, p. 26. 
140 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
to think at once of the three equations for the rotatory 
movement of a body and the three equations for its move- 
ment of translation. I believed further, that, in accordance 
with the principle of specific energy, we ought to assume 
special sensations of the position of the head. 
Breuer, 1 in a later piece of research, has made it probable 
that the sensations of progressive acceleration vanish very 
much more quickly than those of angular acceleration, and 
that perhaps the organ of the former, at any rate in human 
beings, is atrophied. Further, Breuer finds that, except for 
the semicircular canals, B, the otolithic apparatus, <9, with 
its planes of sliding corresponding to the planes of the 
semicircular canals, is the only organ adapted to the signaliz- 
ing of progressive accelerations and position simultaneously. 
The three components of gravity corresponding to the three 
planes of sliding characterize the position of the head. Every 
alteration of the position alters these components, and in- 
stantaneously sets the apparatus of the semicircular canals 
going. But progressive accelerations alter these components 
without making any demands on the semicircular canals. 
Consequently, according to Breuer, the three combinations, 
O alone, O + B, and B alone, would suffice for the decision 
of all cases. Thus this theory, if it can be maintained, 
would be an important simplification. 
If I still had it in my power to carry out experiments, I 
would submit the motor-sensations in themselves to a re- 
newed and thorough investigation. The difference in the 
behaviour of the sensations of angular and progressive 
accelerations now seems to me significant. Acceleration of 
1 Breuer, " Ueber die Funktion des Otolithen-Apparates," Pfliiger's 
Archiv, Vol. XLVL, p. 195. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 141 
rotation gives rise to a sensation which, long after the 
acceleration has become nil, persists with a decreasing 
force which can be quantitatively x measured. Progressive 
acceleration is felt in its pure form only in the case of 
vertically accelerated falling or rising. When the accelera- 
tion vanishes the sensation also disappears quickly. The 
simplest means of producing a constant acceleration in a 
constant direction with respect to the body is by uniform 
rotation. We soon cease to have any sensation of uniform 
rotation. But a constant centrifugal acceleration also does 
not evoke the illusion of flying away in its direction, but 
rather calls up the sensation of changed position, which 
sensation again vanishes immediately with the disappearance 
of the centrifugal acceleration. Does this mean that pro- 
gressive acceleration exhausts itself as a stimulus, or that 
when the stimulus becomes constant the sensation changes 
in character ? In that case we shall have to suppose that 
the sensation is composed of two elements. 
We have sensations, not of uniform motion, but only of 
acceleration. To the elements of the change in progressive 
and angular velocity there correspond elements of the 
motor-sensations ; and, of these, those sensations at any 
rate which correspond to angular velocities persist with 
gradually decreasing force, and moreover are algebraically 
summable just like the sensations corresponding to pro- 
gressive velocities ; so that a sensation p, corresponding 
to the total change in velocity, and consequently to the 
velocity attained #, is correlated with a movement, usually 
of velocity nil upwards, set up in a short time. 2 Now the 
1 Beweg^mgsem.pfind^^ngen, p. 96, Experiment 2. 
- Bewegungsempfindungen, pp. 116 sqq. 
142 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
aggregate of sight and-touch-impressions that we passed in 
review increases with p and with the time /. We need not 
therefore be surprised that experience teaches us to 
interpret p conceptually as a velocity and pt as a path, 
although of course p in itself has nothing to do with con- 
cepts of spatial measurement. In this way it seems to 
me that we get rid of the last remaining paradox in the 
theory of the motor sensations. This paradox still troubled 
me in 1875, an d I see that it has also troubled others. 1 
The following experiments and reflexions, which form a 
sequel to an earlier publication of mine, 2 will perhaps assist 
us in obtaining a correct view of these phenomena. 
If we take our stand upon a bridge, and look fixedly at 
the water flowing beneath, we shall generally have the 
sensation of being ourselves at rest, whilst the water will 
seem in motion. Prolonged gazing, however, as is well 
known, almost invariably results in the sensation that 
suddenly the bridge, with the observer and his whole 
environment, begins to move in the direction opposite to 
that of the water, while the water assumes the appearance 
of being at rest. 3 The relative motion of the objects is in 
1 Bewegungsempfindungcn, p. 122. 
8 Bewegungsempfindungen^ p. 85. 
3 As we all know, the most varied forms of the same impression are 
obtained in the midst of a number of railway trains some of which are 
in motion and some at rest. A short time ago, while making a steam- 
boat excursion on the Elbe, I was astonished at getting the impression, 
just before landing, that the ship was standing still and that the whole 
landscape was moving towards it an experience that will be readily 
understood from what follows. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 143 
both cases the same, and there must therefore be some 
adequate physiological reason why at one time one, and at 
another another, part of them is felt to move. In order to 
investigate the matter at my leisure, I had the simple 
apparatus constructed which is represented in Fig. 18. An 
oil-cloth of simple pattern is drawn horizontally over two 
rollers, two metres long and fixed three metres apart in bear- 
ings, and is kept in uniform motion by means of a crank. 
Across the oil-cloth and about 
thirty centimetres above it, 
is stretched a string ff> with 
a knot K, which serves as a 
fixation-point for the eye of 
the observer stationed at A. 
Now, if the oil-cloth be set 
in motion in the direction of 
the arrow, and the observer 
follow the pattern with his eyes, he will see it in motion, 
himself and his surroundings at rest. on the other 
hand, if he gazes at the knot, he and the whole room 
will presently appear in motion in the contrary direction 
to the arrow, while the oil-cloth will stand still. This 
change in the aspect of the motion takes more or 
less time according to the mental condition of the 
observer, but usually requires only a few seconds. If we 
once get the knack of it, the two impressions may be made 
to alternate with some rapidity and at will. Every follow- 
ing of the oil-cloth brings the observer to rest, every fixation 
of K) or non-attention to the oil-cloth, by which its pattern 
becomes blurred, sets the observer in motion. Two in- 
vestigators, for whom I have the deepest respect, do not 
144 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
agree with me as to the result of this experiment in the 
circumstances indicated. one is William James, 1 the other 
Crum Brown. 2 I have performed the experiment over and 
over again with the same result. I am at present not in 
a position to carry out experiments, and must consequently 
renounce any idea of a new test ; but the method of after- 
images described by Brown seems to have much to recom- 
mend it. I pass over for the moment the different possible 
theoretical explanations of the experiment. 
10. 
This phenomenon, of course, must not be confounded 
with the familiar Plateau-Oppel phenomenon, which is a 
local retinal effect. In the preceding experiment, the entire 
environment, so far as it is distinctly visible, is in motion, 
whilst in the latter a moving veil is drawn along in front of 
the object, which is at rest. The attendant stereoscopic 
phenomena, for example, the appearance of the thread 
and knot underneath the transparent oil-cloth, are quite 
immaterial in this connexion. 
In my book on Bewegungsempfindungen (p. 63) I made it 
clear that the Plateau-Oppel phenomenon was the result ot 
a peculiar process, which had nothing to do with the other 
sensations of movement. I wrote there as follows : 
" We must therefore suppose that, during the movement 
of an image on the retina, a peculiar process is excited 
which is absent during rest, and that in the case of move- 
ments in opposite directions, very similar processes are 
1 W. James, Principles of Psychology, II., pp. 512, sqq. 
2 Crum Brown, " on Normal Nystagmus " (see p. 133 above). 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 145 
excited in similar organs, processes which are, however, 
mutually exclusive, so that with the commencement of the 
one, the other must cease, and with the exhaustion of the 
one, the other begins." 
This statement of mine seems to have been overlooked 
by S. Exner and Vierordt, who subsequently expressed 
similar views on the same subject. 
ii. 
Before we proceed to the explanation of the experiment 
(Fig. 1 8), it will be well to introduce a few variations. An 
observer stationed at B seems, under the same conditions, 
to be speeding, with all his surroundings, towards the left. 
We now place above the oil-cloth T T, Fig. 1 9, a mirror 
S S, inclined at an angle of 45 to the horizon. We 
observe the reflexion T T' in S S, after having placed on 
our nose a shade n , which intercepts 
the direct view of T Thorn the eye, O. 
If TT moves in the direction of the 
arrow, while we are looking at K f > the 
reflexion of K^ we shall presently fancy 
ourselves sinking downward with the 
whole room, whereas if the motion be 
reversed, we shall seem to ascend as Fig- 19. 
if in a balloon. 1 Finally, the experi- 
ments with the paper drum, which I have elsewhere de- 
o 
1 Such phenomena often make their appearance quite unsought. As 
my little daughter was once standing near a window, on a calm winter's 
day, during a heavy snowfall, she suddenly cried out that she and 
the whole house were rising upward. 
K 
146 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
scribed, 1 and to which the following explanation also applies, 
should be cited here. None of these phenomena are purely 
optical, but all are accompanied by unmistakable motor 
sensations of the whole body. 
12. 
What form, now, must our thoughts take on, in order to 
acquire the simplest explanatory setting for the preceding 
phenomena ? Objects in motion exert, as is well known, a 
peculiar motor stimulus upon the eye, and draw our atten- 
tion and our gaze after them. If the eye really follows 
them, we must assume, from what has gone before, that 
the objects appear to move. But if the eye is kept for some 
time at rest in spite of the moving objects, the constant 
motor stimulus proceeding from the latter must be com- 
pensated by an equally constant stream of innervation flow- 
ing to the motor apparatus of the eye, exactly as if the 
motionless point on which the eyes rest were moving uni- 
formly in the opposite direction, and we were following it 
with our eyes. But when this process begins, all motion- 
less objects on which the eyes are fastened must appear in 
motion. It is obviously unnecessary that this stream of 
innervation should always be consciously and deliberately 
called into action. All that is requisite is that it should 
proceed from the same centre and by the same paths as 
voluntary fixation. 
No special apparatus is necessary for observing the fore- 
1 Bewegungsempfindtmgen, p. 85. For more recent experiments see 
A. von, Szily, " Bewegungsnachbild und Bewegungskontrast," 
Ztitschrift far Psychologic nnd Physiologic der Sinnesorgane, 1905. 
Vol. XXXVIII., p. 81, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 147 
going phenomena. They are to be met with on all hands. 
I walk forward by a simple act of the will. My legs swing 
to and fro without my having to attend to them particularly. 
My eyes are fixed steadfastly upon my goal without suffer- 
ing themselves to be drawn aside by the motion of the 
retinal images consequent upon progression. All this is 
brought about by a single act of the will, and this act of the 
will itself is the sensation of forward movement. The same 
process, or at least a part of it, must also be set up, if the 
eyes are to resist for any length of time the stimulus of a 
mass of moving objects. Hence the motor sensations ex- 
perienced in the above experiments. 
The eyes of a child in a railway train will be observed to 
follow almost uninterruptedly and with a jerking motion the 
objects outside, which appear to it to be running. The 
adult has the same sensation if he will passively yield him- 
self to the natural impressions. If I am riding forwards, 
the whole space to my left, for obvious reasons, rotates, in 
the direction of the hands of a watch, about a very distant 
vertical axis and the space to my right does the same, but 
in the opposite direction. only when I resist following the 
objects with my eyes, does the sensation of forward motion 
arise. 
My views regarding the sensations of movement have 
been repeatedly attacked, as is well known, but invariably 
the adverse arguments have been aimed solely at the 
hypothesis, to which I attached comparatively little import- 
ance. That I am ready and willing to modify my views in 
accordance with newly discovered facts, the present work 
148 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
will testify. The decision as to how far I am in the right 
I will cheerfully leave to the future. on the other hand, I 
should like to mention that observations have been made 
that strongly favor the theory propounded by myself, Breuer, 
and Brown. To these belong, first, the facts collected by 
Dr. Guye of Amsterdam (Du Vertigo de Meniere : Rapport 
lu dans la section cFotologie dit congres periodique international 
de sciences medicales a Amsterdam^ 1879). Guye observed, 
in diseases of the middle ear, that reflex turnings of the 
head were induced when air was blown into the cavity of 
the tympanum, and found a patient who was able to state 
exactly the direction and number of the turnings which he 
had felt during the injection of liquids. Prof. Crum Brown 
(on a Case of Dyspeptic Vertigo," Proceedings of the 
Royal Society of Edinburgh, 1881-1882), has described an 
interesting case of pathological vertigo observed in him- 
self, which admitted of explanation, as a whole, by the 
increased intensity and lengthened duration of the sensa- 
tion incident upon every turning of the body. But most 
remarkable of all are the observations of William James 
(" The Sense of Dizziness in Deaf-Mutes," American Journal 
of Otology, Vol. IV., 1882). James discovered in deaf- 
mutes a striking and relatively general insensibility to the 
dizziness of whirling, often great uncertainty in their walk 
when their eyes were closed, and in many cases an astonish- 
ing loss of the sense of direction on being plunged under 
water, in which case there always resulted alarm and com- 
plete uncertainty as to up and down. These facts speak 
very strongly in favor of the view, which naturally follows 
from my conception, that in deaf-mutes the sense of 
equilibrium proper is considerably degenerated, and that 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 149 
the two other senses that give direction, the sense of sight 
and the muscular sense (the latter of which loses all its 
points of reference when the weight of the body is neutra- 
lized by immersion in water), are rendered proportionately 
more necessary. 
It is impossible to maintain the view that we arrive at 
knowledge of equilibrium and of movement solely by means 
of the semi-circular canals. on the contrary, it is extremely 
probable that lower animals, in whom this organ is entirely 
wanting, also have sensations of movement. I have not yet 
been able to undertake experiments in this direction. But 
the experiments which Lubbock has described in his work, 
Ants, Bees, and Wasps, become much more comprehensible 
to me on the assumption of sensations of movement. As 
experiments of this sort may be interesting to others, it will 
not be amiss perhaps to consider an apparatus which I have 
briefly described before (Anzeiger der Wiener Akademie, 
3oth December 1876). Other apparatuses of the same kind 
have since been constructed by Govi and Ewald. They have 
been called "cyclostats." 
The apparatus serves for the observation of the conduct 
of animals while in rapid rotation. Since, however, the 
view of the animal will necessarily be effaced by the rotatory 
motion, the passive rotation must be optically nullified and 
eliminated, so that the active movements of the animal 
alone shall be left and rendered observable. The optical 
neutralization of the rotatory motion is attained simply by 
causing a totally reflecting prism to revolve, with the aid of 
gearing, above the disk of the whirling machine, about 
exactly the same axis, in the same direction, and with half 
the angular velocity of the disk. 
150 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Fig. 20 gives a view of the apparatus. on the disk of the 
whirling machine is a glass receiver, g, in which the animals 
to be observed are enclosed. By means of gearing the eye- 
piece o is made to revolve with half the angular velocity 
and in the same direction as g. The following figure gives 
the gearing in a separate diagram. The eyepiece oo, and 
Fig. 20. 
the receiver gg, revolve about the axis A A, while a pair of 
cog-wheels, rigidly connected together, revolve about BB. 
Let the radius of the cog-wheel act, rigidly connected with 
gg, be = r. Then r is the radius of M, and 2^/3 is the 
radius of cc t but the radius of dd is = 4^/3, wherewith 
the desired relation of velocity between oo and gg is 
obtained. 
In order to centre the apparatus, a mirror S, provided 
with le veiling-screws, is laid upon the bottom of the receiver 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 151 
and so adjusted that, on rotation, the reflexions in it remain 
at rest. It is then perpendicular to the axis of rotation. A 
second small mirror, *S', in the silvering of which is a small 
hole Zj is so adjusted to the open tube of the eyepiece, 
with its reflecting surface downward, that, on rotation, the 
images seen through the hole, in the mirrored reflexion of 
S' in S, remain motionless. Then S' stands perpendicular 
to the axis of the eyepiece. With the aid of a brush we 
may now mark upon the mirror S a point P 9 whose position 
is not altered on rotation (a result which is easily accom- 
plished after a few trials), 
and so place the hole in 
the mirror S' that it also 
remains stationary on 
rotation. In this way J 
points on both axes of 
rotation are found. If 
now by means of screws 
we so adjust the eye- 
piece, that, on looking 
through the hole in S', 
the point P on S and the reflexion of L in S f (or really the 
many reflexions of P and Z) fall on the same spot, then 
the two axes are not only parallel but coincident. 
The simplest eyepiece that can be employed is a mirror 
whose plane coincides with the axis, and I adopted this 
device in the initial form of my apparatus. But one-half of 
the field of vision is lost by this method. A prism of total 
reflexion, therefore, is much more advantageous. Let ABC 
(Fig. 22) represent a plane section of such a prismatic eye- 
piece cut perpendicularly to the planes of the hypothenuse 
Fig. 21. 
152 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
and the two sides. Let this section include, also, the axis 
of rotation onPQ, which is parallel to AB. The ray 
which passes along the axis QP must, after refraction and 
reflexion in the prism, proceed again along the axis NO 
and will meet the eye O in the prolongation of the axis. 
This done, the points of the axis can suffer no displacement 
from rotation, and the apparatus is centred. The ray in 
question must accordingly fall at M, the middle point of 
AB, and, hence, since it falls on crown glass at an angle of 
incidence of 45, will meet AB 
at about 16 40'. Therefore, OP 
must be distant about 0*115 AB 
from the axis, a relation which 
can best be obtained by trial, by 
so moving the prism in the eye- 
piece that oscillations of the 
objects in gg during rotation are 
eliminated. 
Fig. 22 also shows the field of 
vision for the eye at O. The ray 
OA, which falls vertically upon 
AC, is reflected at AB in the 
direction AC and passes out 
towards S. The ray OR, on the 
other hand, is reflected at B and emerges, after refraction, 
in the direction of T. 
The apparatus has hitherto proved quite sufficient for 
my experiments. If a printed page is placed in gg, and the 
apparatus turned so rapidly that the image on the retina is 
entirely obliterated, one can easily read the print through 
the eyepiece. The inversion of the image by reflexion could 
Fig. 22. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 153 
be removed by placing a second, stationary reflecting prism 
above the revolving prism of the eyepiece. But this com- 
plication appeared to me unnecessary. 
With the exception of a few physical experiments, I have 
hitherto undertaken rotation-experiments only with various 
small vertebrates (birds, fishes), and have found the data 
given in my work on Motor Sensations fully confirmed. 
However, it would probably be of advantage to make 
similar experiments with insects and other lower animals, 
especially with marine animals. 
Such experiments have subsequently been carried out, 
with most instructive results, by Schafer (Natunvissen- 
schaftliche Wochenschrift, No. 25, 1891), by Loeb (Helio- 
tropismus der Tiere, Wiirzburg, 1890, p. 117), and by 
others. In my lecture " on Sensations of Direction " 
(Schriften des Vereins zur Verbreitung naturwissenschaft- 
licher Kenntnisse in Wien, 1897, and Populdrwissenschaft- 
liche Vorlesungen, 3rd edition, 1903) will be found the 
remainder of what I have to say on the sense of direction. 
But I should like to refer particularly to Breuer's researches 
on the otolithic apparatus, to Pollak and Kreidl's experi- 
ments on deaf-mutes, and above all to Ewald's work of 
fundamental importance, Ueber das Endorgan des Nervus 
octavus (Wiesbaden, 1892). In the third volume of the 
Handbuch der Physiologic des Menschen (1905), by W. 
Nagel, there is a full account of the "theory of the 
sensations of position, movement, and resistance." Since 
for some years past I have not been in a position to 
follow the experimental work that has been done in this 
department with any closeness, I have asked Professor 
Josef Pollak to give an account here of so much of the 
154 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
most recent work as is likely to interest readers of this 
book. Dr. Pollak has very kindly complied with my 
request, and the following paragraphs 14-19 are from 
his pen. 
14. 
The results in the course of the last ten years of 
morphological research and of research in comparative 
and experimental physiology in connexion with the laby- 
rinth of the ear (the cochlea, the semicircular canals, 
and the otolithic apparatus) have been almost without 
exception favorable to the Mach-Breuer hypothesis. 
It may now be taken as proved that the organ of hearing 
is constituted by the cochlea alone, and that the vestibular 
apparatus has no acoustic functions. A complete proof 
of this has been furnished by Biehl, 1 who, by intracranial 
operations on sheep, succeeded in severing the vestibular 
branch of the acoustic nerve without injuring the ramus 
cochlearis ; the result was that disturbances of equilibrium 
were produced, though the sense of hearing remained 
unaffected. Further, that part of the theory of the static 
function of the labyrinth is firmly founded and scarcely 
open to attack, which regards the semicircular canals as 
sense-organs that serve the perception of turnings of the 
head (and, mediately, of the body), especially since this 
hypothesis has received at the hands of Breuer important 
modifications based on his anatomical studies of the 
epithelial hairs of the ampullae. 2 
1 Karl Biehl, " Ueber intrakranielle Durchtrennung des Nervus 
vestibularis und deren Folgen," Sitzungsberichte of the Vienna Academy 
of Science, 1900. 
2 J. Breuer, "Studien liber den Vestibularapparat," Ibid., Vol. CXIL, 
1903. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 155 
This hypothesis now runs as follows : 
" Persistent uniform rotations are not felt, however 
rapid they are ; but the beginning and end of the rotation, 
acceleration and retardation, are felt. The ampullary 
apparatus is not affected by angular velocities that persist, 
but only by positive and negative angular accelerations. 
These cause a momentary displacement of the endolymph- 
ring and of the cupula terminalis (which as a consistent 
mass holds the epithelial hairs together in a constant 
figure of fixed shape), and, concomitantly, set up a 
tension of the cell-hairs and an excitement of the terminal 
apparatus of the nerves on one side of the crista involved. 
As long as these excitations last, they give rise to a sensa- 
tion of rotation, which persists until the contrary impulse 
of negative acceleration, when the rotation stops, or the 
gradual effect of the elasticity of the stretched complexes, 
restores the normal state of things again." 
The system of semicircular canals, moreover, possesses, 
like all other sense-organs, the property of giving rise not 
only to sensations but also to reflexes (Breuer, Delage, 
Nagel). Prominent among reactive organs are the muscles 
of the eyes, which communicate rotations to the eyes 
when the body rotates. 
Previously, however, the opinion had been conjecturally 
put forward by Mach that progressively accelerated motion 
could exercise no influence on the lymph enclosed in the 
semicircular canals; he had also suggested that special 
organs exist in the labyrinth for the perception of accelera- 
tions and for the sensation of the position of the head. 
156 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Breuer then succeeded in making it at least very probable 
that this function belongs to the otolithic apparatus. He 
supposes that the otoliths exert, by means of their weight, 
a definite pressure on the hair-cells underneath them. 
Every inclination of the head must change the position 
of the sacculus, and consequently that of the sense- 
epithelia also. By determining the position of the 
directions in which the otoliths slide for different positions 
of the head, Breuer shewed that an unambiguous pro- 
nouncement as to the position of the head is only made 
possible by the co-operation of the two sacks. " For every 
position of the head there is only one definite combina- 
tion of magnitudes of gravitation of the otoliths in the 
four maculae. When, as we suppose, the gravitation of the 
otoliths is felt, then every position of the head is charac- 
terized by a definite combination of these sensations." In 
the case of acceleration in a straight line, every shock that 
causes motion will evoke, owing to the inertia of the 
otolithic masses, a relative acceleration of these masses 
in the opposite direction, this relative acceleration repre- 
senting the adequate sensational stimulus. 
Heuristically, this part of the hypothesis is now on a very 
firm footing. It has become the basis of research on 
the lower animals in which otoliths alone occur, and in the 
case of higher animals also it has pointed the way to the 
isolation and experimental testing of the functions of the 
otoliths. 
From the mass of facts concerning the lower animals, 
which have been discovered of recent years, I will only 
select a few pregnant instances. The phenomena that 
result on the removal of the otoliths have been studied, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 157 
also the behaviour of animals under rotation and the com- 
pensatory movements. The experiments of Prentiss, 1 are 
particularly interesting. He first repeated Kreidl's famous 
experiments in compelling sloughing Crustacea to absorb 
" iron " otoliths ; he confirmed the fact that the behaviour 
of these towards magnets is in accordance with the theory. 
But he was also so fortunate as to obtain observations on 
free-swimming larvse of lobsters, which had been deprived 
of the power of growing otoliths after they had sloughed 
their skin. He was able to convince himself that they 
present the same phenomena as full-grown shrimps, from 
which the otoliths have been removed : they roll from one 
side to another, swim with belly upwards, are more easily 
turned over on to their backs than normal larvae, and, 
when they are blinded, the loss of equilibrium is still more 
striking. The same writer also describes as follows the 
behaviour of a crustacean (Virbius zostericula\ in which 
the statocyst is normally absent. 
" It is not a free-swimming form, but attaches itself to 
grasses, in the positions that are independent of gravity. 
If it is compelled to swim, it does so in a very uncertain 
manner, but generally back upwards. It is easily turned 
over on to its back, and, once in this position, is very slow 
at setting itself right. Its uncertain manner of swimming 
is reminiscent of that of other Crustacea after their stato- 
cysts have been destroyed. If the eyes are covered with 
lamp-black, all sense of direction in swimming is 
lost." 
The experiments of Prentiss recall those of K. L. 
1 " The Otocyst of Decapod Crustacea, its Structure, Development 
and Functions," Bulletin of the Museum of Comparative Zoology ', 
Harvard, 1900-1. (Quoted by Kreidl.) 
158 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Schafer. 1 Schafer rotated the larvae of frogs, and dis- 
covered that the first appearance of rotatory vertigo 
coincides in time with the completion of the formation of 
the semicircular canals. 
Ach's 2 researches on frogs are important. He discovered 
that the otoliths are connected with the lid-reflex of the 
crossed side ; from the fact that, in the case of a frog de- 
prived of its otoliths and subjected to rapid movement, 
the lid-reflex vanishes both horizontally and vertically, he 
concluded that the function of the otoliths is to subserve 
displacements of the body in a straight line in space. 
16. 

on the other hand, the wheel-like movements of the 
eyes that take place when the position of the head under- 
goes a series of changes, and the nystagmic movements 
caused by rotation and by passing a galvanic current through 
the head, have long been known and have been sufficiently 
analysed. The typical movements of the head, and the 
jerking movements of the eyes which are repeated at 
regular intervals when the head is continuously rotated 
or when a galvanic current is passed through it, and which 
can also be easily felt through the closed eyelids, are sure 
objective signs of vertigo. Nystagmus of eyes and head 
is completely absent in animals without a labyrinth, as has 
been shown by Ewald in the case of doves, and by Breuer 
1 K. L. Schafer, " Funktion und Funktionsentwicklung der Bogen- 
giinge, Zeitschrift fur Psychologic und Physiologic der Sinnesorgane, 
1894. 
2 Ach, " Ueber die Otolithenfunktion und Labyrinth tonus," Pfliiger's 
Archiv, Vol. LXXXVL, 1900. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 159 
in the case of cats, whose nervous octavus had been 
severed on both sides. Breuer and Kreidl have proved 
that the optical distortion of the vertical, experienced by 
anyone who rides in a whirling chair or sits in a railway 
train passing quickly enough over a sharp curve, depends 
upon a real wheel-like movement of the eyes. Again, we 
owe to Breuer the proof that individual ampullae, even 
when isolated, can be galvanically stimulated ; when that 
is done, they produce a movement of the head in the 
plane of the canal involved, whereas, according to Breuer, 
the consequence of diffused stimulation is the so-called 
galvanotropic reaction, consisting in an inclination of the 
head towards the anode. 
So much having been premised, the phenomena observed 
by James, 1 Kreidl 2 and Pollak 3 as resulting with deaf- 
mutes when affected with rotatory or galvanic vertigo, can 
easily be explained on the Mach-Breuer theory. Accord- 
ing to Mygind, 4 out of 118 deaf-mutes subjected to an 
anatomical examination, pathological changes of the 
vestibulary apparatus were present in 56 per cent. ; 50 to 
58 per cent, of the deaf-mutes experimented on by Kreidl 
felt no rotatory vertigo ; 2 1 per cent, of those on whom 
Kreidl reproduced the conditions of Mach's experiment 
with the whirling chair, did not succumb to the illusion as 
to position with respect to the vertical, which is inevitable 
1 William James, American Journal of Otology, 1887. 
2 A. Kreidl, " Beitrage zur Physiologic des Ohrlabyrinths auf 
Grund von Versuchen bei Taubstummen," Pfliiger's Archiv, Vol. LI. 
3 J. Pollak, " Ueber den galvanischen Schwindelbei Taubstummen," 
etc., 7^^., Vol. LIV. 
4 H. Mygind, " Ueber die pathologisch-anatomischen Veranderungen 
der Gehororgane Taubstummer," Ibid., Vol. XXV. 
i6o THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
in normal persons : they also without exception displayed, 
when rotated, no reflex movements of the eyes. The 
explanation of the lower percentage is that, according to 
Mygind's statistics, the semicircular canals are more 
frequently found to be diseased than the vestibule. 
Pollak found that 30% of the deaf-mutes he investigated 
experienced no galvanic vertigo, and that most of the deaf- 
mutes who display no eye-movements and no illusion as to 
the vertical when placed on the rotating platform or the 
whirling chair, are also devoid of the characteristic symptoms 
of galvanic vertigo. Further researches by Strehl, Kreidl, 
Alexander and Hammerschlag confirmed these facts ; the 
three latter discovered, further, that, when the deaf-mutes 
were divided into congenital deaf-mutes and those with 
acquired deafness, an extremely high percentage of the 
former (in Kreidl and Alexander's experiments 84/ , in 
Hammerschlag's 95%) displayed normal galvanic reaction, 
while only 29% of the subjects with acquired deafness 
reacted normally to the galvanic current. 
Congenital deaf-mutes, i.e., those with hereditary degenera- 
tion, behave in this connexion in the same way as Japanese 
dancing mice, the explanation of whose physiological 
behaviour lies, as Kreidl and Alexander I have shewn, in 
their anatomical structure. 
These mice are completely deaf, and progress in a sprawl- 
ing, hobbling fashion ; to a superficial observer their power 
of equilibrium seems unimpaired ; but if one tries experi- 
mentally to get them to move along a narrow path, the 
1 Alexander and Kreidl, " Zur Physiologic des Labyrinthes der 
Tanzmaus," Pfliiger's Archiv, I., II., III., Vols. LXXXIL, 
LXXXVIII. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 161 
high degree in which their power of balance is defective 
becomes immediately obvious. They are free from rotatory 
vertigo, but when a galvanic current is passed through their 
heads they behave like normal animals. Anatomical 
examination gives the following results. Destruction of the 
papilla basilaris cochleae, advanced emaciation of the ramus 
inferior of the eighth nerve, advanced atrophy of the spiral 
ganglion, destruction of the macula sacculi, medium 
emaciation of the branches and roots of the ramus superior 
and medius of the eighth nerve, and medium diminution of 
both vestibular ganglia. 
Among recent experiments in the field of comparative 
physiology. those of Dreyfuss 1 seem to me very remarkable. 
He observed the behaviour of normal guinea-pigs, and of 
guinea-pigs deprived of their labyrinths (operated on one 
side only and on both sides), when placed on a rotating 
platform, his special object being to study the compensatory 
movements of the eyeball and the head. He records a 
striking difference in the behaviour under rotation of the 
operated animal as contrasted with the behaviour of the 
intact animal. The animal that has been deprived of both 
labyrinths remains motionless in one place under rotation ; 
it displays no displacement of the longitudinal axis of the 
vertebral column, and no nystagmus of head or eyes. It 
is unconscious of the rotation. To prove this, Dreyfuss 
devised the following experiment in feeding the guinea-pigs. 
If four of them, one normal, one with the left, one with 
1 Dreyfuss, " Experimentale Beitrage zu der Lehre von der nichtakus- 
tischen Funktion des Ohrlabyrinthes," Pfluger's Archiv, Vol. LXXXI. 
162 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
the right, and one with both labyrinths destroyed, are 
placed on the rotating platform, and the experimenter waits 
until they have all begun to feed, the normal guinea-pig 
stops eating during rotation ; the guinea-pig without the 
right labyrinth goes on eating while the rotation is to the 
right, and stops when it is to the left; the one without 
the left labyrinth goes on eating when the rotation is to the 
left, and stops when it is to the right ; and the one with 
neither labyrinth goes on eating whichever the direction of 
rotation. Breuer and Kreidl obtained analogous results 
from comparative experiments with normal and acoustically 
defective cats. 
1 8. 
Morphologically, and from the teleological standpoint, 
Alexander's work on the organs of equilibrium and hearing 
in animals with congenitally defective visual apparatus, the 
mole (Talpa europced} and the blind mouse (Spalax typhlus^ 
is interesting. 1 
It is well-known that, in comparison with the lower 
animals, the vestibular apparatus in the higher animals and 
in man is defectively developed. In the case of all animals 
that are able to move in air or water, we find three nerve- 
ends carrying statoliths ; in the higher mammals there are 
only two. As regards the higher animals, Mach and Breuer 
have repeatedly emphasized the fact " that they are far from 
meaning to imply that the labyrinth alone furnishes the 
sensations necessary for the maintenance of equilibrium ; 
1 G. Alexander, " Zur Frage der phylogenetischen Ausbildung der 
Sinnesorgane," Zeitschrift fur Psychologic und Physiologic der Sinnes- 
organe, Vol. XXXVIII. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 163 
rather it co-operates to this end with the sense of pressure 
and the muscular sense, as well as with the sense of sight." 
It has never been denied, and is indeed quite certain, that 
absence or loss of the labyrinth-sensations can to a large 
extent be replaced by the other sense-perceptions just 
mentioned, so that, as Ewald pre-eminently has shewn, the 
major functions of the maintenance of equilibrium, such as 
walking and standing, can be adequately performed even 
when the labyrinth-function has been lost, or when there is 
some congenital defect in it. We see this, not only in the_ 
case of operated animals, but also in that of those deaf 
mutes in whom we have reason to assume some lesion of 
the semicircular canals (Breuer). However, James and 
Krei'dl have shewn that deaf-mutes who are not subject to 
rotatory vertigo are very unskilful in all the more delicate 
problems of balance. 
The mole, on the other hand, is an animal whose move- 
ments take place principally underground, though the 
surface on which it moves is solid ; moreover it dispenses 
almost completely with any sense of orientation by means 
of the organ of sight, and Alexander has shewn that this 
is fully compensated by its exquisite power of balance. This 
is anatomically expressed by the unusual size of the terminal 
nerve cells, by the relatively large number of the sense-cells, 
and especially by the presence, in the sinus utricularis 
inferior, of a macula neglecta which is wanting in other 
mammals, and which, apart from birds and reptiles, has 
only been found in one other lower mammal, Echidna 
aculeata. 
It is Alexander's merit to have proved that, in respect 
of the structure of its static terminal nerve-cells, Echidna 
164 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
represents the hitherto unknown transition from mammals 
to birds. Echidna possesses a cortical organ which, in histo- 
logical structure, corresponds with that of mammals, whereas 
in the number of the other terminal points of nerves it 
agrees with the labyrinth of birds ; in addition to the three 
macular nerve-terminations (macula utriculi, macula sacculi, 
and macula lagenae) it exhibits a macula neglecta Retzii. 
19. 
The results of these researches, of which only a small 
selection has been mentioned, may be summed up as follows. 
The compensation in the visual field of every movement of 
the head by means of movements of the eyes, which are 
carried out also by the blind and by normal persons with 
their eyes shut ; the absence of these movements in many 
deaf-mutes ; the nystagmus of the eyes that takes place 
under continued rotation ; the wheel-like movement of the 
eyes when the direction of the acceleration of masses in the 
body is altered by a centrifugal force ; rotatory vertigo and 
its law; the absence "of this vertigo in many deaf-mutes; 
finally, the identical character of galvanic vertigo in man 
and in animals, all these facts serve strongly to confirm 
the theory of Mach and Breuer, although it cannot be denied 
that many questions still remain unsolved. As against other 
hypotheses, such as those of Ewald and Cyon, this theory has 
at any rate the advantage that, in the case of the ampullary 
and otolithic apparatus, it provides a clearer explanation of 
the specific disposition to the adequate stimulus than we 
have for any other sense organ, and also that, in accord- 
dance with it, the two sense-organs in the labyrinth are 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 165 
readily brought under the principle of specific sense- 
energies (Nagel). In any case the sensation of motion is 
proved to be a special and peculiar department of sensa- 
tion. 
20. 
Professor Pollak's communication here comes to an end. 
Without doing violence to the facts described in my 
book on The Sensations of 'Movement ', the preceding observa- 
tions suggest the possibility of modifying the theoretical 
view there taken of the facts, as we shall point out in what 
follows. It remains extremely probable that an organ 
exists in the head it may be called the terminal organ 
(TO] which reacts upon accelerations, and by means 
of which we are made aware of movements. To me person- 
ally the existence of sensations of movement, of the same 
nature as other sensations, does not seem doubtful, and I 
can scarcely understand how anyone, who has really re- 
peated on himself the experiments in question, can deny 
the existence of these sensations. 
But instead of imagining that the terminal organ excites 
special motor-sensations, which proceed from this apparatus 
as from a sense-organ, we might also assume that this organ 
simply disengages innervations after the manner of reflexes. 
Innervations may be voluntary and conscious or involuntary 
and unconscious. The two different organs from which 
these proceed may be designated by the letters WI and 
UI. Both sorts of innervation may pass to the oculo- motor 
apparatus (OM) and to the locomotor apparatus (LM). 
Let us now consider the accompanying diagram. We 
induce by the will, that is by a stimulus from WI> an active 
166 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
movement, which passes in the direction of the unfeathered 
arrows, to OM and LM. The appropriate innervation, 
whether it precedes or follows the movement, is directly 
felt. In this case, therefore, a specific sensation of move- 
ment, differing from the innervation, is unnecessary. If the 
motion in the direction of the unfeathered arrows is a 
passive one (taking us by surprise), then, as experience 
shews, reflexes pass from TO to 77, which produce com- 
pensatory movements, indicated by the feathered arrows. 
If WI takes no part in the process, and the compensation 
is effected, both the 
motion and the neces- 
sity for motor sensa- 
tion are absent. But 
if the compensatory 
movement is inten- 
tionally suppressed, 
that is, by intervention 
Fig. 23. from WI, then the 
same innervation is 
necessary for achieving this result as for active movement, 
and it consequently produces the same motor sensation. 
The terminal organ TO is accordingly so adjusted to 
WI and UI that upon a given motor stimulus in the first, 
contrary innervations are set up in the last two. But 
further, we have to notice the following difference in the 
relation of TO to fF/and UI. For TO, the motor excita- 
tion is naturally the same whether the movement induced 
is passive or active. In active movements, too, the inner- 
vations proceeding from WI would eventually be neutralized 
by TO and UI, did not an inhibitory innervation proceed 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 167 
simultaneously with the willed innervation from WI to TO 
or UI. The influence of TO upon WI must be conceived 
as much weaker than its influence upon UI. If we should 
picture to ourselves three animals, WI, UI, and TO, 
between whom there was a division of labor, such that the 
first executed only movements of attack, the second only 
those of defence or flight, while the third filled the post of 
sentinel, all of whom were united into a single new organism 
in which WI held the dominant position, we should have a 
conception approximately corresponding to the relation 
represented. There is much in favor of such a conception 
of the higher animals. 1 
I do not offer the preceding view as a complete and 
perfectly apposite picture of the facts. on the contrary, I 
am fully aware of the defects in my treatment. But the 
attempt to reduce to one and the same quality of sensation, 
in accordance with the cardinal principle evolved in our 
investigation (p. 62), all sensations of space and movement 
which arise in the province of sight and touch during 
change of place, and which, even when locomotion is only 
remembered, or a distant spot only thought of, arise in a 
shadowy form, will be found to be not without justification. 
The assumption that this quality of sensation is the will, 
so far as the will is occupied with position in space and 
spatial movement, or that it is innervation, does not fore- 
1 If I grasp a little bird in my hand, the bird will behave towards 
my hand exactly as a human being would towards a giant cuttle-fish. 
In watching a company of little children whose movements are largely 
unreflecting and unpractised, the hands and eyes remind one very 
strongly of polypoid creatures. Of course, such impressions do not 
afford solutions of scientific questions, but it is often very suggestive to 
abandon oneself to their influence. 
168 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
stall future investigation and only represents the facts as 
they are known at the present time. 1 
21. 
From the discussions of the previous chapter relative to 
symmetry and similarity, we may immediately draw the 
conclusion that to like directions of lines which are seen, 
the same kind of innervation-sensations, and to lines 
symmetrical with respect to the median plane very similar 
sensations of innervation correspond, but that with looking 
upwards and looking downwards, or with looking at ob- 
jects afar off and at objects near at hand, very different 
sensations of innervation are associated, as we should 
naturally be led to expect from the symmetrical arrange- 
ment of the motor apparatus of the eye. With this single 
observation we explain at once a long chain of peculiar 
physiologico-optical phenomena, which have as yet received 
scarcely any attention. I now come to the point which, at 
least from the physical point of view, is the most important. 
The space of the geometrician is a mental construction 
of three-dimensional multiplicity, that has grown up on the 
basis of manual and intellectual operations. Optical space 
(Hering's "sight-space") bears a somewhat complicated 
geometrical relationship to the former. The matter may 
be best expressed in familiar terms by saying that optical 
space represents geometrical space (Euclid's space) in a 
1 Compare Hering's opinion given in Hermann's Handbiich der 
Physiologie^ Vol. III., Part I., p. 547. I do not wish to conceal the 
method by which I was led to my theory, although now the view repre- 
sented by James, Miinsterberg and Hering, as explained in Chapter 
VIII., seems to me preferable. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 169 
sort of relievo-perspective a fact which can be teleo- 
logically explained. In any event, optical space also is a 
three-dimensional multiplicity. The space of the geome- 
trician exhibits at every point and in all directions the 
same properties a quality which is by no means charac- 
teristic of physiological space. But the influence of 
physiological space may nevertheless be abundantly 
observed in geometry. Such is the case, for example, 
when we distinguish between convex and concave curva- 
tures. The geometrician should really know only the 
amount of deviation from the mean of the ordinates. 
22. 
As long as we conceive the (12) muscles of the eye to be 
separately innervated, we are not in a position to understand 
the fundamental fact that optical space is presented as a 
three-dimensional multiplicity. I felt this difficulty for 
years, and also recognized the direction in which, on the 
principle of the parallelism of the physical and the psychical, 
the explanation was to be sought ; but owing to my defec- 
tive experience in this province, the solution itself remained 
hidden from me. All the better, therefore, am I able to 
appreciate the service rendered by Hering, who discovered 
it. To the three optical space co-ordinates, viz., to the 
sensations of height, breadth and depth, corresponds 
according to the shewing of this investigator (Hering, 
Beitrdge zur Physiologic, Leipzig, Engelmann, 1861-1865; 
Die Lehre vom binokularen Sehen, 1868) simply a threefold 
innervation, which turns the eyes to the right or to the 
left, raises or lowers them, and causes them to converge, 
170 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
according to the respective needs of the case. This is the 
point which I regard as the most important and essential. 1 
Whether we regard the innervation itself as the space- 
sensation, or whether we conceive the space-sensation as 
before or behind the innervation, a question neither 
easy nor necessary to decide, nevertheless Hering's 
account throws a flood of light on the psychical obscurity 
of the visual process. The phenomena cited by myself 
with regard to symmetry and similarity, moreover, accord 
excellently with this conception. But it is unnecessary, 
I think, to dwell any further on this. 2 
1 This is the point to which reference was made above (p. 122, note 
i, p. 138). 
2 This conception also removes a difficulty which I still felt in 1871, 
and to which I gave utterance in my lecture on " Symmetry " (Prague, 
Calve, 1872), now translated into English in my Popular Scientific 
Lectures, Chicago, 1894, in the following words : "The possession of 
a sense for symmetry by persons who are one-eyed from birth is certainly 
an enigma. Yet the sense for symmetry, although originally acquired 
by the eyes, could not have been confined exclusively to the visual 
organs. By thousands of years of practice it must also have been 
implanted in other parts of the human organism, and cannot, therefore, 
be immediately eliminated on the loss of an eye." As a fact, the 
symmetrical apparatus of innervation remains, even when one eye 
is lost. 
VIII. THE WILL. 
i. 
IN what precedes, the phrase " the will " has often been 
used, and has always been intended merely to denote a 
generally recognized psychic phenomenon. I do not mean 
by the will any special psychical or metaphysical agent, nor 
do I assume a specific psychical causality. Rather, I am 
convinced, in company with the overwhelming majority of 
physiologists and modern psychologists, that the phenomena 
of volition must to put it briefly, but in a way that 
everyone can understand be explained by means of the 
physical forces of the organism alone. I would not lay any 
special emphasis on the fact that this is a matter of course, 
were it not that the remarks of many critics have shewn the 
emphasis to be necessary. 
The movements of lower animals, and, equally, the first 
movements of all new-born animals, are immediately set 
free by some stimulus; they follow the stimulus quite 
mechanically;, they are reflex movements. Nor are such 
reflex movements absent in the later stages of the lives of 
higher animals, and when the occasion arises for us to 
observe them for the first time in ourselves, for instance, 
the sinew-reflexes, we are as much surprised by them as by 
any unexpected event in our environment. The behaviour 
of the young sparrow described above (p. 74) depends on 
reflex movements. The chick pecks quite mechanically at 
171 
172 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
everything that it sees, just as the child grasps at everything 
that strikes its notice, and, on the other hand, withdraws 
its limbs from every unpleasant contact without any co- 
operation of the intellect. For there are fixed organic 
arrangements which determine the preservation of the 
organism. If we adopt Hering's views on living sub- 
stance, according to which living substance strives towards 
the equilibrium of the antagonistic processes taking place 
in it, we shall be forced to ascribe to the elements of the 
organism themselves this tendency towards self-preservation 
or actual stability. 
Sensational stimuli can be partly or wholly replaced by 
memory-images. All memory-traces that remain behind 
in the - nervous system co-operate with the sensations to 
set free, to assist, to inhibit and to modify the reflexes. It 
is in this way that voluntary movement arises, since we can 
conceive voluntary movement, at any rate in principle, as 
reflex movement modified by memories, however far we 
may fall short of understanding it in detail. The child that 
has once burnt itself at a bright flame refrains in future from 
grasping at the flame, because the grasp-reflex is inhibited 
by the antagonistic avoidance-reflex which the memory of 
the pain sets free. The chick begins by pecking at every- 
thing; but soon, under the influence partly of inhibitory 
and partly of encouraging memories of taste, it exercises a 
choice. The gradual transition from reflex movement to 
voluntary action can be very prettily followed in the 
case of our sparrow (p. 74 above). For the reflecting 
subject, the characteristic mark of voluntary action, as 
distinct from reflex movement, lies in the subject's re- 
cognition that the determining factor in voluntary action 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 173 
is his own presentations, which anticipate this action 
(p. 100 above). 
2. 
The psychic processes that accompany voluntary action 
and voluntary movement have been admirably analysed by 
William James x and by Hugo Miinsterberg. 2 It seems a 
simple and natural view to suppose that the actual move- 
ment is associated with the imagined movement in the same 
way as one presentation is associated with another. But 
as regards the sensations of the kind and amount of the 
movement, and of the amount of effort involved, which 
are connected with the execution of the movement, two 
opposite views are taken. According to one view, which 
is held by Bain, Wundt and Helmholtz, the innervation 
which flows to the muscles is itself felt. James and 
Miinsterberg take a different view. They hold that all 
the kinaesthetic sensations that accompany a movement are 
peripherally excited by sensible elements in the skin, the 
muscles and the joints. 
Against the hypothesis of the central origin of the 
kinaesthetic sensations we have to set, first and foremost, 
the observations on anaesthetic subjects, 3 who, when their 
sensations are cut off, are able to give no account of the 
passive movement of their limbs, although they are able to 
move their limbs under the guidance of the sense of sight. 
We feel the exertion of a faradised muscle just as much 
as in the case of a muscle that is voluntarily innervated. 4 
1 W. James, Principles of Psychology ', Vol. II., pp. 486 sqq. 
2 H. Miinsterberg, Die Willenshandlung, Freiburg im Breisgau, 1888. 
3 W. James, op. fit., Vol. II., p. 489. 
W. James, op. at., Vol. II., p. 502. 
174 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
The hypothesis of specific sensations of innervation is not 
required for the explanation of the phenomena, and, on the 
principle of economy, is consequently to be avoided. 
Finally, sensations of innervation are not directly observed. 
A special difficulty is constituted by certain optical pheno- 
mena, to which we shall return. 
The law of association connects not merely processes 
that emerge into consciousness (presentations), but also the 
most diverse organic processes. The man who blushes 
readily when he is embarrassed, whose hands sweat readily, 
etc., generally observes these processes taking place in him- 
self the moment he is reminded of them. For purposes of 
study Newton 1 acquired a dazzling after-image by gazing 
at the sun; this image disappeared, but during a period of 
several months, although he remained for several days in 
the dark, it always returned with full sensational intensity 
the moment he reminded himself of it. It was only by 
diverting his attention by a long-continued and violent 
psychic effort that he was able to get rid of this trouble- 
some phenomenon. Boyle narrates a similar observation 
in his book on colors. When brought into connexion 
with these facts, the association of motor processes with 
presentations ceases to appear strange. 
An apoplectic stroke which I experienced in 1898, with- 
out its in the least affecting my consciousness, has made 
me personally familiar with part of the facts now under 
1 King's Life of Locke, 1830, Vol. I., p. 404 ; Brewster, Memoirs of 
Newton, 1855, Vol. I., p. 236. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 175 
consideration. I was in a railway train, when I suddenly 
observed, with no consciousness of anything else being 
wrong, that my right arm and leg were completely paralysed; 
the paralysis was intermittent, so that from time to time I 
was able to move again in an apparently quite normal way. 
After some hours it became continuous and permanent, 
and there also set in an affection of the right facial muscle, 
which prevented me from speaking except in a low tone 
and with some difficulty, I can only describe my condition 
during the period of complete paralysis by saying that when 
I formed the intention of moving my limbs I felt no effort, 
but that it was absolutely impossible for me to bring my 
will to the point of executing the movement. on the other 
hand, during the phases of imperfect paralysis, and during 
the period of convalescence, my arm and leg seemed to me 
enormous burdens which I could only lift with the greatest 
effort. It seems to me plausible to suppose that this was 
caused by the energetic innervation of other muscle-groups 
in addition to the muscles of the paralysed extremities. 1 
The paralysed limbs retained their sensibility completely, 
except for one place on the thigh, and thus I was enabled 
to be aware of their position and of their passive movements. 
I found that the reflex excitability of the paralysed limbs 
was enormously heightened; this expressed itself particu- 
larly in violent jerks on the slightest alarm. Optical and 
tactual motor-images persisted in my memory. Very often 
during the day I formed the intention to do something with 
my right hand, and had to think of the impossibility of 
doing it. To the same source are to be referred the vivid 
dreams which I had of playing the piano and writing, 
1 W. James, op. cit. y Vol. II., p. 503. 
176 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
accompanied by astonishment at the ease with which I 
wrote and played, and followed by bitter disappointment 
on awaking. Motor hallucinations also occurred. I often 
thought that I felt my paralysed hand opening and shutting, 
and at the same time the total movement seemed to be 
hampered as if by a loose, but stiff glove. But I had only 
to look to convince myself that there was not the slightest 
movement. Over the flexors of this hand I have ac- 
quired a very slight control, but over the extensors none 
at all. 
Since the sensibility of the hand is preserved, while the 
power of voluntary movement is lacking, I do not know 
how to explain the illusion of movement properly, even on 
the new theory. The muscles that are withdrawn from the 
influence of the will react now to the most diverse stimuli, 
so that the hand is sometimes extended and sometimes 
clenched. Strong tastes of different qualities seem to act 
as stimuli to different extents on different muscles of my 
paralysed hand. Water impregnated with sulphate of 
magnesia, for example, excites involuntary movements of 
tension in the thumb and the two fingers next to it. 
The theory of James and Miinsterberg fits these facts, 
as I think, without any straining, and we ought therefore to 
consider it as correct in essentials. The innervation is not 
felt, but the consequences of the innervation set up new 
peripheral sensible stimuli, which are connected with the 
execution of the movement. There are, however, some 
difficulties which prevent me from believing that this view 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 177 
which was originally my own, 1 completely explains the 
facts. 

one would think that the central process which condi- 
tions the mere presentation of a movement must differ in 
some respect from the process which also releases an actual 
movement. To be sure, the strength of the process, the 
absence of antagonistic processes, and the extent to which 
the innervation-centres are charged, may be partial deter- 
minants; but still it is scarcely possible to deny that 
further explanation is required. In particular, the difference 
in behaviour of the muscles of the eye and the other 
muscles that can be excited at will needs closer investiga- 
tion. Most muscles have variable amounts of work to 
perform, and it is of practical importance for us to know 
these amounts approximately. The work done by the eye- 
muscles, on the other hand, is small, and is always exactly 
connected with the alteration in position of the eyes ; this 
latter alone is of optical importance, while the work" as such 
is matter of indifference. This may be the reason why the 
kinaesthetic sensations play such a much greater part in the 
case of the muscles of the extremities. 
5- 
Hering 2 has shewn how small is the importance of the 
sensations proceeding from the muscles of the -eye. 
1 Before the phenomena connected with paralysis of the eye-muscles 
were known to me, z'.<?., before 1863. 
2 Hering in Hermann's Handbuch der Physiologie^ Vol. III., I, 547. 
Cf. also Hillebrand, " Verhaltnis der Akkommodation und Konvergenz 
zur Tiefenlokalisation," Zeitschrift fur Psychologic und Physiologic der 
Sinnesorgane t Vol. VII., pp.97, sqq. 
M 
178 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Usually we scarcely attend at all to the movements 
of our eyes, and the position of objects in space remains 
uninfluenced by these movements. If one imagines two 
spherical surfaces, covered with movable retinae, and 
remaining fixed in space while the retinse revolve, a super- 
ficial consideration might even induce us to believe that 
the space-values of the objects seen would only be deter- 
mined by the two positions of reflexion on the fixed 
spheres. But the facts mentioned on p. 127 above, compel 
us to separate these space-values into two components, one 
of which depends on the co-ordinates of the point of 
reflexion on the retina, and the other on the co-ordinates 
of the point of vision, which components undergo mutually 
compensating alterations corresponding to voluntary altera- 
tions of the point of vision. 1 Now, if we refuse to admit 
a sensation of innervation, and deny the importance of 
the peripherally excited kinaesthetic sensations of the eye- 
muscles, the only remaining alternative is that adopted by 
Hering, namely to regard the position of attention as 
determined by a definite psycho-physical process, which at 
the same time is the physical factor that releases the corre- 
sponding innervation of the eye-muscles. 2 But this process 
is still a central process, and "attention " remains scarcely 
different from " the will to see." In this way I might still 
hold in essentials to my expression on p. 130 above; for 
which of the series of processes excited from and pro- 
1 Cf. p. 114 above ; Hering, op. ?., pp. 533, 534. I am now unable 
to decide whether the view that the alteration of the space-values is 
completed immediately with the change in attention can be brought 
into harmony with the fact mentioned on p. 130 above. 
- Hering, op. cit. t pp. 547, 548. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 179 
ceeding from the centre is the one that enters into 
sensation, is a many-sided problem which can for the 
present remain unsolved. 
6. 
In conformity with what precedes, we might replace, in 
the explanation attempted on p. 166 above, the two 
antagonistic innervations by two antagonistic processes of 
attention, one excited by the sensible stimulus, and the 
other a central process. I cannot give my assent to the 
explanation proposed by James 1 of the phenomena con- 
nected with paralysis of the muscles of the eye, since this 
explanation seems, formally at any rate, to drift towards 
the doubtful waters of " unconscious inferences." In the 
case under discussion we are concerned with sensations 
and not with the results of reflexions. 
The function of the muscles of the eyes is merely to 
ensure our orientation in space ; that of the muscles of the 
limbs is principally the performance of mechanical work. 
We thus have here two extreme cases, between which there 
will lie many middle terms. When we see the newly- 
hatched chick pecking and hitting its mark accurately, it is 
easy to believe that the muscles of its neck and head to 
some extent perform a similar office to that of its eye- 
muscles, and act as an apparatus of spatial orientation. 
Probably the jerking movements of the head which take 
place in birds when they walk forward, are executed, like 
nystagmic movements of the head under rotation, in the 
1 W. James, op. cit. y Vol. II., p. 506. 
i8o THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
interests of orientation. The muscles of the extremities 
also cannot be entirely without analogy to the eye-muscles. 
Otherwise how could we understand the blind man's tactual 
presentation of space ? For it is not easy to combine a 
nativistic theory of visual space with an empirical theory 
of tactual space. 1 
1 Cf. p. 135 above, note 2, and p 138. 
IX. BIOLOGICO-TELEOLOGICAL 
CONSIDERATIONS AS TO SPACE. 1 
i. 
WE have already repeatedly had occasion to notice 
how very different the system of our space-sensa- 
tions our physiological space, if we may use the expression 
is from geometrical (by which is here meant Euclidean) 
space. This is true, not only as regards visual space, but 
also as regards the blind man's tactual space in comparison 
with geometrical space. Geometrical space is of the same 
nature everywhere and in all directions, it is unlimited and 
(in Riemann's sense) infinite. Visual space is bounded and 
finite, and, what is more, its extension is different in 
different directions, as a glance at the flattened " vault of 
heaven " teaches us. Bodies shrink when they are removed 
to a distance ; when they are brought near they are enlarged : 
in these features visual space resembles many constructions 
1 This subject cannot be treated in detail here. I may refer to my 
articles in The Monist> of which the first appeared in April 1901, the 
second in July 1902, and the third in October 1903. The physiological 
considerations outlined here are partly related to Wlassak's views as 
stated in his paper, " Ueber die statischen Funktionen des Ohrlaby- 
rinthes " Vierteljahrsschrift fur wissenschaftliche Philosophic^ Vol. 
XVII., I, p. 28), except that I assume, not one, but two, reactions to 
the stimuli in question. Cf. also the passages cited above from Hering, 
and W. James, Psychology, Vol. II., pp. 134, sqq. Cf. also my 
Erkenntnis imd Itrtum, 1905, pp. 331-414, 426-440, 
181 
182 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
of the metageometricians rather than Euclidean space. 
The difference between "above" and "below," between 
" before " and behind," and also, strictly speaking, between 
"right and left," is common to tactual space and visual 
space. In geometrical space there are no such differences. 
For man, and for animals of similar structure to man, 
physiological space is related to geometrical very much as 
a "triclinal" is to a "tesseral" medium. This is true for 
men and animals, so long as they are not endowed with 
freedom of movement and of orientation. When mobility 
is added, physiological space approximates to Euclidean, 
though without completely attaining to the simplicity of the 
properties of Euclidean space. Three-dimensional multi- 
plicity and continuity are common to geometrical and to 
physiological space. To the continuous movement of a 
point A in geometrical space, corresponds a continuous 
movement of a point A' in physiological space. We have 
only to remember the difficulties which the doctrine of the 
antipodes had to overcome, to see how geometrical space- 
presentations can be disturbed by physiological. Even our 
most abstract geometry does not employ purely metrical 
notions, but uses also such physiological conceptions as 
direction, sense, right, left, etc. 
In order to keep the physiological and geometrical 
factors completely apart, we have to reflect that our space- 
sensations are determined by the dependence of the 
elements which we have called ABC... upon the 
elements of our body K L M . . . but that geometrical 
conceptions are formed by means of the spatial comparison 
of bodies by the relations of the A B C's ... to one 
another. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 183 
If we consider the spatial sensations not as isolated 
phenomena, but in their biological connexion, in their 
biological function, they become easier to understand, at 
any rate teleologically. As soon as an organ or a system of 
organs is stimulated, movements take place as reflex 
reactions ; these movements are generally purposive, and 
may be defensive or offensive, according to the nature 
of the stimulus. For example, different places on the skin 
of a frog may be successively stimulated by dropping acid 
on them. To each excitation the frog will reply by a 
specific defensive movement according to the spot stimu- 
lated. The stimulation of places on the retinae sets free 
the equally specific reflex of snapping. That is to say, 
alterations that make their entrance into the organism by 
different paths are reproduced externally also by different 
paths on the animal's environment. Now, let us suppose 
that, in complicated conditions of life, such reactions can 
also arise spontaneously by memory, that is to say, on a 
slight impulse, and that they can be modified by memories ; 
then traces, corresponding to the nature of the stimulus 
and to the stimulated organs, must remain behind in the 
memory. As our observation of ourselves teaches us, we not 
only recognize identity of quality in the stimulus of burning, 
whatever be the spot burnt, but at the same time we 
distinguish between the spots stimulated. We must there- 
fore suppose that there is attached to the qualitatively 
identical sensation an element of difference, which depends 
on the specific nature of the elementary organ stimulated, 
on the spot stimulated, or, to use Hering's expression, on 
184 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
the "place of attention." It is precisely in the perception 
of space that the intimate mutual biological adaptation of a 
multiplicity of connected elementary organs is displayed 
with peculiar clearness. 
3- 
Let us assume only one kind of element of consciousness, 
namely sensations. In so far as we have spatial perceptions, 
these depend, according to our theory, on sensations. What 
is the nature of these sensations, and what organs are active 
in connexion with them, we must leave an open question. 
We have to imagine a system of elementary organs of 
common embryological origin as being naturally so arranged 
that neighbouring elements display the greatest ontological 
affinity, and that this affinity decreases as the segregation 
of the elements from one another increases. The organic 
sensation, which alone depends upon the individuality of 
the organ, and which varies with the variation in the degree 
of affinity, will correspond to the sensation of space, and 
from this we distinguish the sensations which depend on 
the quality of the stimulus as specific sensations. Organic 
sensations and specific sensations can only appear con- 
comitantly. 1 But, over against the varying specific sensa- 
tions, the unchanging organic sensations presently constitute 
a fixed register, in which the former are arranged. We are 
here only making as to the elementary organs similar pre- 
suppositions such as we should find natural in the case of 
separated individuals of the same descent but of different 
degrees of affinity. 
1 Similarly the internal organs are only sensed and localized when 
some disturbance of their equilibrium takes place. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 185 
The perception of space has arisen from biological 
necessities, and can best be understood by reference to 
these necessities. An endless system of space-sensations 
would not only be purposeless for the organism, but would 
also be physically and physiologically impossible. Space- 
sensations which should be orientated with reference to 
the body would also be valueless. It is also advantageous 
that, in visual space, the sensation-indices for nearer objects, 
which are biologically the most important, should be more 
sharply graded, while as regards more remote, and con- 
sequently less important, objects, the limited supply of 
indices is used economically. This relation, again, is the 
only one physically possible. 
The following considerations enable us to understand the 
motor organization of the visual apparatus. The greater 
clearness and the finer distinctions that exist at a given 
spot on the retina of the eye of a vertebrate are an economic 
arrangement. By this means a movement of the eyes that 
follows a change of attention is recognized as advantageous, 
just as the influence of a voluntary movement of the eyes 
on the space-sensation caused by objects at rest is re- 
cognized as disadvantageous, if it is misleading. Neverthe- 
less the displacement of images on the retina, which itself 
remains at rest, is biologically necessary, in order to enable 
us to perceive moving objects with our eyes at rest : the 
only case in which it is unnecessary for the organism, is 
the very rare one when it is required to perceive an object 
at rest when the eye is moved by some cause that does not 
emerge into consciousness, such as an external mechanical 
186 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
force or a twitching of the muscles. The only solution that 
provides for all the foregoing requirements is that, when the 
eye is moved voluntarily, the displacement of images on the 
retina corresponding to this movement should be com- 
pensated by the voluntary movement in respect of space- 
value. But from this it follows, that when the eye is kept 
still, the mere intention to move the eye must cause objects 
at rest to undergo some displacement in visual space. By 
means of a suitable experiment (p. 128 above) the existence 
of the second also of the two mutually compensatory com- 
ponents is directly proved. These organic arrangements 
are ultimately the reason why under peculiar circumstance, 
when our eyes are at rest, objects at rest appear to move 
and the space-values to fluctuate, why we see bodies in 
motion, which nevertheless do not change their position 
relative to our body, and neither move farther away nor 
come nearer. What seems paradoxical under these peculiar 
circumstances, is, under ordinary circumstances (those of spon- 
taneous locomotion) of the highest biological importance. 
The relations of tactual space are, apart from certain 
peculiarities, similar to those of visual space. The sense 
of touch is not a long-range sense ; there is no perspec- 
tival shrinkage and enlargement of tactual objects. But 
otherwise the phenomena which we find here are akin 
to those of vision. The finger-tips correspond to the 
macula lutea. We can tell the difference perfectly well 
between passing our finger-tips over a motionless object 
and the movement of an object over our motionless finger- 
tips. Analogous paradoxical phenomena connected with 
rotatory vertigo appear here also. They were known to 
Purkinje. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 187 
Biological considerations of a general nature force us to 
conceive optical and tactual space as homogeneous. A 
newly-hatched chick notices a small object and at once 
both looks and pecks at it. The stimulus excites a certain 
tract of the sense-organ and of the central organ, by means 
of which both the looking movement of the eye-muscles and 
the pecking movement of the muscles of the head and neck 
are released perfectly automatically. The excitement of one 
and the same nerve-tract, which, on the one hand, is deter- 
mined by the geometrical position of the physical stimulus, 
must, on the other hand, be regarded as the foundation of 
the sensation of space. A child that notices a glittering 
object, then looks at it and grasps at it, behaves in the 
same way as the chick. In addition to optical stimuli there 
are others acoustic stimuli, stimuli of heat and smell 
which can also release movements of grasping or of defence ; 
and these of course are operative with blind people also. 
Again, the same places of stimulus and the same sensations 
of space will correspond to the same movements. In 
general, the stimuli that excite a blind person are only con- 
fined to a narrower sphere and are less clearly and definitely 
localized. The system of his space-sensations will con- 
sequently be rather poorer and more blurred than that of 
a normal person, and, in the absence of a special education, 
will even remain so. Consider, for example, a blind man 
who tries to keep off a wasp that is buzzing round him. 
Accordingly as an object stimulates me to turn my gaze 
upon it, or stimulates me to seize it, the tracts of the central 
organ that come into play must be partially different, 
i88 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
although adjacent. If the two stimuli take place at once, 
the tract involved is of course larger. on biological 
grounds we should expect that the space-sensations con- 
nected with different senses, which, though not identical, 
are closely akin to one another, would be linked together 
by means of the movements which they induce, move- 
ments which are directed to the preservation of the 
organism, would merge into one another by way of 
association, and would mutually support one another ; and 
this is in fact the case. 
But this conclusion does not exhaust the phenomena 
with which we are concerned. A chick may look at an 
object or may peck at it ; it may also be determined by 
the stimulus to turn towards it and to run up to it. 
Exactly similar is the behaviour of a child that crawls 
towards some goal, and then one day stands up and runs a few 
steps towards the goal. All these cases pass gradually over 
into one another, and we have to think of them all as homo- 
geneous. Probably there are always certain parts of the brain 
which! when stimulated in a relatively simple manner, deter- 
mine space-sensations on the one hand, and on the other hand 
release automatic movements which are sometimes extremely 
complicated. Optical, thermal, acoustic, chemical and 
galvanic stimuli can excite a great deal of locomotion and 
change of orientation, and these effects can be produced even 
in animals that are blind, either originally or by degeneration. 
6. 
When we observe a millipede (fulus) crawling regularly 
on its way, we cannot resist the thought that a uniform 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 189 
current of stimulus proceeds from some one of the insect's 
organs, and that the motor organs of the successive 
segments of the body reply to this current with rhythmic 
automatic movements. The longitudinal wave, which 
seems to pass along the insect's rows of feet with machine- 
like regularity, arises from the difference in phase of the 
segments behind as compared with those in front. We 
should expect to find analogous processes in the more 
highly organized animals, and in fact such processes occur. 
I need only refer to the phenomena connected with stimula- 
tions of the labyrinth, for instance to the well-known 
nystagmic movements of the eyes, which are released under 
active and passive rotation. Now, if there are organs, as in 
the case of the millipede, by the simple stimulation of 
which, the complicated movements of a definite kind of 
locomotion are induced, then we may regard this simple stimu- 
lation, in the case where it is present to consciousness, as the 
will to the locomotion in question, or as the attention to 
the locomotion, which automatically draws the locomotion 
after it. At the same time, we recognize that it is a necessity 
for the organism to feel the effect of the locomotion in a 
correspondingly simple manner. And, in fact, objects of 
sight and touch do appear with varying and fluctuating 
space-values, instead of their values being stable. Even if 
we exclude all sensations of sight and touch as completely 
as possible, there still remain sensations of acceleration, 
which evoke, by way of association, the images of the 
various space-values with which they have often been con- 
nected. Between the first and last members of the process 
lie the sensations of movement in the extremities, whicrij 
however, are usually only fully present to consciousness 
igo THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
when some obstacle arises and makes a modification of the 
movement necessary. 
The man who is motionless as a whole is only aware of 
space-sensations which are limited, locally individualized, 
and orientated with reference to his own body; but the 
sensations which arise on occasion of locomotion and 
change of orientation possess the character of regularity 
and inexhaustibility. All these experiences are required 
as a basis for the construction of a conception of space 
approximately similar to Euclidean space. Apart from the 
fact that the first set of experiences only gives us agree- 
ments and differences, but no magnitudes and no metrical 
determinations, the latter set does not attain absolute 
uniformity on account of the obstacles in the way of 
permanent and free disorientation in respect of the 
vertical. 
For the animal organism, the relations between the parts 
of its own body are, first of all, of the highest importance. 
An alien object only acquires value by standing in relation 
to parts of the animal's own body. In the lowest organisms 
the sensations, including the space-sensations, are sufficient 
to secure adaptation to primitive conditions of life, But 
as these conditions become more complicated they force 
on the development of the intellect. Then the mutual 
relations of those functional complexes of elements 
(sensations) which we call bodies, acquire an indirect 
interest. Geometry arises from the spatial comparison 
of bodies with one another. 
Our understanding of the development of geometry may 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 191 
be assisted by the observation that our immediate interest 
is connected, not with spatial properties alone, but with 
the whole permanent complex of material properties which 
is important for the satisfaction of our needs. But the 
forms, positions, distances, and extensions of bodies are 
decisive for the mode and the quantity of the satisfaction 
of needs. Mere perception by itself (estimation, ocular 
measurement, and memory) proves to be too much under 
the influence of physiological circumstances that are not 
easily controlled, for us to build securely upon it, when 
the question is one of judging accurately the spatial 
relations of bodies to one another. We are therefore 
compelled to look to the bodies themselves for trust- 
worthy indications. 
Everyday experience brings home to us the permanence 
of bodies. Under ordinary circumstances this permanence 
extends also to particular qualities, such as color, shape, 
and size. We become acquainted with rigid bodies, which, 
in spite of their mobility in space, always produce the 
same space-sensations as soon as they are brought into a 
definite relation with our body and are seen and handled. 
Such bodies display spatial substantiality ; l they remain 
spatially constant and identical. one rigid body A may 
be immediately or mediately superimposed spatially on 
another rigid body B, or on parts of it, and this relation 
remains always and everywhere the same. We then say 
B is measured by A. When bodies are compared with 
1 It is certain that this view has been privately held by innumerable 
geometricians. It comes out clearly in the whole arrangement of 
Euclid's geometry, and is still clearer in Leibniz, particularly in his 
"geometrical characteristic." But Helmholtz was the first to discuss 
it openly. 
192 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 

one another in this way, the question is no longer one 
as to the kind of space-sensation involved; rather, we 
have a judgment as to their identity under similar circum- 
stances, and this judgment is formed with great accuracy 
and certainty. Variations in the results of measurement 
are, in fact, negligible in comparison with the element 
of error involved in immediate spatial judgments as to 
juxtaposed or successive bodies, and it is in this fact that 
the advantage and the rational justification of the process 
of measurement consist. Instead of the individual hands and 
feet, which everyone carries about with him without noticing 
any appreciable spatial change in them, a universally acces- 
sible standard of measure is soon chosen, which, by fulfilling 
in a high degree the condition of immutability, ushers in an 
era of greater precision. 
8. 
The object of all geometrical problems is to establish 
a numerical correspondence between spaces that it is 
required to ascertain and known homogeneous bodies. 
Empty vessels for the measurement of fluids, or of com- 
pact aggregates of almost exactly similar bodies, are 
probably the oldest measures. The volume of a body, 
the aggregate of the positions occupied by its matter, 
which we instinctively represent to ourselves when we 
look at or grasp some body with which we are familiar, 
comes to be considered as a quantum of material properties 
that satisfy our needs, and constitutes, as such, an object 
of dispute. Indeed, originally the measurement of a surface 
is undertaken solely with the object of ascertaining the 
amount of the homogeneous closely juxtaposed bodies 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 193 
covering the surface. Measurement of length, that is 
to say, enumeration by means of similar pieces of string 
or chain, determines the minimum volume that can be 
interpolated in one and only way between two points, 
or two very small bodies. If in this process we abstract 
from one or two dimensions of the bodies used as 
measures, or, again, if we suppose these bodies to be 
everywhere constant, but as small as we like to choose 
them, we arrive at the idealized representations of geometry. 
Our intuition of space is enriched by experimenting with 
material objects, owing to the fact that metrical experiences, 
which spatial intuition would not be able to acquire by 
itself, are connected with these objects. Thus we become 
acquainted with the metrical properties of forms with which 
we have long been familiar, such as the straight line, the 
plane, and the circle. Again it is experience, as history 
testifies, which has first led to the knowledge of certain 
geometrical propositions, by shewing that, if an object has 
certain dimensions, certain other dimensions of it were 
thereby determined. Scientific geometry set itself the 
economical task of ascertaining the dependence of dimen- 
sions on one another, of avoiding superfluous measurements, 
and of discovering the simplest geometrical facts from which 
the remaining facts would follow as logical consequences. 
For this purpose, since we have no mental control over nature, 
but only over our own simple logical constructions, our 
ultimate geometrical experiences had to be conceptually 
idealized. Henceforth there was no obstacle in the way of 
i 9 4 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
the discovery of geometrical propositions by a kind of 
"thought-experiment," by advancing along the road of 
mental visualization, and thinking of these representations as 
connected with the idealized geometrical experiences. The 
procedure throughout is analogous to that of all the natural 
sciences. But the ultimate experiences of geometry are 
reduced to so small a minimum that is only too easy to 
overlook them altogether. We imagine bodies as moving 
over the shadows or ghosts of bodies, and we cling mentally 
to the notion that their measurements, if they were taken, 
would not be altered in the process. Physical bodies 
harmonize with the results in so far as they are sufficient for 
the presuppositions. 
Intuition, physical experiences, and conceptual idealiza- 
tion, are, therefore, the three co-operating factors in 
scientific geometry. The wide divergence in the views of 
different investigators as to the nature of geometry is due 
to over or under estimation of one or the other factor. 
The only possible foundation for a correct view is the 
precise separation of the part played by each of these factors 
in the building up of geometry. For instance, our 
anatomically symmetrical motor organization, which has 
been acquired for purposes of rapid locomotion, causes our 
intuition to make the two halves of a spatially symmetrical 
construction appear to us as equivalent ; but this is by no 
means true from a physico-geometrical point of view, since 
they cannot be brought into congruence. Physically they 
are no more equivalent than a movement is to an opposite 
movement, or a rotation to a rotation in the opposite 
direction. Kant's paradoxes on this subject depend on an 
inadequate separation of the various factors involved. 
X. THE RELATIONS OF THE 
SIGHT-SENSATIONS TO onE 
ANOTHER AND TO OTHER 
PSYCHICAL ELEMENTS. 
i. 
IN normal psychical life, sight-sensations do not make 
their appearance alone, but are accompanied by other 
sensations. We do not see optical images in an optical 
space, but we perceive the bodies round about us with their 
many and varied sensible qualities. Deliberate analysis is 
needed to single out the sight-sensations from these com- 
plexes. But even the total perceptions themselves are 
almost invariably accompanied by thoughts, wishes, and 
impulses. By sensations are excited, in animals, the move- 
ments of adaptation demanded by their conditions of life. 
If these conditions are simple, altering but little and slowly, 
immediate sensory excitation is sufficient. Higher intel- 
lectual development is unnecessary. But the case is 
different where the conditions of life are intricate and 
variable. Here so simple a mechanism of adaptation cannot 
develop, still less would it lead to the accomplishment of 
the required ends. 
Lower species devour everything that comes in their 
way and that excites the proper stimulus. A more highly 
developed animal must seek its food at risks to itself; 
when found, must seize it at the right spot, or capture it by 
195 
196 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
cunning, and cautiously test its character. Long trains of 
varied memories must pass before its mind before one is 
sufficiently strong to outweigh the antagonistic considera- 
tions and to excite the appropriate movement. Here, 
therefore, a sum of associated remembrances (or experi- 
ences) coincidently determining the adaptive movements, 
must accompany and confront the sensations. In this 
consists the intellect. 
In the young of higher animals under complex conditions 
of life, the complexes of sensations necessary to excite 
adaptive movements are frequently of a very complicated 
nature. The sucking of young mammals, and the be- 
haviour of the young sparrow described on pp. 74, 75 are 
good examples of this. With the development of intelli- 
gence, the parts of these complexes necessary to produce 
the excitation constantly diminish, and the sensations are 
more and more supplemented and replaced by the intellect, 
as may be daily observed in children and adolescent animals. 
In a note to the edition of 1886 I uttered a warning 
against the tendency, which was still widespread at that 
time, to over-estimate the intelligence of the lower animals. 
My view was based solely on occasional observations on the 
machine-like movement of beetles, the flight of moths 
towards the light, etc. Subsequently the important works 
of J. Loeb appeared, and provided a solid experimental 
basis for this view. 
At the present moment (1906) the psychology of the 
lower animals has again become the field of much contro- 
versy. While A. Bethe l advocates an extreme reflex-theory, 
1 A. Bethe. " Diirfen wir den Ameisen und Bienen psychische 
Qualitaten zuschreiben ? " Pfliiger's Archiv, Vol. LXX., p. 17; " Noch 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 197 
based on ingenious and interesting experiments on ants and 
bees, according to which these insects are to be regarded 
as Cartesian machines, other careful critical observers, 
such as E. Wasmann, 1 H. von Buttel-Reepen, 2 and A. 
Forel 3 ascribe to the same insects a high degree of psychic 
development. The psychology of the higher animals also 
has lately become the object of general interest. The 
writings of Theodor Zell, which are intended principally 
for the general public, are full of excellent observation and 
felicitous insight, and seem to hit with great caution the 
proper mean between over-estimating and under estima- 
ting the animals of which they treat. 
Anyone who has studied physiology, or even anyone who 
can appreciate the work of F. Goltz, knows the very 
important part played by reflexes in preserving the life of 
all animal organisms, even of the human organism, which 
is the most highly developed of all. To anyone, again, 
who has observed the striking way in which the influence 
exercised upon the biological reactions by a memory that 
einmal fiber die psychischen Qualitaten der Ameisen," Ibid,, Vol. 
LXXIX., p. 39 ; Beer, Be the and Uexkiill, " Vorschlage zu einer objek- 
tivierenden Nomenklatur in der Physiologic des Nervensystems," 
Centralblatt far Physiologic, 1899, Vol. XIII., No. 6; H. E. Hering, 
" Inwiefern ist es moglich die Physiologic von der Psychologic sprach- 
lich zu trennen?" Detitsche Arbeit, ist year, No. 12. 
1 E. Wasmann, Die psychischen Fiihigkeiten der Ameisen, Stuttgart 
1899 (Zoologica, No. 26) ; Vergleichende Studien Uber das Seelenleben 
der Ameisen ttnd der hb'heren Tiere, 2nd edition, Freiburg im 
Breisgau, 1900. 
2 H. v. Buttel-Reepen, Sind die Bienen Reflexmaschinen?, Leipzig-, 
1900. 
3 A. Forel, " Psychische Fahigkeiten der Ameisen," Transactions of 
the Fifth International Zoological Congress, Jena, 1902 ; " Experiences 
et remarques critiques sur les sensations des insectes," Rivista di 
Scienze Biologiche, Como, 19001. 
198 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
registers the experiences of the individual, decreases with 
the simplification of the organism, it will naturally occur 
to try whether and to what extent the behaviour of simpler 
organisms can be explained solely by reference to reflexes. 1 
It is not, indeed, probable that there exist any animal 
organisms entirely devoid of memory and endowed with 
reflexes absolutely incapable of modification, since it is 
scarcely possible to draw a sharp line between the acquisi- 
tions of the species and the acquisitions of the individual. 2 
Still, I should consider such an attempt as well worth 
making, although a critical analysis of the result would be 
still more valuable. 
I hope that we shall still learn a great deal for our own 
psychology, not only from our children, but also from " our 
younger brothers 1 ' the animals. But in order to under- 
stand why man is psychically so much more than the 
cleverest animal, it will be sufficient to reflect on the 
acquisitions which the individual and the species have 
made in the atmosphere of a social culture extending over 
many thousand years. 
Representation by images and ideas, therefore, has to 
supply the place of sensations, where the latter are im- 
perfect, and to carry to their issue the processes initially 
determined by sensations alone. But in normal life, 
representation cannot permanently supplant sensation, 
1 Mach, Populdr-wissenchaftliche Vorlesungen, " Ueber den Einfluss 
zufalliger Umstande," etc. , Leipzig, 1903, 3rd edition, pp. 294-295; 
Prinzipien der Wdrmelehre, Leipzig, 1900. See the chapter on 
" Sprache und Begriffe." 
2 Cf. the fourth edition of this work, p. 153. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 199 
where this is at all present, except with the greatest danger 
to the organism. As a fact, there is, in normal psychical 
life, a marked difference between the two species of 
psychical elements. I see a blackboard before me. I 
can, with the greatest vividness, represent to myself on 
this blackboard, either a hexagon drawn in clear, white 
lines, or a colored figure. But, pathological cases apart, 
I always distinguish what I see and what I represent to 
myself. In the transition to mental imagery, I am aware 
that my attention is turned from my eyes, and directed 
elsewhere. In consequence of this attention, the spot seen 
upon the blackboard and the one represented to myself as 
situated in the same place differ as by a fourth co-ordinate. 
It would not be a complete description of the facts to say 
that the image is superimposed on the object as the images 
reflected in a transparent plate of glass are superimposed 
on the bodies seen through it. on the contrary, what is 
represented seems to me to be supplemented by a qualita- 
tively different and opposite sensational stimulus, which 
stimulus it in its turn sometimes supplants. We are con- 
fronted here, for the time being, with a psychological fact, 
the physiological explanation of which will sometime 
undoubtedly be discovered. 
It is natural to suppose that, when mental images occur, 
the interaction of the organs of the nervous system causes 
the repetition of organic processes partially identical with 
those which were determined by the physical stimulus 
on occasion of the corresponding sensations. Images 
are normally distinguished from sensations by being less 
intense, and above all by their instability. When I draw 
a geometrical figure in imagination, it is as if the lines faded 
200 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
immediately after they are drawn, as soon as my attention 
is directed to ether lines : when one comes back to them 
they have vanished, and must be reproduced over again. 
This is the principal reason of the advantage in point of 
convenience which an actual material geometrical drawing 
possesses over a merely imagined one. It is easy enough 
to hold firmly before the mind a small number of lines, for 
instance an arc of a circle with the angles at the centre and 
circumference and a pair of coincident or intersecting sides ; 
but if in this case we proceed to add the diameter drawn 
through the apex of the angle at the circumference, it at 
once becomes more difficult to deduce in imagination the 
relative sizes of the angles, without continually renewing and 
completing the figure. The power of replacing the figure 
with ease and rapidity, is, however, enormously increased by 
practice. When I was studying the geometry of Steiner 
and Von Staudt, I was able to do this to a much greater 
extent than I can now. 
Where the development of intelligence has reached a high 
point, such as is presented now in the complex conditions 
of human life, mental images may frequently absorb the 
whole of attention, so that events in the neighbor- 
hood of the reflecting person are not noticed, and 
questions addressed to him are not heard ; a state 
which persons unused to it are wont to call absent- 
mindedness, although it might with more appropriate- 
ness be called present-mindedness. If the person in 
question is disturbed in such a state, he has a very 
distinct sensation of the labor involved in the transference 
of his attention. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 201 
It is well to note this sharp division between images 
and sensations, as it is an excellent safeguard against 
carelessness in psychological explanations of sense-pheno- 
mena. The well-known theory of " unconscious inferences " 
would never have reached its present extended development 
if more heed had been paid to this circumstance. 
The organ, of which the states determine images, can 
provisionally be conceived as one which, in a diminished 
degree, is capable of all the specific energies of the sense 
and motor organs, so that the specific energy now of one, 
now of another, sense-organ can play upon it, according to 
the nature and direction of its attention for the time being. 
Such an organ is eminently qualified to effect physiological 
relations between the different energies. As is shewn by 
experiments with animals whose cerebrum has been re- 
moved, there are probably, in addition to the organ of 
representation, a number of other analogous organs of 
mediation, which are less intimately connected with the 
cerebrum, and whose processes consequently do not appear 
in consciousness. 
That wealth of representative life with which we are 
personally acquainted from self-observation, doubtless made 
its first appearance with man. But the beginnings of this 
expression of life, in which nothing but the relations of the 
various parts of the organism to one another is manifested, 
go back with no less certainty to quite primitive stages in 
the animal scale. But the parts of single organs must also, 
in virtue of their reciprocal tension, stand to one another 
in a relation analogous to that in which the parts of the 
202 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
organism as a whole stand to one another. The two 
retinae, with their motor mechanism of accommodation 
and of luminous adjustment, dependent on light-sensations, 
afford a very clear and familiar example of such a relation. 
Physiological experiment and simple self-observation teach 
us that such an organ has its own purposive habits, its own 
peculiar memory, one might almost say its own intelligence. 
The most instructive observations in this connexion are 
probably those of Johannes Miiller, collected in his admir- 
able work on " The Phantasms of Sight " ( Ueber diephantas- 
tischen Gesichtserscheinungen, Coblenz, 1826). The sight- 
phantasms observed by Miiller and others in the waking 
state are entirely withdrawn from the influence of either 
the will or the reason. They are independent phenomena, 
essentially connected with the sense-organs, and charac- 
terized by complete visual objectivity. They are veritable 
imagination- and memory-phenomena of sense. Miiller 
considers that the free individual existence of hallucinations 
is a part of the life of the organism, and that it cannot be 
brought under the so-called laws of association, in which 
he indicates that he does not believe. It seems to me that 
the continuous alteration of the phantasms, as described by 
him, is no evidence against the laws of association. These 
processes can, on the contrary, be conceived as recollec- 
tions of slow perspectival changes in visual images. The 
element of desultoriness in the common connexion of 
a train of representations by way of association, only 
comes in when sometimes one, and sometimes another, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 203 
department of sensation begins to be involved (see 
Chapter XL) 
Those processes which (according to Miiller) are normally 
induced in the "visual substance" by excitations of the 
retina, and which condition the act of seeing, may also, 
under exceptional conditions, be spontaneously produced 
in the visual substance without excitation of the retina, and 
thus become the source of phantasms or hallucinations. 
We speak of sense-memory when the phantasms are closely 
allied in character to objects seen before, of hallucinations 
when the phantasms arise more freely and independently. 
But no sharp distinction between the two cases can be 
maintained. 
I am acquainted with all manner of sight-phantasms from 
my own experience. The mingling of phantasms with 
objects indistinctly seen, the latter being partly supplanted, 
is probably the most common case. In my own case, these 
phenomena are particularly vivid after a tiring night's 
journey in the train. Rocks and trees then assume the 
most fantastic shapes. Years ago, while engrossed with the 
study of pulse-tracings and sphygmography, the fine white 
curves on the dark background often came up before my 
eyes, in the evening or in the dim light of day, with the full 
semblance of reality and objectivity. Later also, during 
miscellaneous work in physics, I witnessed analogous 
phenomena of "sense-memory." More rarely, images of 
things which I have never seen before, have appeared before 
my eyes in the daytime. Thus, years ago, on a number 
of successive days, a bright red capillary net (similar to 
a so-called enchanted net) shone out upon the book in 
which I was reading, or on my writing paper, although 
204 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
I had never been occupied with forms of this sort. The 
sight of bright-colored changing carpet patterns before falling 
asleep was very familiar to me in my youth ; the pheno- 
menon will still make its appearance if I fix my atten- 
tion on it. one of my children, likewise, often used 
to tell me that he " saw flowers " before falling asleep. 
Less often, I see in the evening, before falling asleep, 
various human figures, which alter without the action 
of my will. on a single occasion I attempted suc- 
cessfully to change a human face into a fleshless skull; 
this solitary instance may, however, be an accident. 
It has often happened to me that, on awaking in a 
dark room, the images of my latest dreams remained 
present in vivid colors and in abundant light. A 
peculiar phenomenon, which has for some years frequently 
occurred with me, is the following. I awake and lie 
motionless with my eyes closed. Before me I see the bed- 
spread with all its little folds, and upon it, motionless and 
unchanging, my hands in all their details. If I open my 
eyes, either it is quite dark, or it is light, but the bed-spread 
and my hands lie quite differently from the manner in 
which they appeared to me. This is a remarkably fixed and 
persistent phantasm with me, such as I have not observed 
under other conditions. As regards this image, I think that I 
notice that all its parts, even those that are widely separated, 
appear with equal distinctness in a way which for obvious 
reasons is impossible in the case of anything objectively seen. 
When I was young I used frequently to have very vivid 
acoustic, and particularly musical, hallucinations on waking 
up ; they have, however, become extremely rare and faint 
since my interest in music has decreased. But perhaps 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 205 
the interest in music is itself a secondary effect, rather 
than a cause. 
When we withdraw the retina from the influence of 
outward excitations, and turn the attention to the field of 
vision alone, traces of phantasms are almost always present. 
Indeed, they make their appearance when the outer 
excitations are merely weak and indistinct, in a half-light, 
or when we look at a surface covered with dim, blurred 
spots, such as a cloud, or a grey wall. The figures which 
we then seem to see, provided they are not produced by a 
direct act of attention in selecting and combining distinctly 
seen spots, are certainly not products of representation, 
but constitute, at least in part, spontaneous phantasms, 
which, for the time being and at some points, take forcible 
precedence over the retinal excitation. In these cases 
expectation seems to be favorable to the occurrence of 
the phantasms. When I have been looking for interfer- 
ence-bands I have very often thought that I could clearly 
detect the first dull traces of them in the field of vision, 
when the progress of the experiment has convinced me 
that I was certainly deluded. Over and over again, in a 
half-light, I have thought that I could distinctly see a jet 
of water that I was expecting to come out of an india- 
rubber tube, and have had to touch with my finger to 
convince myself of my mistake. Such weak phantasms 
seem as a rule to yield readily to the influence of the 
intellect, whereas the intellect is unable to produce any 
effect on strong phantasms with vivid colors. The former 
are more akin to representations, the latter to sensations. 
These weak phantasms, which are sometimes over- 
powered by sensations, are sometimes in equilibrium 
206 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
with them, and sometimes replace them, suggest the 
possibility of comparing the strength of phantasms with 
the strength of sensations. Scripture has carried out this 
idea. He takes an observer who thinks that he sees a 
colored cross, which is really non-existent, and then causes 
to appear in his field of vision a real line of intensity 
increasing from zero upwards and drawn in a direction 
which is not known beforehand, until the line is noticed 
and given the same value as the phantasm. 1 In this way 
all the transitional stages between sensation and representa- 
tion can be obtained. At no point do we come upon a 
psychical element that is absolutely incapable of being 
compared with the sensation, which we must undoubtedly 
regard as a physical object also. The way in which the 
presentations are connected by association is, however, 
quite different from the way in which the sensations are 
connected. 
Leonardo da Vinci discusses the mingling of phantasms 
with objects seen (see p. 66 above) in the following words : 
" I shall not omit to give a place among these directions 
to a newly-discovered sort of observation, which may, 
indeed, make a small and almost ludicrous appearance, but 
which is, nevertheless, very useful in awakening the mind 
to various discoveries. It consists in this, that thou 
shouldst regard various walls which are covered with all 
manner of spots, or stone of different composition. If 
thou hast any capacity for discovery, thou mayest behold 
there things which resemble various landscapes decked 
1 Scripture, The New Psychology, London, 1897, p. 484. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 207 
with mountains, rivers, cliffs, trees, large plains, hills and 
valleys of many a sort. Thou canst also behold all 
manner of battles, life-like positions of strange, unfamiliar 
figures, expressions of face, costumes, - and numberless 
things which thou mayest put into good and perfect form. 
The experience with regard to walls and stone of this sort 
is similar to that of the ringing of bells, in the strokes of 
which thou willst find anew every name and every word 
that thou mayest imagine to thyself. 
" Do not despise this opinion of mine when I counsel 
thee sometimes not to let it appear burdensome to thee to 
pause and look at the spots on walls, or the ashes in the 
fire, or the clouds, or mud, or other such places; thou 
wilt make very wonderful discoveries in them, if thou 
observest them rightly. For the mind of the painter is 
stimulated by them to many new discoveries, be it in the 
composition of battles, of animals and human beings, or 
in various compositions of landscapes, and of monstrous 
things, as devils and the like, which are calculated to bring 
thee honor. For through confused and undefined things 
the mind is awakened to new discoveries. But take heed, 
first, that thou understandest how to shape well all the 
members of the things that thou wishest to represent, for 
instance, the limbs of living beings, as also the parts of a 
landscape, namely the stones, trees, and the like." 
All marked and independent appearance of phantasms 
without excitation of the retina dreams and the half- 
waking state excepted must, by reason of their biological 
purposelessness, be accounted pathological. In like 
manner, we are constrained to regard every abnormal 
dependence of phantasms upon the will as pathological. 
208 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Such, very likely, are the states that occur in insane 
persons who regard themselves as very powerful, as God, 
etc. But the delusions of the megalo-maniac can equally 
be produced by the mere absence of inhibitory associations ; 
for instance, one can believe in a dream that one has solved 
the most tremendous problems, because the associations 
that reveal the contradiction do not take place. 
6. 
After these introductory remarks we may now turn to the 
consideration of a few physiologico-optical phenomena, the 
full explanation of which, it is true, is still distant, but which 
are best understood as the expressions of an independent 
life on the part of the sense-organs. 
We usually see with both eyes, and agreeably to definite 
needs of life, not colors and forms, but bodies in space. It 
is not the elements of the complex, but the whole physio- 
logico-optical complex that is of importance. This complex 
the eye seeks to fill out and supplement, according to the 
habits acquired (or inherited) in its environment, whenever, 
as a result of special circumstances, the appearance of the 
complex is incomplete. This occurs oftenest in monocular 
vision, but is also possible in the binocular observation of 
very distant objects where the stereoscopic differences con- 
sequent upon the distance of the eyes from each other vanish. 
We generally perceive, not light and shadow, but objects 
in space. The shading of bodies is scarcely noticed. 
Differences in brightness produce differences in the sensa- 
tion of depth, and help to produce the modelling of bodies 
when the stereoscopic differences are insufficient for this 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 209 
purpose, a condition which is very noticeable in the 
observation of distant mountains. 
Very instructive, from this point of view, is the image on 
the dull plate of the photographic camera. We are often 
astounded at the brightness of the lights and the depth of the 
shadows, which were not noticed in the bodies themselves as 
long as one was not compelled to see everything in a single 
plane. I remember quite well that, in my childhood, all 
shading of a drawing appeared to me an unjustifiable 
disfigurement, and that an outline-drawing was much more 
satisfactory to me. It is likewise well known that whole 
peoples, for instance the Chinese, despite a well-developed 
artistic technique, do not shade at all, or shade only in a 
defective manner. 
The following experiment, which I made many years 
ago, 1 illustrates very clearly the relation in question between 
the sensation of light and the sensation of depth. 
We place a visiting-card, bent crosswise before 
us on the desk, so that its bent edge b e is to- 
wards us. Let the light fall from the left. The 
half abdev$> then much lighter, the \\d\ibcef l 
much darker a fact which is, however, scarcely 
perceived in unprejudiced observation. We now 
close one eye. Hereupon, part of the space-sensations dis- 
appear. Still we see the bent card spatially and nothing 
noticeable in the illumination. But as soon as we succeed 
in seeing the bent edge depressed instead of raised, the light 
and the shade stand out as if painted thereon. I pass over 
for the moment the perspectival reversal of the card, which 
1 " Ueber die physikalische Wirkung raumlich verteilter Lichtreize," 
Sitzungsbcrichte der Wiener Akademie^ Vol. LIV., October 1866. 
210 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
can easily be explained. Such an " inversion " is possible, 
because depth is not determined by a monocular image. If 
in Fig. 25, i O represents the eye, a b c a section of a bent 
card, and the arrow the direction of the light, ab will 
appear lighter than be. Also in 2, a b will appear lighter 
than b c. Plainly, the eye must acquire the habit of varying 
the fall in the sensation of depth concomitantly with the 
change in brightness of the surface-elements that it sees. 
The fall and the depth diminish, with diminishing illumina- 
tion, towards the right, when 
the light falls from the left (i) ; 
contrariwise, when it falls from 
the right. Since the wrappings 
of the bulb in which the retina 
is embedded are translucent, it 
is not a matter of indifference 
for the distribution of light 
upon the retinae whether the 
light falls from the right or the 
left. Accordingly, things are so 
arranged that, without any aid of the judgment, a fixed 
habit of the eye is developed, by means of which illumina- 
tion and depth are connected in a definite way. If now, by 
virtue of another habit, it is possible to bring a part of the 
retina into conflict with the first habit, as in the above experi- 
ment, the effect is made manifest in remarkable sensations. 
Certain experiments of Fechner's have shewn how im- 
portant the effect of the light that penetrates through the 
wrappings of the bulb can become. 1 one observation in 
1 Feclmer, " Ueber den seitlichen Fenster- und Kerzenversuch," 
Berichte der Leipziger Gesellschaft der Wissensckaf/en, 1860. 
Fig. 25. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 211 
this connexion is as follows. Beneath my writing-table 
is a grey-green rug, a small piece of which I can see as 
I write. Now, when a double image of this bit arises, 
accidentally or intentionally, when the sunlight or daylight 
comes from the left, the image belonging to the left, or 
more strongly illuminated eye, is a vivid green by contrast, 
while the image on the right side is quite dull in color. 
It would be interesting to study the variation of intensity 
and color of the illumination of the bulb in the case of 
these images and in experiments in inversion. 
The purpose of the preceding remarks is merely to 
point out the character of the phenomenon under con- 
sideration and to indicate the direction in which a physio- 
logical explanation (exclusive of psychological speculation) 
is to be sought. We will further remark that, with respect 
to interchangeable qualities of sensation, a principle similar 
to that of the conservation of energy seems to hold. 
Differences of brightness are partly transformed into differ- 
ences of depth, and themselves become weaker in the 
process. At the expense of differences of depth, on 
the other hand, differences of brightness may be 
augmented. An analogous observation will be made 
later on in another connexion. 
The habit of observing bodies as such, that is, of giving 
attention to a large and spatially cohering mass of light- 
sensations, is the cause of peculiar and often surprising 
phenomena. A two-colored painting or drawing, for 
instance, appears in general quite different according as we 
212 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
take the one or the other color as the background. The 
puzzle pictures, in which, for example, an apparition makes 
its appearance between tree- 
trunks as soon as the dark 
trees are taken as the back- 
ground, and the bright sky as 
the object, are well known. 
In exceptional instances only 
do background and object 
possess the same form a 
configuration frequently em- 
ployed in ornamental designs, 
as may be seen in Fig. 
26, taken from p. 15 of the 
above - mentioned Grammar 
of Ornament^ also in Figs. 20 
and 22 of Plate 45, and in 
Fig. 13 of Plate 43 of that work. 
Pig. 26. 
The phenomena of space-vision which accompany the 
monocular observation of a perspective drawing, or, what 
amounts to the same thing, the monocular observation of 
an object, are generally very lightly passed over, as being 
self-evident in nature. But I am of the opinion that there 
is yet much to be investigated in these phenomena. one 
and the same image in perspective may represent an 
unlimited number of different objects, and consequently 
the space-sensation can be only in part determined by such 
a drawing. If, therefore, despite the many bodies conceiv- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 213 
able as belonging to the figure, only a few are really seen 
with the full character of objectivity, there must exist some 
good physiological reason for the fact. It cannot arise from 
the adducing of auxiliary considerations in thought, nor from 
the awakening of conscious remembrances in any form, but 
must depend on certain organic life habits of the visual sense. 
If the visual sense acts in conformity with the habits 
which it has acquired under the conditions of life of the 
species and the individual, we may, in the first place, 
assume that it proceeds according to the principle of prob- 
ability ; that is, those functions which have been most 
frequently excited together before, will afterwards tend to 
make their appearance together when only one is excited. 
For example, those particular sensations of depth which in 
the past have been most frequently associated with a given 
perspective figure, will be readily reproduced again when 
that figure makes its appearance, although not necessarily 
co-determined thereby. Furthermore, a principle of 
economy appears to manifest itself in the observation of 
perspective drawings ; that is to say, the visual sense never 
of itself burdens itself with any greater effort than is 
demanded by the stimulus. The two principles coincide 
in their effects, as we shall presently see. 
The following may serve as a detailed illustration of the 
above. When we look at a straight line in a perspective 
drawing, we always see it as a straight line in space, 
although the straight line, qua perspective drawing, may 
correspond to an unlimited number of different plane 
214 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
curves, qua objects. But only in the special case where 
the plane of a curve passes through the centre of one 
eye, will it be reproduced on the retina in question as a 
straight line (or as a great circle), and only in the yet more 
special case where the plane of the curve passes through 
the centres of both eyes, will it be reproduced as a straight 
line for both eyes. It is thus extremely improbable that a 
plane curve should ever appear a straight line, while on the 
other hand a straight line in space is always reproduced on 
both retinae as a straight line. The most probable object, 
therefore, answering to a straight line in perspective, is a 
straight line in space. 
The straight line has various geometrical properties. 
But these geometrical properties, for example the familiar 
characteristic of being the shortest distance between two 
points, are not physiologically of importance. It is of 
far more consequence that straight lines lying in the 
median plane or perpendicular thereto are physiologically 
symmetrical to themselves. A vertical lying in the median 
plane is also physiologically distinguished by its perfect 
uniformity of depth-sensation, and by its coincidence with 
the direction of gravity. All vertical straight lines may be 
readily and quickly made to coincide with the median plane, 
and consequently partake of this physiological advantage. 
But the spatial straight line generally, must be physiologi- 
cally distinguished by some further mark. Its sameness of 
direction in all its elements has already been pointed out. 
In addition to this, however, it is to be noted that every 
point of a straight line in space marks the mean of the 
depth-sensations of the neighboring points. Thus the 
straight line in space gives a minimum of departure from 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 215 
the mean of the depth-sensations, just as every point on 
the straight line gives the mean of the similar space-values 
of the adjacent points; and the assumption forthwith 
presents itself that the straight line is seen with the least 
effort. The visual sense acts therefore in conformity with 
the principle of economy, and, at the same time, in con- 
formity with the principle of probability, when it exhibits 
a preference for straight lines. 
As early as 1866, I wrote, in the Proceedings of the 
Vienna Academy ', Vol. 54 : " Since straight lines every- 
where surround civilized human beings, we may, I think, 
assume, that every straight line which can possibly be 
produced upon the retina has been seen numberless times, 
in every possible way, spatially as a straight line. The 
efficiency of the eye in the interpretation of straight lines 
ought not, therefore, to astonish us." Even then I wrote 
this passage (opposing the Darwinian view,- which I sup- 
ported in the same paper) half-heartedly. To-day I am 
more than ever convinced that the efficiency referred to 
is not the result of individual practice, nor indeed of 
human practice at all, but that it is also characteristic of 
animals, and is, at least in part, a matter of inheritance. 
10. 
The deviation of a sensation from the mean of the 
adjacent sensations is always noticeable, and exacts a 
special effort on the part of the sense-organ. Every new 
turn of a curve, every projection or depression of a surface, 
involves a deviation of some space-sensation from the 
mean of the surrounding field on which the attention is 
2i6 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
directed. The plane is distinguished physiologically by 
the fact that this deviation from the mean is a minimum, 
or for each point in particular = o. In looking through a 
stereoscope at a spotted surface, the separate images of 
which have not yet been combined into a binocular image, 
we experience a peculiarly agreeable impression when the 
whole is suddenly flattened out into a plane. The aesthetic 
impressions produced by the circle and the sphere seem 
to have their source mainly in the fact that the above- 
mentioned deviation from the mean is the same for all 
points. 
1 1. 
That the deviation from the mean of the environment 
plays a r61e in light-sensation I pointed out many years 
ago. 1 If a row of black and white sectors, such as are 
shown in Fig. 27, be painted on a strip of paper AABB^ 
and this be then wrapped about a cylinder the axis of 
which is parallel to AB, there will be produced, on the 
rapid rotation of the cylinder, a grey field with increasing 
illumination from B to A, in which, however, a brighter 
line a a, and a darker line /3 /3, make their appearance. 
The points which correspond to the indentations a are 
not physically brighter than the neighboring parts, but 
their light-intensity exceeds the mean intensity of the 
immediately adjacent parts, while, on the other hand, the 
1 " Ueber die Wirkung der raumlichen Vertheilung des Lichtreizes auf 
die Netzhaut," Sitzungsberichle der Wiener Akademie (1865), Vol. 
LII. Continuation of the same inquiry: Sitzber. (1866), Vol. LIV. ; 
Sitzber. (1868), Vol. LVII. ; Vierteljahrsschrift fur Psychiatrie, 
Neuwied- Leipzig, 1868 (" Ueber die Abhangigkeit der Netzhautstellen 
von einander "). 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 217 
light-intensity at /3 falls short of the mean intensity of the 
adjacent parts. 1 This deviation from the mean is thus 
distinctly felt, and accordingly imposes a special burden 
upon the organ of sight. on the other hand a continuous 
change in brightness is scarcely noticed, as long as the 
brightness of each particular point corresponds to the mean 
of the adjacent points. Long ago I drew attention to the 
important teleological bearing of this fact on the saliency 
and the delimitation of objects (Sitzungsberichte der Wiener 
Akademie October 1865, and January 1868). Small 
differences are slurred over by the retina, and larger 
A A 
Fig. 27. 
differences stand out with disproportionate clearness. 
The retina schematizes and caricatures. At an even 
earlier period the important part which outlines play in 
vision had been noticed by Panum. 
A series of very various experiments, of which that repre- 
sented in Fig. 27 is one of the simplest, led me to the 
conclusion that the illumination of a position on the retina 
is felt in proportion to its deviation from the mean of the 
1 A remark concerning the analogies between light-sensation and 
the potential function will be found in my note " Ueber Herrn 
Gu6bhards Darstellung der Aequipotentialkurven," Wiedemann's 
Annalen, 1882, Vol. XVII., p. 864; and see my Prinzipien der 
Warmelehre, 2nd edition, 1900, p. 118. 
218 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
illuminations of the adjacent positions. The value of the 
retinal positions in determining this mean is to be conceived 
as rapidly decreasing with their distance from the position 
under consideration, a fact which of course can only be 
explained as depending on an organic reciprocal action of 
the retinal elements on one another. Let i=f (x, y) be 
the intensity of illumination of the retina with reference to 
a system of co-ordinates (XY); then the mean value deter- 
mining the intensity for a given position may be symbolically 
represented as approximately 
where m is constant, and the radii of all curves of the 
surface / (x, y) are taken as large in proportion to the 
distance at which the retinal positions are still perceptibly 
influenced. Now according as f_I+_lji s positive or 
negative, the position on the retina experiences a darker or 
a brighter sensation respectively than it does under equal 
illumination of the adjacent positions with the intensity 
corresponding to itself. If the surface / (x, y) has edges 
and indentations, ( a4-~T ] becomes infinite, and the 
\ 4& <y 2 / 
formula is useless. In this case, however, a marked increase 
of darkness or brightness corresponds to the indentation, 
though of course not an infinite increase or decrease. The 
increase or decrease, again, are not denned by a hard and 
fast line, but fade gradually away, as we should expect from 
the principle of deviation from the mean. For the retina 
consists, not of sensitive points, but of an infinite number 
of sensitive elements of finite extension. As regards the 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 219 
law of the reciprocal action of these elements, we still do 
not know it accurately enough to enable us to determine 
precisely the phenomena of this special case. 
It is easy to go wrong in judging of the objective distri- 
bution of light according to the subjective impression, and 
consequently a knowledge of the above-mentioned law of 
contrast is important even for purely physical researches. 
Thus Grimaldi was deceived by a phenomenon of this kind. 
We come across the same phenomenon in the investigation 
of shadows, and of spectral absorption, and in countless 
other cases. Peculiar circumstances prevented my papers on 
this subject from becoming generally known, and the relevant 
facts were discovered for the second time thirty years later. 1 
It may seem surprising that, in addition to /, the second 
differential quotients of *, but not the first, , , seem 
dx oy 
to influence the sensation of brightness. We scarcely notice 
a regular and continuous rise in the intensity of illumination 
of a surface, for instance, in the direction x t and special 
devices are necessary to convince one that there is a rise. 
on the other hand, these first differential quotients exercise 
an influence on the modelling, on the plastic quality, 
1 H. Seeliger, " Die scheinbare Vergrosserung des Erdschattens bei 
Mondfinsternissen," Abhandlungen der Munchener Akademie^ 1896 ; 
H. Haga and C. H. Wind, " Beugung der Rontgenstrahlen," Wiede- 
mann's Annalen, Vol. LXVIII., 1899, p. 866; C. H. Wind, "Zur 
Demonstration einer von E. Mach entdeckten optischen Tauschung," 
Riecke and Simon's Physikalische Zeitschrift^ I., No. 10. A. von 
Obermayer (" Ueber die Saumeum die Bilder dunkler Gegenstande auf 
hellem Hintergrunde," Eder's Jahrbiich der Photographic ; 1900) pub- 
lished a number of new facts which can be explained on the law of 
contrast laid down in the text. But, of my four papers, he is only 
acquainted with the first, and consequently states the law in its earlier 
defective form. 
220 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
of the surface seen. Call the horizontal direction x, and 
the distance as regards depth of a point on the illuminated 
surface r ; then and ^ are parallel. This expression, 
which of course is only to be understood symbolically, 
means that we have the representation of a cylindrical 
surface with vertical generatrix and plane horizontal 
directrix r = F (jc), of which the second differential 
<y 2 r 
quotients ^ (curvatures) are parallel to the first differential 
oOC 
quotients, the rises in intensity of illumination. The 
tracing of the curve is determined by the accessory circum- 
stances indicated on p. 210. 
12. 
With regard to the depth-sensations excited by a 
monocular image, the following experiments are instructive. 
Fig. 28 is a plane quadrilateral with its two diagonals. If 
we regard it monocularly, it is most easily 
seen, according to the laws of probability 
and economy, as a plane. In the great 
majority of cases, objects which are not 
plane, force the eye to the vision of depth. 
^ . - Where this compulsion is lacking, the plane 
^^^ object is the most probable and at the same 
Fg. 28. time the most convenient for the organ of 
sight. 
The same drawing may be also viewed monocularly as a 
tetrahedron, the edge b d of which lies in front of a c, or as 
a tetrahedron, the edge b d of which lies behind a c. The 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 221 
influence of the imagination and the will upon the visual 
process is extremely limited ; it is restricted to the directing 
of the attention and to the selection of the appropriate dis- 
position of the organ of sight for one of a number of cases 
given by habit, of which, however, each one, when chosen, 
takes its place with mechanical certainty and precision. 
Looking at the point e y we can, as a fact, produce either of 
the two optically possible tetrahedrons at will, according as we 
represent to ourselves b d as nearer or farther away than a c. 
The organ of sight is practised in the representation of these 
two cases, since it often happens that one body is partly 
covered by another. 
Loeb I thinks that the act of bringing Fig. 3 1 nearer to 
the eyes gives rise to short-distance accommodation, and 
thereby also to our seeing the fixed edge b e as raised. I 
have not been able to obtain any such definite result myself, 
nor can I find any sufficient theoretical ground for it, 2 
although I readily admit that changes in the distance of the 
figure easily lead to changes in our view of it. 
The same figure may, finally, be seen as a four-sided 
pyramid, if we imagine the conspicuously situated point of 
intersection e before or behind the plane abed. This is 
difficult to do, lib e d and a e c are two perfectly straight 
lines, because it conflicts with the habit of the organ of 
sight to see, without constraint, a straight line bent; the 
effort is successful only because the point e has a con- 
1 Loeb, " Ueber optische Inversion," Pfliiger's Archiv, Vol. XL., 
1887, p. 247. 
2 Hillebrand (" Verhaltnis von Akkommodation und Konvergenz 
zur Tiefenlokalisation," Zeitschrift fur Psychologic und Physiologic der 
Sinnesorgane, Vol. VII., p, 97) has proved the slight importance which 
accommodation has for the seeing of depth. 
222 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
spicuous position. But if there is a slight indentation at e, 
the attempt involves no difficulty. 
The effect of a linear perspective drawing is felt as 
unerringly by one who is ignorant of perspective as by 
one who is thoroughly conversant with the theory, provided 
he is able to disregard the plane of the drawing, a con- 
dition readily fulfilled in monocular observation. Reflexion, 
and even the remembrance of seen objects, have, according 
to my belief, little or nothing to do with the effect in 
question. Why the straight lines of a drawing are seen as 
spatial straight lines, has already been pointed out. Where 
straight lines appear to converge to a point 
in the plane of the drawing, the converging 
or approaching ends are transferred, accord- 
ing to the principles of probability and 
economy, to like or to nearly like depth. 
This gives us the effect of vanishing points. 
Fig. 29. 
It is possible to see such lines as parallel, 
but there is no necessity for such an impression. If we 
hold the drawing, Fig. 29, on a level with the eye, it may 
represent to us a glance down a passage-way. The ends 
ghef are transferred to like distances. If the distance 
is great, the lines ae^bf^cg^dh appear horizontal. If we 
raise the drawing, the ends efgh rise, and the floor abef 
seems to have an upward slope. Upon lowering the draw- 
ing, the opposite phenomenon is presented ; and analogous 
changes may be observed by moving the drawing towards 
the right or the left. In these facts, the elements of per- 
spective effect find simple and clear expression. 
Plane drawings, provided they consist entirely of straight 
lines, everywhere intersecting each other at right angles, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 223 
almost always appear plane. If oblique intersections and 
curved lines occur, the lines easily pass out of 
the plane ; as is shown, for example, by Fig. 30^ 
which may, without difficulty, be conceived as 
a curved sheet of paper. When outlines, such 
as are represented in Fig. 30, have assumed 
definite spatial form, and are seen as the 
IR 30. 
boundary of a surface, the latter, to describe 
it briefly, appears as flat as possible, that is to say, is 
presented with a minimum of deviation from the mean 
of the depth-sensation. 1 
The peculiar reciprocal action of lines intersecting 
obliquely in the plane of the drawing (or on the retina), 
whereby such lines are mutually forced out of the plane of 
the drawing (or out of the plane perpendicular 
to the line of sight) was first observed by me 
on the occasion of the above-mentioned (p. 209) 
experiment with the monocular inversion of a 
card. The card in Fig. 31, whose edge b e 
when turned outwards towards me is in a 
vertical position, assumes, when I succeed in 
seeing b e depressed, a recumbent position, like that of a 
book lying open upon my table, with the result that b 
appears further away than e. When one is once acquainted 
with this phenomenon, the inversion may be performed 
1 Here again, the depth-sensation resembles the potential function, 
in a space at the boundaries of which it is determined. This flat-as- 
possible surface does not coincide with the surface of minimal area, 
which would be obtained if the spatial outlines were made of wire, and 
then dipped in soap-suds, producing a Plateau's liquid film. 
224 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
with almost every object, and one can always observe along 
with the change of form or tilting over, this remarkable 
simultaneous change of position. The effect is especially 
astonishing in the case of transparent objects. Let abed 
be a section of a glass cube lying on a table / /, and let O 
be the eye (Fig. 32). on monocular inversion, the angle 
a is projected to a 1 ', b to the nearer point V ', t to </, and 
d to d'. The cube will seem to stand obliquely on its edge 
c f upon the table t' /'. In order that the drawing might 
afford a better survey of the 
phenomenon, the two images 
have been represented behind, 
not within one another. If a 
drinking-glass partly filled with 
a colored liquid be substi- 
tuted for the cube, it will be 
seen, together with the surface 
of the liquid, in a similar oblique position. 
With sufficient attention, the same phenomena may be 
observed with any linear drawing. If we place the page 
containing Fig. 31 vertically before us, and 
observe it monocularly, we shall see b project 
if b e be raised, but if b e be depressed b will 
retreat and e will project and come nearer to 
the observer. Loeb l notices that when this 
happens the points a e remain in the plane 
of the drawing. And, in fact, this makes the 
change of direction intelligible. If we draw 
the dotted lines, as in Fig. 3 2 A, and imagine the figure, 
so far as it lies outside the dotted triangle, obliterated, we 
1 Loeb, " Ueber optische Inversion," quoted p. 221 above. 
Fig 32 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 225 
are left with the image of a hollow or raised three-sided 
pyramid, which lies with its base in the plane of the draw- 
ing. Inversion no longer produces any sort of mysterious 
change of position. It would seem, therefore, that every 
point seen monocularly aims at the minimum deviation 
from the mean of the sensation of depth, which is attainable 
under the conditions of the experiment, and that the whole 
object seen aims at the minimum attainable amount of 
removal from Hering's nucleus-surface. 
When we consider the deformations which a plane 
rectilinear figure undergoes when traced in monocular 
space, all such deformations may be qualitatively reduced 
to the following principle : the legs of an acute angle are 
thrust out on opposite sides of the plane of the drawing, or 
of the plane perpendicular to the line of sight, and the legs 
of an obtuse angle are thrust out on the same side. In 
this process acute angles are magnified and obtuse angles 
diminished. All angles tend to become right angles. 
14. 
This principle suggests that the phenomenon just 
described is closely related to Zollner's pseudoscopy and the 
numerous phenomena connected with it. Here again 
everything turns on the apparent enlargement of acute and 
the apparent reduction of obtuse angles, except that the 
drawings are seen in the plane. But when they are seen in 
monocular space the pseudoscopic effects vanish, and the 
phenomena described above appear. Now although these 
phenomena have been much studied, no completely 
satisfactory explanation of them has as yet been offered. 
Naturally such superficial explanations as, for instance, the 
226 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
assumption that we are chiefly accustomed to see right 
angles, are inadmissible, if the investigation is not utterly to 
miscarry or to be prematurely broken off. We see oblique- 
angled objects often enough, but never, without artificial 
preparation, the surface of a liquid at rest and yet oblique, 
as we did in the experiment given above. Yet, the eye, it 
would seem, prefers the oblique liquid surface to an oblique- 
angled body. 
The elemental power displayed in these processes has, I 
believe, its root in far simpler habits of the organ of sight, 
habits whose origin doubtless antedates the civilized life of 
man. I once tried to explain the phenomena in question 
by a contrast of directions analogous to the contrast of 
colors, but without arriving at a satisfactory result. But 
more recent researches by Loeb, 1 Heymans, 2 and others, 
and observations by Hoefler 3 on curve-contrasts, are very 
much in favor of a theory of contrast. Moreover, quite 
lately at any rate, there is a decidedly increased tendency to 
adopt some purely physiological explanation. 4 
The principle of economy, again, has afforded me no 
enlightenment as far as Zollner's pseudoscopy is concerned. 
A somewhat greater prospect of success seems to be 
offered by the principle of probability. Let us conceive 
the retina as a perfect sphere and imagine the eye fixed 
upon the vertex of an angle a in space. The planes passing 
through the centre of the eye and the lines containing the 
angle, project these lines upon the retina, describing thereon 
1 Loeb, Pfluger's Archiv, 1895, p. 509. 
2 Heyman's Zcitschrift fttr Psychologic und Physiologic dcr Sinncs- 
organe, Vol. XIV., p. 101. 
3 Hoefler, Ibid., Vol. XII., p. i. 
4 Witasek, Ibid., Vol. XIX,, p. I. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 227 
a spherical segment having the angle A, which represents the 
angle of the monocular image. Now an infinite number of 
values for a, varying from o to 180, may correspond 
to a constant value of A, as will be seen if we reflect that 
the lines including the objective angle may assume every 
possible position in the planes of their projection. Conse- 
quently, to a seen angle A, we may have corresponding all 
the possible values of the objective angle a that 
can be obtained by causing each of the sides, b 
and c, of the triangle to vary between o and 
1 80. The actual result is, supposing the calcula- 
tion to be performed in a definite manner, that 
larger angles are the most probable objects 
corresponding to observed acute angles, and 
smaller angles the most likely counterparts of 
observed obtuse angles. I was not, however, 
in a position to determine whether those cases, 
which we are inclined to regard as geometrically equally 
probable, ought also to be regarded as physiologically 
equally probable a question which is both essential 
and important. Moreover, the whole conception has a 
much too artificial cast for me. 
I cannot refrain from mentioning here the attempt which 
has been made by A. Stohr to reach an explanation of the 
phenomena described above from an entirely new point of 
view. With the general considerations by which he was 
guided I am in full sympathy and agreement. on the other 
hand, I have not yet been able to convince myself that there 
is a demonstrable foundation of fact corresponding to his 
228 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
hypotheses. Moreover, the relations which he presupposes 
are so complicated that it is not easy to decide this question, 
without thoroughly covering the ground experimentally 
oneself. I therefore do not know whether Stohr's views 
will amount to a complete explanation on all points. In 
one of his less recent works * the assumption is made that 
to the dioptric image of the eye in front of the retina, 
there corresponds a catoptric image in the retina, the 
latter having relief in proportion to the depth of the former. 
Depth in the retina is thus both the determining factor for 
the sensation of depth in visual space, and the regulating 
factor in accommodation. As a matter of fact, I have always 
asked myself what the means could be by which the 
direction of change of accommodation is determined ; for 
change of accommodation cannot be determined merely by 
the magnitude of the circle of dispersion ; also there is only 
a loose connection between accommodation and conver- 
gence, and moreover a single eye by itself is accommodated. 
Against this view, on the other hand, must be set the 
numerous observations which have been made as to the 
worthlessness of accommodation for the sensation of depth. 
The great thickness of the retina in the eyes of insects 2 
suggests, again, that the perception of relief may be con- 
nected with some function of the retina. 
In two later works 3 he goes further, taking this theory as 
a basis. In the second of these books we find a view not 
unlike Scheffler's, but in a more physiological form. The 
1 Zur nativistiscken Behandhmg des Tiefensehens, Vienna, 1892. 
2 Exner, Die physiologic der facettierten Augen, p. 188, Vienna, 1891. 
3 Zur Erklamng der Zollnerschen Pseiidoskopie, Vienna, 1898 ; Bino- 
kulare Figurmischimg und Pseudoskopie, Vienna, 1900. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 229 
dominant view, according to which the images of positions 
which deviate more or less from the corresponding positions 
are fused into one unified impression, Stohr thinks is unten- 
able. "Where is the pointsman who arranges the change 
in such a way that, not only in extraordinary cases, but also 
as of set purpose, two stimuli may be brought into com- 
bination in the central organ over a quite unfamiliar pair of 
lines of conduction?" It is assumed that the retinae of 
both eyes naturally endeavour to minimalize the light- 
stimulus, and thus tend towards the equalization of unequal 
images. The nervous elements excite the ciliary muscle, 
doing this not only in a quite regular and uniform manner, 
but also, according to requirements, with great irregularity. 
Regular contraction of the ciliary muscle produces a greater 
bulging of the lens and slight contraction of the retina. If 
in this process the retinal elements carry their position-values 
with them, the same retinal image appears enlarged. In 
this way, according to Stohr, we can understand why 
Panum's proportional systems of circles (up to circles with 
radii in the proportion of 4 to 5) are seen, in virtue of the 
mutual adaptation of the two eyes, with identical parts of 
the retina, as simple and as having a size which is the mean 
of their sizes. By depicting one system in red and the 
other in green points alternately, so that in the united 
binocular image the red points appear between the green, 
Stohr proves that the fusion of the systems of circles is not 
caused by the suppression of one of the images. And 
irregular contraction of the ciliary muscle is supposed to 
produce various effects, (i) an irregular deformation ot 
the lens with very various displacements of the apices of 
the diacaustic of different pencils of rays, whereby change 
230 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
in the relief of the dioptric and catoptric images is pro- 
duced ; and (2) various minimal deformations of the retina. 
Stohr thinks that he can demonstrate the possibility of his 
theory by detailed calculations, and that he can prove the 
actuality of his presuppositions by investigating subjects 
with eyes in which the crystalline lens is absent or out of its 
proper position (aphakia). In any case his theory has led 
to experiments with surprising results, for instance, the 
stereoscopic indentation of straight lines, and, if only on 
that account, it deserves to be considered with respect. But 
although his whole conception of the eye and its parts as 
living organisms is extremely congenial to me, I have not 
yet been able to convince myself that the assumptions 
which he makes in order to explain more complicated cases 
of spatial vision everywhere fulfil their purpose. 1 
Stohr's departure from the traditions of physiological 
optics is very great. In itself this can be no reason for 
refusing to test his theory closely, especially since S. Exner's 
and Theodor Beer's 2 researches in comparative physiology, 
which have been so rich in beautiful and remarkable results, 
have made us familiar with eyes characterized by a com- 
plexity and variety of organic adaptation such as a physicist 
would scarcely have supposed possible a priori. It is 
possible that Stohr's views may apply to other organs of 
vision, although perhaps not to the human eye. 
1 The following book has subsequently appeared : A. Stohr, Grund- 
fragen der psychc-physiologischen Optik, Leipzig and Vienna, 1904. 
The problems in question are here discussed further. 
- Th. Beer, " Die Akkommodation des Fischauges," Pfliiger's 
Archiv Vol. LVIIL, p. 523 ; " Akkommodation des Auges in der 
Tierreihe," Wiener klinische Wochenschrift, 1808, No. XLII. ; 
" Ueber primitive Sehorgane," Ibid., 1901, Nos. XL, XII., XIII. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 231 
There are many phenomena that make it probable that 
the act of sight involves other processes of change in the 
eye which still require to be investigated. Stereoscopic 
images with prominent stereoscopic differences display, 
when they are gazed at for a long time, an enormous increase 
in the growth of their relief by successive stages, even 
though fusion has apparently been complete for some time. 
Wave-like curvatures and swellings have been observed in 
systems of fine, smooth, parallel lines, and these have been 
explained in a rather peculiar manner as referable to the 
incapacity of the mosaic-like texture of the retina to re- 
produce straight lines of such fineness. I have, however, 
always noticed this phenomenon when I have gazed for 
some time at systems of straight lines which are clearly 
visible and by no means micrometric. Thus the mosaic of 
the retina can have nothing to do with the matter. I 
should prefer to suppose that the exertion involved, perhaps 
by means of small displacements in Stohr's sense, intro- 
duces a certain disorder into the space-values. 1 
16. 
The ease of the transition from the process of seeing 
plane figures pseudoscopically to that of seeing them 
monocularly in space will probably help us to throw light 
upon the former. This conjecture is confirmed by the 
following facts. A plane linear drawing, monocularly ob- 
served, usually appears plane. But if the angles be made 
1 " Ueber die physiologische Wirkung raumlich verteilter Lichtreize," 
Wiener Sitzungsberichte, 2nd part, October 1866, pp. 7, 10, of the off- 
print. 
232 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
to vary and motion be introduced, every drawing of this 
sort will assume a solid form. We then generally see a 
solid body in rotation, such as I have described on a former 
occasion. 1 The well-known vibrating acoustic figures of 
Lissajous, which on varying their difference of phase, 
appear to lie on a revolving cylinder, afford a beautiful 
example of the process in question. 
Here, again, reference might be made to our habit of 
constantly dealing with solid bodies. In fact, solid bodies 
engaged in revolutions and turnings continually surround 
us. Indeed, the whole material world in which we move 
is, to a certain extent, a single solid body ; and without 
the help of solid bodies we could never attain to the con- 
ception of geometrical space. We do not generally notice 
the position of the single points of a body in space, but 
apprehend its dimensions directly. Herein lies, for the 
unpractised, the main difficulty of drawing a perspective 
picture. Children, who are accustomed to seeing bodies 
in their real dimensions, do not understand perspective 
foreshortenings, and are far better satisfied with simple 
outlines or silhouettes. I can well remember this condition 
of mind, and through this remembrance am able to com- 
prehend the drawings of the ancient Egyptians, which 
represent all parts of the body as far as possible in their 
true dimensions, thus pressing them, as it were, into the 
plane of the drawing, as plants are pressed in a herbarium. 
In the Pompeian wall-paintings, too, we still meet with 
a perceptible dislike for foreshortening, although here 
the sense of perspective is already manifest. The old 
1 " Beobachtungen iiber monokulare Stereoskopie," Sitzungsberichte 
der Wiener A kademie (1868), Vol. LVIII. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 233 
Italian masters, on the other hand, in the consciousness of 
their perfect mastery of the subject, often amuse themselves 
with excessive and sometimes even unbeautiful foreshorten- 
ings, which occasionally demand considerable exertion of 
the eye. 
There can be no question, therefore, but that we are 
much more familiar with the process of seeing solid bodies 
with the distances between their salient points unchanged, 
than with the process of separating out their depth, which 
is always the result, in the first place, of deliberate analysis. 
Accordingly, we may expect that wherever a coherent mass 
of sensations, which, in virtue of its continuous transitions 
and its common coloring, merged into a unity, exhibits 
spatial alteration, the change will be seen preferably as the 
motion of a solid body. I must confess, however, that this 
way of looking at the matter does not satisfy me. I believe, 
rather, that here, too, an elementary habit of the organ of 
sight is at the root of the matter, a habit which did not 
originally arise through the conscious experience of the 
individual, but, on the contrary, antecedently facilitated 
our apprehension of the movements of solid bodies. If 
we should assume, for example, that every diminution of 
the transverse dimension of an optical sensation-mass to 
which the attention was directed had the tendency to induce 
a corresponding augmentation of the dimension of depth, 
and vice versa, we should have a process quite analogous 
to that which we have already considered above (p. 199) 
and which was compared with the conservation of energy. 
This view is certainly much simpler and supplies an equally 
234 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
adequate explanation. Furthermore, it enables us to 
comprehend more easily how such an elementary habit 
could be acquired, how it could find expression in the 
organism, and how the disposition towards it could be 
inherited. 
As a sort of counterpart to the rotation of solid bodies 
exhibited to us by the organ of sight, I will cite here an 
additional observation. If an egg, or ellipsoid with dull, 
uniform surface be rolled over the top of a table, but in 
such manner that it does not turn about its axis of genera- 
tion, but performs jolting movements, we shall fancy 
we see, on viewing it binocularly, a liquid body, or large 
oscillating drop. The phenomenon is still more noticeable 
if the egg, with its longitudinal axis in a horizontal position, 
be set in moderately rapid rotation about a vertical axis. 
This effect is immediately destroyed when marks, whose 
movements we may follow, are made upon the surface of 
the egg. A rotating solid body is then seen. 
The explanations offered in this chapter are certainly 
far from complete, yet I believe that the considerations 
adduced will have some effect in stimulating and preparing 
the way for a more exact and thorough study of these 
phenomena. 
XI. SENSATION, MEMORY AND 
ASSOCIATION. 
I. 
THE foregoing discussions have shewn beyond all 
possible doubt that out of mere sensations no 
psychical life resembling ours even in the remotest degree 
could be constituted. When a sensation is forgotten the 
moment after it has vanished, the only possible result is a 
disconnected mosaic and series of psychic states, such as 
we have to suppose in the case of the lowest animals and 
the most degraded idiots. At this stage, a sensation which 
does not have some such effect as to stimulate violently 
to movement a sensation of pain, for instance will 
scarcely receive attention. For instance, the sight of a 
vividly-colored spherical body, which is not supplemented 
by a memory of smell and taste, by memory, in a word, 
of the properties of a fruit and the experiences connected 
with a fruit, remains unintelligible and is devoid of interest, 
in the manner that has been observed in " psychic blind- 
ness." The storing up and connexion of memories, and 
their power to evoke one another, in short, Memory 
and Association, are the fundamental requirements of a 
developed psychical life. 
What is memory? A psychical event leaves psychical 
traces behind it, but it also leaves physical traces. Physi- 
cally, as well as psychically, a child that has been burnt, or 
235 
236 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
stung by a wasp, behaves in quite a different way from a 
child that has not had this experience. For the psychical 
and the physical are different only according to the way 
in which they are regarded. Nevertheless it is extremely 
difficult to discover in the physical phenomena of the 
inorganic world characteristics having any affinity to memory. 
In the physics of the inorganic world everything seems 
to be determined by the circumstances of the moment, and 
the past seems to be entirely without any influence. The 
oscillations of a pendulum are equal, whether it is perform- 
ing its first oscillation or whether 1000 others have already 
taken place. Hydrogen combines with chlorine in the 
same way, no matter whether it was previously in combina- 
tion with bromine or with iodine. There are indeed, even 
in the physical sphere, cases in which the influence of the 
past is clearly expressed. The earth reveals to us the 
history of its geological past, and the moon does the same. 
My friend E. Suess has shewn me a piece of rock marked 
with a system of very peculiar congruent parallel fissures, 
which he very plausibly interprets as a prehistoric seismogram. 
A wire notices, so to speak, during a considerable time, 
every torsion that it sustains. Every spark of a discharge 
is an individual, and is influenced by the discharges that 
have preceded it. The insulating layer of the Leyden jar 
preserves a history of all the previous charges. 
The apparent contradiction is solved when we remember 
how in physics we are accustomed to idealize and 
schematize in an extreme degree the cases under considera- 
tion, always presupposing the simplest possible circum- 
stances. If we assume a mathematical pendulum, then no 
doubt the thousandth oscillation is as the first, and no 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 237 
traces of the past are visible, precisely because we disregard 
such traces. But a real pendulum wears away -its knife- 
edge, and is heated by internal and external friction, so that 
no oscillation, accurately considered, is exactly like any 
other. The result of every second and third torsion of a 
wire is somewhat different from what it would have been 
if there had been no previous torsions. If a similar 
schematization were possible in psychology, we should have 
men who behave identically and do not betray any of the 
influence of individual experiences. 
In reality every psychical process leaves indelible traces 
behind, just as every physical process does. In both 
spheres there are irreversible processes : entropy increases, 
or the bond of a friendship that has been broken, and then 
renewed, is felt. And every real process contains at any 
rate some irreversible components. 
Now it will be said, and with justice, that traces of the 
past are still far from being the same thing as memory. 
As a matter of fact, what is required to increase the 
resemblance is, that processes which have taken place in 
the past should be set up afresh by some slight impulse. 
Old violins that have been well played on, Moser's 
electrical images (that come out when breathed upon), 
and the phonograph, afford rather better examples. Still, 
violins and phonographs have to be played by external 
forces, while human beings and their memories play them- 
selves. For organic beings are not rigid material systems ; 
they are essentially forms of the dynamic equilibrium of 
238 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
currents of "matter" and "energy." Now it is the forms 
of the deviation of these currents from the state of dynamic 
equilibrium that always repeat themselves in the same way, 
according to the way in which they have once been intro- 
duced. Such variations in the forms of dynamic equilibrium 
have still been but little studied by inorganic physics. As 
a very rough example we may take changes in the flow of 
liquids, produced by some chance circumstance, and then 
maintained. If we screw up a tap so tightly that only a 
thin, quiet trickle of water comes but, a chance jolt is 
enough to disturb the unstable equilibrium of the trickle, 
and to cause the water to run out in drops with a persistent 
rhythm. Suppose that a chain, lying coiled up in a tub, 
is allowed to run over a roller acting as a sort of lever, 
and to fall into another tub at a lower level. If the chain 
is very long and the difference of level very great, the 
velocity may. become considerable, and then the chain, 
as is well known, has the property, whenever it is made to 
take a loop, of keeping this loop suspended in the air for 
some time, and continuing its flow in this shape. All these 
examples are very inadequate analogies to the plasticity 
which organisms possess for the repetition of processes 
and series of processes. 
The foregoing considerations are intended to shew that 
a comprehension of memory on physical lines is not un- 
attainable, although we are still very far removed from it. 
There can be no doubt that a considerable enlargement 
of the point of view of physical science by means of the 
study of organic beings is required, before physics is 
capable of such a task. The great richness of memory is 
founded, no doubt, upon the reciprocal interaction and 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 239 
connexion of the organs. Still, we probably must ascribe 
a rudimentary memory even to elementary organisms ; and 
if so, the idea inevitably suggests itself that, every chemical 
process in the organ leaves traces behind which are favour- 
able to the reappearance of the same process. 1 
It is well known that a very prominent position is given, 
in psychology, to the laws of association. These laws can 
be reduced to a single law, which consists in saying that if 
two contents of consciousness, A and B, have once appeared 
simultaneously, one of them, when it arises, will evoke the 
other. And in fact it is much easier to understand physical 
life when we have recognized the constant recurrence of 
this fundamental feature. The differences of mental pro- 
cess, in simple memory of an experience, in serious occupa- 
tion, and in the free exercise of fancy or day-dreaming, can 
easily be understood by means of the concomitant cir- 
cumstances. 2 It would, however, be a complete mistake to 
try to reduce <z//(p. 201) psychical processes to associations 
acquired during the life of the individual. In none of its 
phases do we meet with the psyche as a tabula rasa. At 
the very least we should have to assume innate associations 
side by side with the acquired. The innate impulses, 3 
1 Ostwald has made a bold attempt at a chemical theory of memory, 
based on his theories about katalysis. See his Vorlesimgen fiber 
Naturphilosophie, 1902, pp. 369 sqq. 
2 Mach, Erkenntnis und Irrtuni, 1905, pp. 29 sqq. 
3 The most striking of these, because they make their appearance at 
the moment when the mental faculties and the power of observation are 
fully developed, are the first manifestations of the sexual impulse. I 
240 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
which, to a psychology that is purely introspective and con- 
fined to itself, must necessarily appear to be innate associa- 
tions, are reduced by biology to innate organic connexions, 
and, in particular, to nervous connexions. It is therefore 
worth while to inquire whether all associations, including 
those acquired by the individual, do not depend upon 
innate connexions, of which some have been strengthened 
by use. 1 But in any case we must also ask whether the 
processes for the connexion of which in highly different- 
iated organisms special paths have been evolved, are not 
rather primary facts that already exist in lower organisms, 
and whether it is not their repeated occurrence accompanied 
by one another that has led to the formation of the paths 
in question. 2 A rational psychology cannot, of course, be 
content with temporary associations ; it will have to provide 
for fixed paths of connexion also. Again, room must be 
found for the possibility of spontaneous psychical pro- 
cesses, not due to association, which excite the neighbor- 
ing parts of the nervous system, and, when they are of great 
have been told by a perfectly trustworthy man, a person with a strong 
love of truth, that when he was a lad of sixteen, being quite innocent 
and inexperienced at the time, he saw a lady in a low-necked dress, 
and was startled to find that he was suddenly aware of a striking bodily 
change in his person ; this change he took to be an illness, and con- 
sulted a colleague about it. The whole complex of entirely new 
sensations and feelings which were then suddenly revealed to him was 
colored by a strong additional element of fear. 
1 H. E. Ziegler, " Theoretisches zur Tierphysiologie und vergleich- 
enden Neurophysiologie," Biologisches Zentralblatt ', Leipzig, 1900, 
Vol. XX , No. i. 
2 If we think of organic life as a state of dynamic equilibrium of 
various chemical component-phases, in which, speaking generally, a 
disturbance of one component causes a disturbance of the rest, we shall 
then be justified in hoping to explain, not only memory, but association 
too, on chemical lines. See p. 239 above, note i, and p. 99. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 241 
violence, even spread over the whole nervous system. on 
the one hand hallucinations, on the other reflex movements, 
are examples from the sensational and motor spheres, to 
which there are probably corresponding analogies in other 
spheres. 
Theories of the reciprocal action of the parts of the 
central nervous system seem to be opposed to a view which 
has been expounded by Loeb, 1 partly on the basis of his 
own work, partly on that of Goltz and Ewald. This view 
deserves to be noticed. According to it, the tropisms of 
animals are not essentially different from those of plants, 
the only advantage secured by the nerves in the case of 
animals being the more rapid transference of stimulus. 
The life of the nervous system is reduced to segmental 
reflexes, the co-ordination of movements to reciprocal 
excitation and transference of stimulus, and the instincts 
to chains of reflexes. The snapping-reflex of the frog, for 
instance, sets free the swallo wing-reflex. Organized centres 
of great complication are not assumed, but the brain itself 
is regarded as an arrangement of segments. At the bottom 
of all these theories there lies, so far as I can judge, a 
happily conceived and important effort to shake off the 
trammels of unnecessarily complicated assumptions impreg- 
nated with metaphysics. But I cannot agree with Loeb 
when he treats Darwin's phylogenetic research on the 
instincts as a fallacious and one-sided proceeding, which 
ought to be dropped and replaced by physico-chemical 
investigations. Research of that kind was, no doubt, not 
1 Loeb, Vergleichende Physiologic des Gehirns, Leipzig, 1899. 
9 
242 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
within Darwin's horizon. But it was precisely that fact 
which secured for him the freedom of vision necessary to 
his great and peculiar discoveries, which no physicist, qua 
physicist, could have made. We are, indeed, everywhere 
trying to obtain, where it is possible, some insight into the 
physical constitution of things, some acquaintance with 
their immediate, or causal, connexions. But it is far from 
being the case that this is already possible everywhere. 
And in cases where it is not possible, it would at all events 
only be another and a very dangerous piece of one-sidedness, 
to give up other fruitful points of view, which can always be 
regarded as provisional. The steam-engine can, as Loeb 
says, only be understood on physical lines. But this is only 
true of a particular given steam-engine. When it is a 
question of understanding the present forms of the steam- 
engine, physical considerations are not sufficient. The 
whole history of technical and social culture, and the 
geological presuppositions involved, must be taken into 
account. It is possible that, in the last resort, each one of 
these factors is susceptible of a physical explanation, but it 
has explained our difficulties long before that stage is 
reached. 1 
6. 
If I can imagine that, while I am having sensations, I 
myself or someone else could observe my brain with all the 
necessary physical and chemical appliances, it would then 
be possible to ascertain with what processes of the organism 
sensations of a particular kind are connected. The question 
so often asked, what is the lower limit of sensation in the 
1 Loeb, Vergleichende Physiologic des Gehirns, p. 1 30. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 243 
organic world, whether the lowest animals have sensations, 
or whether plants have, could then be brought nearer to its 
solution, at any rate so far as analogy goes. As long as 
this problem has not been solved in even one single special 
case, no decision of the question is possible. It is some- 
times even asked whether inorganic "matter" has sensa- 
tions. The question is natural enough, if we start from the 
commonly current physical conception which represents 
matter as the immediately and undoubtedly given reality 
out of which everything, inorganic and organic, is con- 
structed ; for sensation must either arise suddenly some- 
where or other in this structure, or else have been present 
in the foundation-stones from the beginning. From our 
point of view the question is merely a perversion. Matter 
is for us not what is primarily given. What is primarily 
given is, rather, the elements, which, when standing to one 
another in a certain known relation, are called sensations. 
Every scientific problem that can have any meaning for a 
human individual is concerned with the ascertainment of 
the dependence of the elements on one another. What in 
every-day life we call matter is a definite kind of connexion 
between the elements. The question as to whether matter 
has sensations would therefore run as follows : does sensa- 
tion belong to a definite kind of connexion between the 
elements, these elements themselves also being, when in a 
certain relation, always sensations ? Put in this form ; no 
one will want to ask the question. 1 Everything that can 
have any interest for us must be reached in the course of 
following out the general task of science. We ask whether 
1 Cf. Mach, Popular- Wissenschajtliche Vorlesungen, 3rd ed., 1903, 
p. 242. 
244 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
animals have sensations, when the assumption of sensations 
helps us better to understand their behaviour as observed 
by means of our own senses. The behaviour of a crystal is 
already completely determined for our senses ; and thus to 
ask whether a crystal has sensations, which would provide 
us with no further explanation of its behaviour, is a 
question without any practical or scientific meaning. 
XII. THE SENSATION OF TIME. 1 
i. 
MUCH more difficult than the investigation of 
space-sensation is that of time-sensation. Many 
sensations make their appearance with, others without, 
a clear sensation of space. But time-sensation accom- 
panies every other sensation, and can be wholly 
separated from none. We are referred, therefore, in our 
investigations here, to the variations of time-sensation. 
With this psychological difficulty is associated another, 
consisting of the fact that the physiological processes with 
which the sensation of time is connected are still less 
known, lie deeper, and are more thoroughly concealed 
than the processes corresponding to the other sensations. 
Our analysis, therefore, must confine itself chiefly to the 
psychological side, without approaching the question from 
its physical aspect, as is possible, in part at least, in the 
provinces of the other senses. 
It is scarcely necessary to lay special emphasis on the 
important part played in our psychical life by the temporal 
1 The position which I here take differs only slightly from that of my 
" Untersuchungen iiber den Zeitsinn des Ohres," Sitzber. d. Wiener 
Akademie, Vol. LI. , 1865. Into the details of these earlier experiments, 
begun in 1860, I shall not enter again here. Nor can I here discuss 
the plentiful material which has resulted from the works of Meumann, 
Munsterberg, Schumann, Nichols, Hermann, and others. Cp. Scripture, 
The New Psychology, London, 1897, p. 170. For a supplementary dis- 
cussion, see my Erkenntnis und Irrtttm, 1905, pp. 415 sqq. 
245 
246 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
ordering of the elements. The temporal order is even 
more important than the spatial. Reversal of the temporal 
order is even more destructive of a process than is the 
reversal of an object in space by turning it upside down ; 
reverse the temporal order, and an experience becomes 
something other than itself, something quite new. This is 
why the words of a speech or a poem are reproduced only 
in the order in which they were experienced and not in the 
reverse order as well, in which they would generally have 
a quite different meaning, or no meaning at all. If the 
whole acoustic sequence is reversed by saying something 
backwards, or by making a phonograph work backwards, 
we do not even recognize any longer the words that are the 
component parts of the speech. Definite memories are con- 
nected only with the definite sequence of sounds in which 
a word occurs, and it is only when the memories are 
evoked in a definite order corresponding to the word- 
sequence, that they combine together to produce a definite 
meaning. 1 But a sequence of notes too, a simple melody 
in which habit and association in any case play a very 
small part, becomes unrecognizable if it is temporally 
reversed. As regards even very elementary representa- 
tions and sensations, their temporal sequence forms part 
of the memory image of them. 
If we conceive time as a sensation, it seems less strange 
that, in a series passing in the order A B CD E, any member, 
C for instance, should call up to the memory only the 
members that follow it, and not those that precede. The 
J Cp. R. Wallaschek, Psychologic nnd Pathologic der Vorstellung, 
Leipzig, 1905, especially the chapter on " The Whole and its Parts/' 
pp. I5sqq. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 247 
memory-image of a building does not arise with the roof 
turned downwards. But, for the rest, it does not seem to 
be a matter of indifference whether the organ B is excited 
after an organ A, or vice versa. There is probably a 
physiological problem concealed here, which would re- 
quire to be solved before we can fully understand the 
fundamental psychological fact of the lapse of reproduced 
series in one determined direction. 1 It is possible that 
this fact is connected with the fact that an excitation 
propagates itself along entirely different paths according 
to the point at which it first enters into the organism, in 
the way in which this was explained for physical cases by 
the considerations on p. 92 and by Fig. \b. Even when 
the medium is perfectly homogeneous, if two excitations 
in it, starting from two distant points, spread uniformly, 
they will more nearly coincide at that one of the two points 
which was excited later. Thus, even in the simplest cases, 
the order of stimulation cannot be a matter of indifference. 
Let a note D follow a note C. The impression is quite 
different from what it would be if C followed D. The 
cause of this is chiefly the notes themselves, and their 
reciprocal action. For if the pause between the two notes 
is made sufficiently long, it is possible that we shall no 
longer distinguish the two cases. Something analogous 
can be observed with sequences of colors, and in general 
1 Perhaps the nervous elements are not merely endowed with a per- 
manent innate faculty of polar orientation, such as is made probable by 
the backward direction of the wave in the intestines and the musculature 
of snakes, and by galvanotropic phenomena, but perhaps they are also 
capable of a temporarily acquired polarity, as manifested in the 
inclusion of the time-series in memory, in practice, etc. Cp. Loeb and 
Maxwell, Zur Theorie des Galvanotropismus^ Pfliiger's Archiv, Vol. 
LXIII. p. 121 ; Loeb, Vergleichende. Gehirnphysiologie, pp. 108 sqq. 
248 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
with sensations of any kind. But if a note A is followed 
by a color or a smell B, we always know that B has followed 
A, and our estimate of the pause between A and B is 
practically not influenced at all by the quality of A and B. 
There must therefore be a further process, which is un- 
affected by variation in the quality of sensation, which is 
quite independent of the quality of sensation, and by 
means of which we estimate time. It is possible, indeed, 
to make a sort of rhythm out of entirely heterogeneous 
sensations, such as sounds, colors and impressions of 
touch. 
That a definite, specific time-sensation exists, appears to 
me beyond all doubt. The rhythmical identity of the two 
r 
adjoined measures, in which the sequence of the notes is 
quite different, is immediately recognized. We have not 
to do here with a matter of the understanding or of reflexion, 
but with one of sensation. In the same manner that 
bodies of different colors may possess the same spatial 
form, so here we have two tonal entities which, acoustically, 
are differently colored, but possess the same temporal 
form. As in the one case we pick out by an immediate 
act of feeling the identical components of the space-sensa- 
tion, so here we immediately detect the identical components 
of the time-sensation, or the sameness of the rhythm. 
It is of course only for small times that I hold that there 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 249 
is an immediate sensation of time. We judge and estimate 
longer times by remembering the processes that took place 
in them, that is to say, by splitting them up into the 
smaller parts of which we had an immediate sensation. 

on hearing a number of strokes of a bell, which are 
exactly alike acoustically, I discriminate between the first, 
second, third, and so on. Is it perhaps the accompanying 
thoughts, or other accidental sensations, with which the 
strokes of the bell happen to be associated, that produce 
these distinguishing marks? I do not believe that any 
one will seriously uphold this view How uncertain and 
unreliable, if this view were true, would our measurement 
of time be ! What would become of it if that accidental 
background of thought and sensation should suddenly 
vanish from memory? 
While I am reflecting upon something, the clock strikes, 
but I give no heed to it. After it has finished striking, it 
may be of importance to me to count the strokes. And 
as a fact, there arise in my memory distinctly one, two, 
three, four strokes. 1 give here my whole attention to this 
recollection, and by this means the subject on which I was 
reflecting during the striking of the clock, for the moment 
completely vanishes from me. The supposed background 
against which I could note the strokes of the bell, is now 
wanting to me. By what mark, then, do I distinguish the 
second stroke from the first ? Why do I not regard all 
the strokes, which in other respects are identical, as one ? 
Because each is connected for me with a special time- 
250 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
sensation which starts up into consciousness along with it. 
In like manner, I distinguish a memory-image from a 
creation of fancy by a specific time-sensation which is not 
that of the present moment. 
Since, so long as we are conscious, time-sensation is 
always present, it is probable that it is connected with the 
organic consumption necessarily associated with conscious- 
ness, that we feel the work of attention as time. During 
any severe effort of attention time is long to us, during 
easy employment short. When we are in a dull. state, 
hardly noticing our surroundings, the hours pass rapidly 
away. When our attention is completely exhausted, we 
sleep. In dreamless sleep, the sensation of time is lacking. 
When profound sleep intervenes, yesterday is connected 
with to-day only by an intellectual bond, apart from the 
feeling common to both that remains the same. 
I have already on a former occasion referred to the 
apparent difference of the ways in which animals of 
different sizes measure time. 1 But the measurement of 
time seems to change with age as well. How short the days 
seem to me now in comparison with the days of my youth ! 
And in my youth I used to watch an astronomical clock 
that struck the seconds ; when I think of that clock now, 
the second-stroke seems to be appreciably accelerated. I 
cannot shake off the impression that my physiological time- 
unit has become larger. 
The fatiguing of the organ of consciousness goes on con- 
1 Zeitsinn des OAres, p. 17. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 251 
tinually in waking hours, and the labor of attention increases 
just as continuously. The sensations connected with 
greater expenditure of attention appear to us to happen 
later. 
Normal as well as abnormal psychical events appear to 
accord with this conception. Since the attention cannot be 
fixed upon two different sense-organs at once, the sensa- 
tions of two organs can never occur together and yet be 
accompanied by an absolutely identical effort of attention. 
Hence, the one appears later than the other. Something 
analogous to the so-called personal equation of astronomers, 
having its ground in analogous facts, is also frequently 
observed in the same sense-province. It is a well-known 
fact that an optical impression which arises physically later 
may yet, under certain circumstances, appear to occur 
earlier. It sometimes happens, for example, that a surgeon, 
in bleeding, first sees the blood spirt out and afterwards his 
lancet enter. 1 Dvorak has shewn, 2 in a series of experi- 
ments which he carried out at my desire, years ago, that 
this relation may be produced at will, the object on which 
the attention is centred appearing (even when it is really 
from 1/8 to 1/6 of a second later) earlier- than that indirectly 
seen. It is quite possible that the familiar experience of 
the surgeon may find its explanation in this fact. The time 
which the attention requires to turn from one place at which 
it is occupied, to another, is shewn in the following experi- 
1 Compare Fechner, Psychophysik^ Leipzig, 1860, Vol. II., 
P- 433- 
2 Dvorak, u Ueber Analoga der persb'nlichen Differenz zwischen 
beiden Augen und den Netzhautstellen desselben Auges," Sitzbcr. d. 
konigl, bohm. Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften (Math-naturw. Classe), 
March 8, 1872, 
252 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
green 
red 
ment instituted by me. 1 Two bright red squares measuring 
two centimeters across and situated on a black background 
eight centimeters apart, are illuminated in a perfectly dark 
room by an electric spark concealed from the eye. The 
square directly seen appears red, but that indirectly seen 
appears green, ^and often quite 
intensely so. The retarded 
attention finds the indirectly 
seen square when it is already 
in the stage of Purkinje's positive 
after-image. A Geissler's tube 
with two bright red spots at a 
short distance from one another, 
exhibits, on the passage of a single discharge, the same 
phenomenon. 2 
The reader must be referred for details to Dvorak's paper. 
Of particular interest are his experiments on the stereoscopic 
(binocular) combination of non-simultaneous impressions. 3 
More recently Sandford 4 and Miinsterberg 5 have carried 
out experiments of this kind. 
indir. seen 
dir. seen 
Fig. 34- 
I have repeatedly observed an interesting phenomenon 
which should be cited here. I have been sitting in my 
1 Communicated by Dvorak, loc. cit. 
-G. Heymans could not succeed at first in this latter experiment, 
but has subsequently convinced himself of the correctness of my 
statement. 
3 Op. cit. , p. 2. 
* Sandford, American journal of Psychology, 1894, Vol. VI., p. 576. 
5 Miinsterberg, Psychological Reviezv, 1894, Vol. I., p. 56. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 253 
room, absorbed in work, while in an adjacent room experi- 
ments in explosions were being carried on. It regularly 
occurred that I shrank back startled, before I heard the report. 
Since the attention is especially inert in dreams, naturally 
the most peculiar anachronisms occur in this state, as every 
one has doubtless observed. For instance, we dream of a 
man who rushes at us and shoots, awake suddenly, and per- 
ceive the object which, by its fall, has produced the entire 
dream. Now there is nothing absurd in assuming that the 
acoustic stimulus enters simultaneously different nerve- 
tracks and is met there by the attention in some inverted 
order, just as, in the case above mentioned, I perceived 
first the general excitation and afterwards the report of the 
explosion. But in many cases it is undoubtedly a sufficient 
explanation to assume the interweaving of a sensation with 
the framework of a dream already present. 
6. 
If organic consumption, or, for that matter, the accumula- 
tion of fatigue-material were immediately felt, we might 
logically expect a reversal of time in dreams. The diffi- 
culty disappears if consumption and restitution are regarded 
as heterodromous processes in Pauli's sense (see p. 68 above). 
The eccentricities of dreams may all be accounted for by 
the fact that many sensations and representations do not 
enter consciousness at all, while others enter with too much 
difficulty and too late. Inertia of association is a funda- 
mental feature of dreams. The intellect often sleeps only 
in part. We converse very sensibly, in dreams, with persons 
long dead, but with no recollection of their death. I 
254 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
speak to a friend of a third person, and this friend is him- 
self the third person of whom I was speaking. We reflect, 
in the dream-state, concerning dreams, and recognize them 
as such by their eccentricities, which then at once cease to 
disturb us. I once dreamed very vividly of a mill. The 
water flowed downwards, in a sloping channel, away from the 
mill, and close by, in just such another channel, upwards 
to the mill. I was not at all disturbed by the contradic- 
tion. At a time when much engrossed with the subject 
of space-sensation, I dreamed of a walk in the woods. 
Suddenly I noticed the defective perspective displacement 
of the trees, and by this recognized that I was dreaming. 
The missing displacements, however, were immediately 
supplied. Again, while dreaming, I saw in my laboratory 
a beaker filled with water, in which a candle was serenely 
burning. " Where does it get its oxygen from ? " I thought. 
11 It is absorbed in the water," was the answer. " Where 
do the gases produced in the combustion go to?" The 
bubbles from the flame mounted upwards in the water, 
and I was satisfied. W. Robert l has made the excellent 
observation that it is principally perceptions and thoughts, 
which owing to some interruption we have been unable to 
carry to a conclusion during the day, of which the thread 
is taken up in dreams. And as a matter of fact we fre- 
quently draw the elements of our dreams from the events 
of the preceding day. Thus I used to be able to refer, 
with almost complete certainty, the dream about the light 
in the water to a certain experiment in my lectures with an 
electric carbon-light under water, 2 and the dream about 
1 W. Robert, Ueber den Traum, Hamburg, 1886. 
* Prinzipien der Warmelehre> 2nd ed., 1900, p. 444. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 255 
the mill to my experiments with the apparatus described on 
p. 143 (Fig. 19) above. Visual hallucinations play the prin- 
cipal part in my dreams. I have acoustic dreams less often, 
though I clearly hear conversations, the sound of bells, and 
music in my dreams. 1 Every sense, even the sense of taste, 
can come into play in dreams, though some more rarely 
than others. Since reflex excitability is greatly heightened 
in the dream-state, and the conscience on the other hand 
very much weakened owing to the inertia of association, 
one is capable of almost any crime in dreams, and at the 
stage of waking may go through the acutest torments. 
Anyone who allows such experiences to affect him, must 
entertain grave doubts as to the Tightness of our method of 
exercising justice, which consists in making good one misery 
by a second, the second being added to the first by means 
of a process that is revolting because deliberate, cruel, and 
solemn. 
I should not like to let this opportunity slip of recommend- 
ing to the reader the excellent book of M. de Manaceine. 2 
What was said above as to the inadequacy of temporary 
associations as an explanation of psychical life (see pp. 201, 
239, 240) holds for the dream-state also. We have to add 
that the faintest traces of something which has long been 
forgotten for the waking consciousness, the slightest disturb- 
ances of health and disposition which have to fall into the 
background during the bustle of the day, can make them- 
selves felt in dreams. In his Philosophic der Mystik (1885, 
p. 123) Du Prel poetically compares this process with the 
1 Wallaschek, "Das musikalische Gedachtnis," Vierteljahrsschrift 
fiir Musikivissenschaft, 1882, p. 204. 
2 M. de Manac6ine, Sleep, its Physiology ', etc., London, 1897. 
256 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
way in which the faintly glimmering starry firmament be- 
comes visible when the sun has set. This book contains 
many passages of remarkable and profound insight. The 
man of science, in particular, whose critical sense is directed 
towards the nearest practicable object of research, reads it 
with pleasure and profit, without allowing himself to be led 
astray by the author's inclination towards the fantastic, the 
miraculous and the extraordinary. 
If time-sensation is connected with the growth of organic 
consumption or with the equally continuous growth of the 
effort following upon attention, then we can understand why 
physiological time is not re- 
versible, any more than physi- 
I f 1 i cal time, but moves only in one 
direction. As long as we are 
in the waking state, consumption and the labor of attention 
can only increase, not diminish. The two accompanying 
bars of music, which present a symmetry to the eye and 
to the understanding, shew nothing of the sort as regards 
the sensation of time. In the province of rhythm, and of 
time in general, there is no symmetry. 
8. 
It is perhaps an obvious and natural, though still an im- 
perfect conception, to regard the " organ of consciousness " 
as capable, in a small degree, of all the specific energies, of 
which each sense-organ is able only to display a few. Hence 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 257 
the shadowy and evanescent character of representation as 
compared with sensation, through which it must be con- 
stantly nourished and refreshed. Hence also the capacity 
of the organ of consciousness to serve as a bridge of 
connexion between all sensations and memories. With 
every specific energy of the organ of consciousness, we 
should then have to conceive still another particular energy, 
the sensation of time, associated, so that none of the former 
could be excited without the latter. Should this new energy 
appear physiologically superfluous and only invented ad hoc, 
we might at once assign to it an important physiological 
function. What if this energy kept up the flow of blood 
that nourishes the brain-parts in their work, guided this 
current to its destination, and regulated it ? Our con- 
ception of attention and of time-sensation would then 
receive a very material basis. The fact that there is 
only one cohering time, too, would become intelligible, 
since the partial attention given to one sense is 
always drawn from the total attention, and is determined 
by it. 
Such a theory is strongly suggested by Mosso's work on 
plethysmography and by his observations on the circulation 
of the blood in the brain. 1 William James gives a cautious 
assent to this conjecture. 2 James indicates that it 
would be desirable to put it into a more definite and 
detailed form, but I have unfortunately not been able to 
do this. 
1 Mosso, Kreislauf dcs Bhites im Gehirn, Leipzig, 1881. Cf. also 
Kornfeld, Ueber die Beziehiing von Atmung und Kreislauf zur geistigen 
Arbeit, Briinn, 1896. 
2 W. James, Psychology, Vol. I., p. 635. 
R 
258 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
In listening to a number of similar strokes from a bell, 
we can distinguish each from the others in memory and 
also count them in memory, provided they are few in 
number. If the number is large, however, we distinguish 
the last ones from one another, but not the first. In this 
case, if we would not make a mistake, we must count them 
immediately upon their being sounded, that is, we must 
voluntarily connect each stroke with an ordinal symbol. 
The phenomenon is perfectly analogous to that which we 
observe in the province of the space-sense, and is to be 
explained on the same principle. In walking forwards, we 
have a distinct sensation that we are moving away from a 
starting-point, but the physiological measure of this removal 
is not proportional to the geometrical. In the same 
manner, elapsed physiological time is subject to perspectival 
contraction, its single elements becoming less and less 
distinguishable. 1 
10. 
If a special time-sensation exists, it goes without saying 
that the identity of two rhythms will be immediately re- 
cognized. But we must not leave the fact unnoticed that 
two rhythms which are the same physically may appear 
very different physiologically, just as the same space-figure 
by change of position may give rise to different physio- 
logical space-forms. The rhythm represented by the 
following notes, for example, appears quite different accord- 
1 Cp. p. 134. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 259 
ing as we regard the short thick, or the long thin vertical 
lines, or the dotted lines, as marking the bars. Evidently 
this is connected with the fact that the attention (guided by 
the accent) sets in at i, 2, or 3, that is, that the sensations 
nn 
of time corresponding to the successive beats are compared 
with different initial sensations. 
When all the times of a rhythm are prolonged or 
shortened, a similar rhythm arises, which, however, can only 
be felt as similar when the prolongation or shortening does 
not exceed the limit imposed by the immediate sensation 
of time. 
The rhythm represented in the following diagram appears 
physiologically similar to the preceding, but only when 
similarly-marked bars are taken in the two that is, when 
the attention sets in at homologous points of time. Two 
physical time-constructions may be termed similar when all 
the parts of the one stand in the same relation to one 
another as do the homologous parts of the other. But 
physiological similarity makes its appearance only when the 
above condition is likewise fulfilled. Furthermore, so far as 
I am able to judge, we recognize the identity of the time- 
ratios of two rhythms only when the same are capable of _. 
being represented by very small whole numbers. Thus we 
260 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
really notice immediately, only the identity or non-identity 
of two times, and, in the latter case, we recognize the ratio 
of the two only by the fact that one part is exactly contained 
in the other. Herewith we have an explanation of the fact 
that, in marking time, the time is always divided into 
absolutely equal parts. 1 
The conjecture thus forces itself upon us, that the sensa- 
tion of time is closely connected with periodically or 
rhythmically repeated processes. But it is scarcely capable 
of being proved, though the attempt has been made in some 
quarters, that the measurement of time in general is based 
on breathing or on the pulse. These questions, however, 
are by no means simple. Many processes, of course, take 
place rhythmically in the bodies of animals, without it 
being possible for us to attribute to them any particular 
sense for time, rhythm or beat. When a pair of horses is 
driven past my house, I can hear for a long time the 
coincidence and alternation of the hoof-beats of the two 
horses fading away into the distance in regular periods. 
Thus each horse keeps to its own time without troubling 
about that of the other horse, and without adapting itself to 
the other. Two men harnessed together would find this 
almost intolerable. Wallaschek mentions the deficiency 
of the sense of time in horses, and also the difficulty of 
keeping up the appearance of it in circus performances. It 
can scarcely be upon the coarser bodily processes that the 
feeling for time is immediately based. Probably it must be 
referred rather to a superior psychical sensibility, in virtue 
of which a trifling psychical circumstance determines the 
1 The similarity of space-figures would be felt, according to this theory, 
much more immediately than the similarity of rhythms. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 261 
attention to notice an otherwise indifferent process. But 
when processes that keep time are carefully observed, and 
such observation always involves a certain amount of co- 
operation and imitation, the psychical functions, and 
finally the coarser bodily functions themselves also, then 
become adapted to the time. 1 
Dr. R. Wlassak has communicated to me in conversation 
a remark which I will reproduce in his own words : 
"When the sensations are connected with a vivid 
emotional coloring, time-values are always markedly dimin- 
ished ; this fact accords with the hypothesis that the sensa- 
tion of time depends on organic consumption. Xhe rule 
holds both for stretches of time that are filled with strongly 
pleasurable sensations and for those filled with unpleasant 
sensations. on the other hand, the sensations that oscillate 
round the indifference-values of emotional coloring are con- 
nected with relatively indistinct sensations of time. These 
facts indicate that the nervous processes belonging to the 
sensations of time and to the emotions respectively offer 
certain analogies. 
In point of fact, all attempts to frame a ^physiological 
theory of the emotions bring the emotions into relation with 
consumption; as is done, for instance, in Meynert's or in 
Avenarius' theory of the emotions." 
1 Wallaschek, Anfilnge der Tonkunst, Leipzig, 1903, pp. 270, 271. 
This book, a profusely illustrated German edition of an English book 
by the same author (Primitive Music, London, 1903), contains many 
very valuable observations on the questions discussed in this and the 
following chapters. 
XIII. SENSATIONS OF TONE. 1 
i. 
AS regards tone-sensations, also, we are restricted mainly 
to psychological analysis. As before, the beginning 
of an investigation is all we can offer. 
Among the sensations of tone possessing greatest im- 
portance for us are those excited by the human voice, as 
utterances of pleasure and pain, of expressions of the will, 
and of the communication of thoughts by speech, etc. Nor 
can there be any doubt that the voice and the organ of 
hearing bear a close relation to each other. The simplest 
and distinctest form in which sensations of tone reveal their 
remarkable characteristics is music. Will, emotion, the 
expression of sound, and the sensation of sound, have 
certainly a strong physiological connexion. There is a 
good deal of truth in the remark of Schopenhauer 2 that 
music represents the will, and in fact generally in the 
"* Apart from details, I have held the position here taken up since 1865. 
Stumpf, whom I must here thank for the repeated consideration of my 
work, has many points of detail (Tonpsychologie, Leipzig, 1883, Vol. I.) 
that appeal to me. The view expressed on page 1 19 of his work, how- 
ever, seemed incompatible with the principle of parallelism, my 
fundamental axiom of research ; though the remark which he directs 
against Lipps (Beitrdge zur Akuitik, Vol. I., p. 47, footnote), repre- 
sents an approximation to my point of view. Compare my note, " Zur 
Analyse der Tonempfindungen," Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akademie^ 
Vol. XCIL, II. Abth., p. 1282 (1895). 
8 Schopenhauer, Die Welt als Wille tind Vorstelhtng. 
262 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 263 
designation of music as a language of emotion ; although 
this is scarcely the whole truth. 
2. 
Following the precedent of Darwin, H. Berg has, to put 
it shortly, attempted to derive music from the amatory cries 
of monkeys. 1 We should be blind not to recognize the 
service rendered and enlightenment conveyed by the work 
of Darwin and Berg. Even at the present day, music has 
power to touch sexual chords, and is, as a fact, widely made 
use of in courtship. But as to the question wherein con- 
sists the agreeable quality of music, Berg makes no satis- 
factory answer. And seeing that in musical theory he 
adopts Helmholtz's position of the avoidance of beats and 
assumes that the males who howled least disagreeably 
received the preference, we may be justified in wondering 
why the most intelligent of these animals were not prompted 
to maintain silence altogether. 
The importance of tracing the connexion of a given 
biological phenomenon with the preservation of the species, 
and of indicating its phylogenetic origin, cannot be under- 
rated. But we must not imagine that in having accomplished 
this we have solved all the problems connected with the 
phenomenon. Surely no one will think of explaining the 
element of pleasure in the specific sexual sensation by show- 
ing its connexion with the preservation of the species. We 
should be more likely to acknowledge that the species is 
preserved because the sexual sensation is pleasurable. 
Although music may actually remind our organism of the 
1 H. Berg, Die Lust an der Musik, Berlin, 1879. 
264 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
courtship of distant progenitors, it must, if it was ever used 
for wooing, have contained at the start some positive 
agreeable quality, which, to be sure, may be reinforced at 
the present time by that memory. To take an analogous 
case from individual life, the smell of an oil-lamp as it goes 
out almost always agreeably reminds me of the magic lantern 
which excited my wonder as a child. Yet in itself the 
smell of the lamp is none the less disgusting for this reason. 
Nor does the man who is reminded, by the scent of roses, 
of a pleasant experience, believe, on this account, that the 
scent was not previously agreeable. It has only gained by 
the association. 1 And if the view in question cannot 
sufficiently explain the agreeable quality of music per se, it 
assuredly can contribute still less to the solution of special 
questions, as, for instance, why, in a given case, a fourth 
is preferred to a fifth. 
A rather one sided view of the sensations of tone would 
be obtained if we were to consider only the province of 
speech and music. Sensations of tone are not only a 
means of communicating ideas, of expressing pleasure and 
pain, of discriminating between the voices of men, women, 
and children ; they are not mere signs of the exertion or 
passion experienced by the person speaking or calling; 
they also constitute the means by which we distinguish 
between large and small bodies when sounding, between 
the tread of large and small animals. The highest tones, 
the very ones which the vocal organs of man cannot pro- 
1 Fechner, notably, has emphasized the significance of association 
for aesthetics. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 265 
duce, presumably are of extreme importance for the deter- 
mination of the direction from which sounds proceed. 1 In 
fact, it is more than likely that these latter functions of 
sensations of tone antedated, in the animal world, by a long 
period, those which merely perform a part in the social life 
of animals. By inclining a piece of cardboard in front of 
the ear, anyone can convince himself that it is only those 
noises which contain very high tones, such as the rustling 
and hissing of a gas flame, of a steam kettle, or of a water- 
fall, that are modified by reflexion according to the position 
of the cardboard, and that deep tones remain entirely 
uninfluenced. This shews that it is only in virtue of their 
effect on high tones that the two ear-conchs can be 
used as indicators of direction. 2 
There is no one but will cheerfully acknowledge the 
decided advance effected by Helmholtz in the analysis of 
auditory sensations, 3 following on the important works of 
his predecessors, Sauveur, Rameau, R. Smith, Young, Ohm, 
1 Mach, " Bemerkungen liber die Function der Ohrmuschel " 
(Troltsch's Archiv Jur Ohrenheilkunde, New Series, Vol. III., p 72). 
Compare also Mach and Fischer, "Die Reflexion und Brechurig 
des Schalles, Fogg. Ann., Vol. CXLIX., p. 221; A. Steinhauser, 
Theorie des binaurealen Horens, Vienna, 1877. 
2 I once had occasion to observe that tame marmots that were quite 
insensible to deep and loud noises, were suddenly frightened, and 
always rushed into hiding, whenever anyone produced a high-pitched 
noise by rubbing straw or crackling paper. Children a few months old 
are also very sensitive to such noises. 
3 Helmholtz, Die Lehre von den l^onempfindungen, 1st ed. , Bruns- 
wick, 1863. 
266 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
and others. 1 Following his principles, we recognize in 
noises combinations of musical tones, of which the number, 
pitch, and intensity vary with the time. In compound 
musical sounds, or clangs, we generally hear, along with the 
fundamental n, the over-tones or partial tones" 2n, $n, 471, 
etc., each of which corresponds to simple pendular vibra- 
tions. If two such musical sounds, to the fundamentals 
of which the rates of vibration n and m correspond, be 
melodically or harmonically combined, there may result, 
if certain relations of n and m are satisfied, 2 a partial coin- 
cidence of the harmonics, whereby in the first case the 
relationship of the two sounds is rendered perceptible, and 
in the second a diminution of beats is effected. All this 
cannot be disputed, although it may not be considered 
exhaustive. 
We may also give our assent to Helmholtz's physiological 
theory of audition. The facts observed on the simultaneous 
sounding of simple notes make it highly probable that there 
exists, corresponding to the series of vibration-rates, a series 
of terminal nervous organs, so that for all the different rates 
of vibration there are different end-organs, each of which 
responds to only a few, closely adjacent rates of vibration. 
on the other hand, Helmholtz's physical theories as to the 
function of the labyrinth have proved untenable. I shall 
return to this point. 
5- 
If we assume with Helmholtz that all noises admit of 
1 Cp. " Zur Geschichte der Akustik " in my Popiilar-ivissenschoftliche 
Vorlesungen. 
3 The /th harmonic of n coincides with the ^th of m when pn - qm t 
that is m = (plq) n, where/ and q are whole numbers. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 267 
being resolved into sensations of tone varying in duration, 
it seems superfluous to seek further for a special auditive 
organ for noises, and Helmholtz himself soon gave up so 
inconsequent a procedure. A long time ago (in the winter 
of 1872-73) I took up the question of the relation of noises 
(especially that of sharp reports) to musical tones, and 
found that every degree of transition between the two may 
be demonstrated. A tone of one hundred and twenty-eight 
full vibrations, heard through a small radial slit in a slowly 
revolving disc, contracts, when its duration is reduced to 
from two to three vibrations, to a short, sharp concussion 
(or weak report) of very indistinct pitch, while with from 
four to five vibrations, the pitch is still perfectly distinct. 
on the other hand, with sufficient attention, a pitch, though 
not a very definite one, may be detected in a report even 
when the latter is produced by an aperiodic motion of the 
air (the wave of an electric spark, exploding soap-bubbles 
filled with 2ff+ O). We may easily convince ourselves, 
furthermore, that in a piano from which the damper has 
been lifted, large exploding bubbles mainly excite to sym- 
pathetic vibration the lower strings, while small ones 
principally affect the higher strings. This fact, it seems 
clear to me, demonstrates that the same organ may be the 
mediator of both tone and noise sensation. We must 
imagine that weak aperiodic movements of the air having 
short durations excite all, though preferably the small and 
more mobile end-organs, whilst more powerful and more 
lasting movements of the air excite the larger and more 
inert end-organs as well, which from being less damped 
perform vibrations of greater amplitude and are thus 
noticed ; and furthermore that even in the case of com- 
268 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
paratively weak periodic movements of the air, the stimulus 
appears, by an accumulation of effects, in some definite 
member of the series of end-organs. 1 The sensation excited 
by a report of low or high pitch is qualitatively the same 
as that produced by striking at once a large number of 
adjacent piano-keys either high or low in the scale, only 
more intense and of shorter duration. Moreover, in the 
single excitation produced by a report, the beats connected 
with periodic intermittent excitations are eliminated. 
6. 
The work of Helmholtz excited general admiration on 
its first appearance ; but of late years it has been subjected 
to various critical attacks, and it almost seems to be as 
much underestimated now as it was originally overesti- 
mated. Physicists, physiologists and psychologists have 
had nearly forty years in which to test the three several 
sides of the theory, and it would have been a marvel if 
they had not found out its weak spots. Without making 
any pretence to completeness, we will now consider the 
principal critical objections to it, taking first together the 
objections which have been urged from the physical and 
physiological side, and, secondly, those of the psycholo- 
gists. 
1 I gave an account of part of my experiments, which were a con- 
tinuation of Dvorak's researches on the after-images due to variations 
of stimulus (1870), in the August number of Lotos, 1873. I have never 
before mentioned the experiments relative to the excitement of piano- 
tones by explosions. It will not be amiss, perhaps, if I do so here. 
Ffaundler, S. Exner, Auerbach, Briicke, W. Kohlrausch, Abraham 
and Brtihl, and others, subsequently treated the same questions in 
detail, and from various points of view. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 269 
Helmholtz assumed, for psychological and physical 
reasons, that the inner ear consists of a system of resonators, 
which singles out the members of Fourier's series, corre- 
sponding to the form of vibration presented, and hears 
them as partial tones. on this view, the relation between 
the phases of the partial vibrations can exert no influence 
on sensation. As against this view, Konig, 1 an eminent 
specialist in acoustics, tried to prove that mere displacement 
of the phases of the partial pendular vibrations causes a 
change in the sensational impression or "sound-color." 
L. Hermann, 2 however, succeeded in shewing that when 
the direction of movement of a phonograph is reversed, 
no change of sound-color results. According to Hermann, 
the individual sinuous bands of Konig's wave-siren do not 
produce any simple tones, and Konig's conclusions must 
therefore be based on a mistaken presupposition. 3 This 
difficulty may therefore be taken as removed. 
The phenomena connected with the combination of 
tones are not so easily explicable on Helmholtz' point of 
view. Young supposed that beats of sufficient rapidity 
1 R. Konig, Quelques experiences d'acoustique, Paris, 1882. 
2 L. Hermann, "Zur Lehre von der Klangwahrnehmung," Pfliiger's 
Archiv, Vol. LVI., 1894, p. 467. 
3 As long ago as 1867, I instituted experiments with a special kind of 
siren, very similar to one of Konig's apparatus. The casing of a 
cylinder was fitted with rings in which were cut wave-shaped slips in 
similar pairs capable of mutual displacement towards one another, so 
that the intensity and the phase of the partial tone under investigation 
could be varied at will. But it appeared on experiment that the wave- 
shaped slits did not yield any simple tones when air was blown against 
them through a slit parallel to the ordinate of the waves. As my 
apparatus was still pretty imperfect, and did not fulfil its purpose, 
which was to compound a sound from partial tones of given intensity 
and phase, I have not published any account of these experiments. 
270 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
could themselves be heard as tones that is to say, that 
they become compound tones. But since it is impossible 
to excite any resonator by means of beats, to the tempo of 
which it is tuned, but only by means of tones, it would be 
impossible, on the resonance theory, to hear any compound 
tones. Helmholtz therefore postulated at the outset that 
compound tones must either be explained objectively by 
means of powerful tones in virtue of the deviation of similar 
vibrations from linearity, or subjectively by means of 
asymmetrical or non-linear conditions of vibration of the 
resonating parts of the inner ear. Now Konig 1 failed to 
prove the existence of objective compound tones, but 
discovered on the other hand that, even between tones 
widely removed from one another, there are beats which 
can invariably be heard as particular tones when the 
sequence is sufficiently rapid. Hermann 2 detected com- 
pound tones with co-operating tones of such feebleness, 
that the compound tones seem entirely inexplicable 
on Helmholtz' theory, either objectively or subjectively. 
Hermann accordingly holds the view, associating himself 
1 Konig, op. cit. He got his tones by a very powerful tuning-fork, 
and I could not help conjecturing when his book appeared that, in 
connexion with his observations of the beats, the overtones came into 
play in various ways. Since then Stumpf has actually demonstrated 
the co-operation of such overtones ( Wiedemann's Annalen, New Series, 
Vol. LVII. , p. 660). Thus the theory of Helmholtz is safe on this side. 
Still, the objection remains that the objective compound tones do not 
exist (Konig, Hermann), and that subjective compound tones occur 
in circumstances which are not compatible with Helmholtz' theory 
(Hermann). Cp. also M. Meyer, " Zur theorie der Differenztone und 
der Gehorsempfindungen Ueberhaupt," Zeitschrijt fur Psychologic. 
Vol. XVI., p. I. 
2 Hermann, " Zur Theorie der Kombinationstone," Pfliiger's Archiv, 
Vol. XLIX., 1891, p. 499. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 271 

on this point with Konig, that the ear re-acts, not only 
to wave-shaped vibrations, but also, with a sensation deter- 
mined by the duration of the period, to every kind of 
periodicity. 
The physical resonance-theory seems, at any rate, in its 
original form, not tenable; but Hermann 1 thinks that it 
can be replaced by a physiological resonance-theory. I 
will deal later with this view, as well as with Ewald's new 
physical theory of audition. 
We now turn to the principal objections brought against 
Helmholtz from psychological points of view. The lack of 
a positive factor in the explanation of consonance has been 
very generally felt, the mere absence of beats not being 
regarded as a sufficient and satisfactory characterization of 
harmony. Thus A. v. Oettingen 2 feels the want of some 
expressed positive element characteristic of each interval 
(p. 30), and refuses to regard the value of an interval as 
dependent upon the physical accident of the overtones 
contained in the sounds. He believes that the positive 
element in question is to be found in the accompanying 
remembrance of the common fundamental tone (or tonic), 
as the harmonics of which the composite notes or clangs of 
the interval have often occurred, or in the accompanying 
remembrance of the common overtone (or phonic) 3 belonging 
to the two (pp. 40, 47). on the negative side of his criticisms 
1 Hermann, Pfliiger's Arckiv, Vol. LVI. , p. 493. 
z Harmoniesystem in dtialer Entwicklung (Dorpat, 1 866), p. 30. 
3 [The lowest of the harmonics common to all I term the coincident 
or phonic harmonic. Von Oettingen, Harmoniesystem in dualer 
Entvoicklung, p. 32. Quoted by translator.] 
272 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
I am in complete agreement with Von Oettingen. But 
" remembrance " does not quite fill the need of the theory, 
for consonance and dissonance are not matters of represen- 
tative activity, but of sensation. My opinion, therefore, 
is that A. von Oettingen's conception is physiologically 
inadequate. His enunciation of the principle of duality, 
however (or of the principle of the tonic and phonic 
relationship of composite notes), as also his conception of 
dissonances as indeterminate composite musical sounds 
admitting of more than one interpretation (p. 224), appear 
to me to be valuable and positive services to science. 1 
8. 
Stumpf has in various writings criticized the doctrine of 
Helmholtz with great penetration. 2 He questions, in the 
first place, the two different definitions which Helmholtz 
gives of consonance, the definition by disappearance of 
beats, and the definition by coincidence of partial tones, 
pointing out that the former is inapplicable to and not 
characteristic of melodic sequence, and the latter inappli- 
cable to and not characteristic of harmonic combination. A 
1 A popular statement of the principle of duality, of which Euler 
Tentamen novce theories tnusica, p. 103), D'Alembert (Elemens de 
musique-, Lyons, 1766), and Hauptmann (Die Natur der Harmonik 
und Metrik, Leipzig, 1853, translation by W. E. Heathcote, London, 
Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1888), had all a faint inkling, is to be found 
in my Popular Scientific Lectures (Chicago, 1894), under the caption 
" Symmetry" (originally published in 1872). Perfect symmetry, such 
as is found in the province of sight, cannot be imagined in music, since 
sensations of tone do not constitute a symmetrical system. 
2 I am here chiefly following Stumpf's Beitrage zur Akustik und 
Musi kwissensc haft, Heft I, Leipzig, 1898. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 273 
pure triple compound note, intermitting according to the 
nature of the beats, is not a dissonance. on the other 
hand, examples can be given of the simultaneous sounding 
of tones far removed from one another, which produce a 
violent dissonance, although the beats become imper- 
ceptible. If two notes of the tuning-fork are distributed 
one to each ear, the beats do indeed sink very much into 
the background, but without the distinction between con- 
sonance and dissonance becoming any less. Subjectively 
heard tones, too, such as ringing in the ears, can be experi- 
enced as dissonances, of course without the beats being 
heard. Tones, finally, that are merely represented, also 
appear as consonant and dissonant, without the representa- 
tion of beats playing any essential part in the process. 
The coincidence of the partial tones ultimately disappears, 
when no overtones are present, without necessarily causing 
the disappearance of the distinction between dissonance 
and consonance. I will pass over Stumpf s polemic against 
the explanation of consonance by means of unconscious 
counting, a view which will probably find few supporters. 1 
Equally readily will it be admitted that agreeableness is 
not a sufficiently characteristic property of consonance, 
since it is a property which under certain circumstances can 
just as well belong to dissonance. 
Stumpf himself finds the characteristic mark of conson- 
1 Such explanations were attempted by Leibniz and Euler, and have 
been revived in more recent times by Oppel, later by Lipps (Psycho- 
logische Studien, 1885), and finally, in a number of voluminous works, 
by A. J. Polak ( Ueber Zeiteinheit in bezttg aiij Konsonanz, Harmonic 
imd Tonalitat, Leipzig, 1900 ; Ueber Tonrhythmik und Stimmfiihrung, 
Leipzig, 1902 ; Die Harmonisierung indischer, turkischer ^^nd japani- 
scher Melodien, Leipzig, 1905). 
S 
274 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
ance in the fact of two tones when sounded together 
approximating, sometimes more and sometimes less, to the 
impression of a single tone. He defines consonance by 
means of " fusion," harking back, as it were, to views pre- 
valent in antiquity, of which he gives an exhaustive history. 1 
Helmholtz also is not unfamiliar with this theory ; he dis- 
cusses it, but thinks that he has given the first correct 
explanation of the fusion of notes. 
Stumpfs statistical experiments shew that a fusion of 
tones takes place in consonance. If two tones are sounded 
simultaneously, unmusical persons mistake them for a 
single tone with a frequency in proportion to the extent to 
which they are consonant. Stumpf does not attempt to 
conceal the necessity for some further explanation of fusion. 
If it is similarity that causes tones to fuse, then this must 
be a different kind of similarity from that on which the 
sequence of tones in a series depends, since this latter 
similarity decreases continuously with the distance of the 
tones from one another. But since such a second relation 
of similarity appears to him purely hypothetical, he prefers 
to imagine a physiological explanation of a different kind. 
He supposes that, when two tones, of which the rates of 
vibration stand to one another in a comparatively simple 
ratio, are heard simultaneously, the cerebral processes 
which take place are connected by a closer relation of 
specific synergy than when the ratio of the rates of vibration 
is more complicated. 2 Tones that succeed one another 
can fuse. Although polyphonous music is preceded his- 
1 C. Stumpf, " Geschichte des Konsonanzbegiiffes," Abhandlwigen 
der Munchener Akademie^ 1897. 
2 C. Stumpf, Beitriige zur Akustik, Heft I, p. 50. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 275 
torically by homophonous, yet Stumpf considers it probable 
that even in the case of homophonous music the selection 
of the scale was guided by experience of the simultaneous 
hearing of tones. In all essential points it is impossible 
not to agree with Stumpf s criticism. 
I myself, as early as I863, 1 and also later, 2 had made 
some critical remarks on the theory of Helmholtz, and 
in 1866, in a small work 3 which appeared shortly before 
that of Von Oettingen, I very definitely pointed out some 
demands which a more perfect theory of the subject would 
have to satisfy. I developed these remarks in more detail 
in the first edition of this book (1886). 
Let us start from the idea that a . series of definitely 
graduated end-organs exists, the members of which, as the 
rate of vibration increases, successively yield their maximum 
response, and let us ascribe to each end-organ its particular 
(specific) energy. Then there are as many specific energies 
as there are end -organs, and as many rates of vibration 
that we distinguish by the sense of hearing. 
Further, we not only distinguish between tones, but we 
also order them in a series. Of three tones of different 
pitch, we recognize the middle one immediately as such. 
1 Mach, "Zur Theorie des Gehororgans" (Sitztmgsberichte der 
Wiener Akademie, 1863). 
2 Cp. my " Bemerkungen zur Lehre vom raumlichen Sehen" 
(Fichte's Zeitschrift ftir Philosophic, 1865), and see my Popular 
Scientific Lectures. 
3 Einleitung in die Helmholtzsche Musiktheorie, Graz, 1 866. See 
the Preface and pp. 23 et seq., 46 and 48. 
276 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
We feel immediately which rates of vibration lie nearer 
together and which are further apart. This is readily 
enough explained for adjacent tones. For, if we represent 
the vibration-amplitudes of a certain tone symbolically by 
the ordinates of the curve abc. Fig. 35, and imagine this 
curve gradually moved in the direction of the arrow, then, 
since necessarily several organs always yield simultaneous 
responses, neighboring tones will always have faint, common 
excitations. But more distant tones also possess a certain 
similarity ; and even between the highest and lowest tones 
we can detect a resem- 
blance. Consequently, in 
accordance with the prin- 
ciple of investigation by 
which we are guided, we 
are obliged to assume in 
all tone - sensations com- 
** mon component parts. 
Consequently, there can- 
not be as many specific energies as there are distinguishable 
tones. For the understanding of the facts with which we 
are here concerned, it suffices to assume only two energies, 
which are excited in different proportions by different rates o* 
vibration. Further complexity of the sensations of tone is 
not excluded by these facts, but on the contrary is rendered 
probable by phenomena to be discussed later. 
Careful psychological analysis of the tonal series leads 
immediately to this view. But even supposing we assume 
a special energy for every end-organ, and reflect that these 
energies are similar to one another, that is, must contain 
common component parts, virtually we arrive at the same 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 277 
standpoint. Let us therefore assume, merely in order to 
have a definite picture before us, that, in the transition 
from the lowest to the highest rates of vibration, the 
tonal sensation varies similarly to the color-sensation 
in passing from pure red to pure yellow, say by the 
gradual admixture of yellow. We can fully retain, on 
this view, the idea that there is for every distinguishable 
rate of vibration a special appropriate end-organ; but 
in that case not absolutely different energies, but 
always the same two energies, only in different propor- 
tions, are disengaged by the different organs. 1 
10. 
How does it happen, now, that so many tones simul- 
taneously sounded are distinguished, and are not fused into 
a single sensation \ or that two tones of different pitch do 
not blend to a mixed tone of intermediate pitch? The 
fact that this does not happen, lends a still more definite 
shape to the conception which we have to form. The case 
is probably similar to that of a graduated series of mixed 
reds and yellows situated at different points of space, which 
are likewise distinguished and do not blend. And in fact, 
the sensation which ensues when the attention passes from 
one tone to another is similar to that which accompanies 
1 The view that different end-organs respond to different rates of 
vibration is too well supported by the production of beats by neighbor- 
ing tones, and by other facts adduced by Helmholtz, and is too valuable 
for the comprehension of the phenomena, to be again relinquished. 
The view here presented utilizes the facts disclosed, notably by Hering, 
in the analysis of color-sensations. 
278 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
the wandering of the fixation-point in the field of vision. 
The tonal series occurs in something which is an analogue 
of space, but is a space of one dimension limited in both 
directions and exhibiting no symmetry like that, for instance, 
of a straight line running from right to left in a direction 
perpendicular to the median plane. It more resembles a 
vertical right line, or one running from the front to the 
rear in the median plane. But while colors are not con- 
fined to certain points in space, but may move about, 
which is the reason we so easily separate space-sensations 
from color-sensations, the case is different with tone- 
sensations. A particular tone-sensation can occur only 
at a particular point of the said one-dimensional space, on 
which the attention must in each case be fixed if the tone- 
sensation in question is to be distinctly perceived. We 
may now imagine that different tone-sensations have their 
origin in different parts of the auditive substance, or that, 
in addition to the two energies whose ratio determines the 
timbre of high and deep tones, a third exists, which is 
similar to a sensation of innervation, and which comes into 
play in the fixation of tones. Or both conditions might 
occur together. At present it may be regarded as neither 
possible nor necessary to come to a conclusion in the 
matter. 
That the province of tone-sensation offers an analogy to 
space, and to a space having no symmetry, is unconsciously 
expressed in language. We speak of high tones and deep 
tones, not of right tones and left tones, although our musical 
instruments suggest the latter designation as a very natural 
one. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 279 
ii. 
In one of my earliest publications 1 I supported the 
view that the fixation of tones was connected with a 
varying tension of the tensor tympanL I am now unable 
to maintain this view in the light of subsequent observa- 
tions and experiments which I have made. Nevertheless, 
the space-analogy does not fall to the ground for this 
reason ; only the appropriate physiological element remains 
to be discovered. The supposition that the processes in 
the larynx during singing have something to do with the 
formation of the tonal series was likewise noticed by me 
in my work of 1863, but I did not find it tenable. Singing 
is connected with hearing in too extrinsic and accidental 
a manner. I can hear and imagine tones far beyond the 
1 Zur Theorie des Gehororgans, 1863. By means of experiments 
carried out by me in co-operation with Kessel (" Ueber die Akkommo- 
dation des Ohres," Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akademie, Vol. LXVI., 
part 3, October 1872), I obtained a proof of the variable disposition 
and capacity for resonance of the anterior auditory apparatus in the 
case of different tones ; this was done by means of microscopic observa- 
tion of sound- vibrations conducted through a tube. By introducing a 
tube, and making our observations by means of a microscopic ear- 
mirror constructed for the purpose, we tried to detect a similar spon- 
taneous change of disposition in the living ear, but unsuccessfully. I 
have, however, subsequently been inclined to doubt whether the 
powerful vibrations which are observed in this way, would of them- 
selves be decisive of the question, since, unless they were muted, they 
could scarcely penetrate into the labyrinth without doing damage. 
Consequently, as long as the vibrations cannot be observed with 
certainty in a normal living ear, it will scarcely be possible to decide 
this question definitely. A method of light-interference might lead to 
the desired result. But such a method would have to be of particularly 
simple form, if it is to be applicable under the difficult conditions of 
the living ear. 
280 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
range of my own voice. In listening to an orchestral 
performance with all the parts, or in having an hallucination 
of such a performance, it is impossible for me to think 
that my understanding of this broad and complicated sound- 
fabric has been effected by my one larynx, which is, more- 
over, no very practised singer. I consider the sensations 
which, in listening to singing, are doubtless occasionally 
noticed in the larynx, a matter of subsidiary importance, 
like the pictures of the keys touched which, when I was 
more in practice, sprang up immediately into my imagina- 
tion on hearing a performance on the piano or organ. 
When I imagine music, I always distinctly hear the notes. 
Music can no more come into being merely through the 
motor sensations accompanying musical performances, 
than a deaf man can hear the music by watching the 
movements of players. I cannot therefore, agree with 
Strieker on this point. (Cp. Strieker, Du langage et de la 
musique, Paris, 1885). 
Different is my opinion with regard to Strieker's views on 
language. (Cp. Strieker, Die Sprachvorstellungen, Vienna, 
1880.) It is true that in my own case words of which 
I think reverberate loudly in my ear. Moreover, I have 
no doubt that thoughts may be directly excited by the 
ringing of a housebell, by the whistle of a locomotive, etc., 
and that small children and even dogs understand words 
which they cannot repeat. Nevertheless, I have been 
convinced by Strieker that the ordinary and most familiar, 
though not the only possible way by which speech is 
comprehended, is really motor, and that we should be 
badly off if we were without it. I can cite corroborations 
of this view from my own experience. I frequently see 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 281 
strangers who are endeavoring to follow my remarks 
slightly moving their lips. If a person tells me his 
place of residence and I omit to repeat the street 
and number of the house after him, I am certain to 
forget the address, but with the exercise of this 
precautionary measure, I retain it perfectly in memory. 
A friend told me recently that he would not read 
the Indian drama Urvasi, because he had great diffi- 
culty in spelling out the names, and consequently 
could not retain them in memory. The dream of 
the deaf-mute, which Strieker relates, is intelligible 
only from his point of view. In fact, on calm 
reflexion this seemingly paradoxical relation is by no 
means so remarkable. The extent to which our thoughts 
move in accustomed and routine channels is shewn 
by the surprise produced by witticisms. Good jokes 
would be more frequent if our minds moved less in 
ruts. To many the obvious collateral meanings of 
words never suggest themselves. Who, for example, 
in using the names Smith, Baker, or Taylor thinks of 
the occupations designated ! To adduce an analogous 
example from a different field, I may state (cp. p. in) 
that I immediately recognize writing reflected in a 
mirror and accompanying its original, as symmetrically 
congruent with the latter, although I am not able 
to read it directly, because of my having learned 
writing by motor methods, with my right hand. 
I can also best illustrate by this example why I do not 
agree with Strieker in regard to music : music is related 
to speech as ornament is to writing. 
282 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
12. 
I have repeatedly illustrated by experiments, which I 
will cite again here, the analogy between fixing the eyes 
on points in space and fixing the attention on tones. one 
and the same combination of two tones sounds different 
according as we fix our attention upon the one or the other. 
Combinations i and 2 in the annexed cut have a perceptibly 
different character according as we fix our attention on the 
higher or on the lower note. Persons not able to transfer 
their attention at will will be helped by having one note 
sounded later than the other (3, 4). The one sounded last 
then draws the attention after it. With a little practice it 
is possible to decompose a chord (as, for instance, 5) into 
its elements and to hear the constituent tones by themselves 
(as in 6). These and the following experiments are better 
and more convincingly carried out upon a physharmonica, 
on which the notes can be held, than on a piano. 
Especially astonishing is the phenomenon produced when 
.we cause one note of a chord, on which the attention is 
fixed, to be damped. The attention then passes over to 
one of the notes nearest to it, which comes out with the 
distinctness of a note that has just been struck. The 
impression made by the experiment is quite similar to that 
which we receive when, absorbed in work, we suddenly 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 283 
hear the regular striking of the clock emerge into distinct- 
ness after having entirely vanished from consciousness. In 
the latter case the entire tonal effect passes the threshold of 
consciousness, whilst in the former a part is augmented. If 
in 7, for example, we fix the attention upon the upper note, 
s 
r j~*7 ' 
Fl H 
pi H 
~P^ 
1 
4 
I 
A 
' X 
p t ^ ' 
letting go, successively from above, the keys damping the 
other notes, the effect obtained is approximately that of 8. 
If, in 9, we fix the attention on the lowest note, and proceed 
in the reverse order, we obtain the impression represented 
in 10. The same chordal sequence sounds quite different 
according to the part on which the attention is fixed. If, 
in 1 1 or 1 2, I fix my attention on the upper note, the timbre 
3 
12 
ry * \\ i 
NHr-^- ^^ 
alone appears to be altered. But if, in II, the attention be 
fixed upon the bass, the entire acoustic mass will seem to 
sink in depth ; while in 1 2 it will appear to rise if we regard 
closely the succession e-f. This makes it quite evident, in 
fine, that chords act the part of clangs (or compound notes 
embracing both fundamentals and harmonics). The facts 
284 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
here advanced remind us strongly of the changing impres- 
sion received when, in observing an ornamental design, the 
attention is alternately fixed on different points. 
We may also recall to mind here the involuntary wander- 
ing of the attention which takes place during the continuous 
and uniform sounding of a note on the harmonium, where 
if the note lasts several minutes, all the overtones will of 
themselves successively emerge into full distinctness. 1 The 
process appears to point to a sort of fatigue for the note on 
which the attention has long been fixed. This fatigue, 
moreover, is rendered quite probable by an experiment 
which I have described at length in another place. 2 
The relations in the sphere of tone-sensation, which 
I we have here been describing, might be 
illustrated perhaps more palpably by some 
such parallel as the following. Suppose 
that our two eyes were capable of only a 
single movement, and that they could only 
follow, by changing motions of symmetrical 
convergence, the points of a horizontal 
straight line lying in the median plane ; and 
suppose that the nearest point on this line 
Fig. 36. 
fixed by the eyes were pure red, and the 
point farthest away, corresponding to the position of 
parallelism, were pure yellow, while between them lay all 
intermediate shades ; then the system of sight-sensations 
so constructed would quite palpably resemble the relations 
of the sensations of tone. 
1 Cp. my Einleitung in die Helmholtzsche Musiktheorie, p. 29. 
2 Cp. my Grundlinien der Lehre von den Bewegiingsempfindtingen^ 
p. 58. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 285 

on the view hitherto developed, an important fact, which 
we shall now consider, remains unintelligible, though its 
explanation is absolutely necessary if the theory is to lay 
any claim to completeness. If two series of tones be begun 
at two different points on the scale, but be made to main- 
tain throughout the same ratios of vibration, we recognize 
in both the same melody, by a mere act of sensation, just 
as readily and immediately as we recognize in two geome- 
trically similar figures, similarly situated, the same form. 
Like melodies, differently situated on the scale, may be 
termed tonal constructs of like tonal form, or they may be 
termed similar tonal constructs. It is easy to convince 
oneself that this recognition is not connected exclusively 
with the employment of ordinary musical intervals or of any 
comparatively simple ratio of vibration-numbers in common 
use. If the open strings of a violin, or of any other instru- 
ment with more than one string, be "tuned to any discon- 
nected notes we please, and a strip of paper, divided up 
into any complicated series of ratios, be fastened to the 
finger-board, we can play the notes indicated in any order 
(or slide from one to the other), first on one string and 
then on the others. Now although the resultant sound 
may have no sense as music, we can recognize the melody 
as the same on each string. The experiment would not 
be any more convincing, if we deliberately divided the 
finger-board into irrational intervals. Indeed in practice 
the result would be only approximate. The musician could 
still maintain that he heard intervals that were approximate 
or intermediate to the familiar musical intervals. Untrained 
286 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
song-birds use the musical intervals only in exceptional 
cases. 
Even in a series of only two tones, the sameness of the 
ratios of vibration is at once recognized. Thus in the 
series c-f, d-g, e-a, etc., the notes which have all the same 
ratios of vibration (3 : 4), are immediately recognized as 
like intervals, as fourths. Such is the fact, in its simplest 
form. The ability to pick out and recognize intervals is 
the first thing required of the student of music who is 
desirous of becoming thoroughly familiar with his subject. 
In a little work, 1 well worth reading, by E. Kulke, mention 
is made, bearing on this point, of an original method of 
instruction by P. Cornelius a notice which I will now 
supplement by the following communication made to me 
orally by Kulke himself. According to Cornelius, it is a 
great help in the recognition of intervals to make note of 
particular pieces of music, folk-songs, etc., which begin 
with these intervals. The overture to TannMuser, for 
example, begins with a fourth. If I hear a fourth I at once 
remark that the tone-sequence might be the beginning of 
the overture to Tannhauser, and by this means I recognize 
the interval. In like manner, the overture to Fidelia 
(No. i) may be used as the representative of the third ; and 
so on. This excellent device, which I have put to the test 
in my lectures on acoustics and have found very effective, 
apparently complicates matters. one would naturally 
suppose that it would be easier to make note of an interval 
than of a melody. Nevertheless, a melody offers a greater 
hold to memory than does an interval, just as an individual 
1 E. Kulke, Ueber die Umbildung der Melodic. Ein Beitrag zur 
Entwicklungslehre, Prague, Calve, 1884. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 287 
countenance is more easily remarked and associated with a 
name than is a certain facial angle or a nose. Every one 
makes note of faces and associates with them names ; but 
Leonardo da Vinci arranged noses in a system. 
14. 
Just as every interval in a sequence of tones is made per- 
ceptible in a characteristic manner, so it is with the harmonic 
combinations of tones. Every third, every fourth, every 
major or minor triad has its characteristic color, by which it 
is recognized independently of the pitch of the fundamental, 
and independently of the number of beats, which rapidly 
increases with increasing pitch. 
A tuning-fork held before one ear is very feebly heard by 
the other ear. If two slightly discordant, beating tuning- 
forks are held in front of the same ear, the beats are very 
distinct. But if one of the forks be placed before one ear, 
and the other before the other, the beats will be greatly 
weakened. Two forks of harmonic interval always sound 
slightly rougher before one ear. But the character of the 
harmony is preserved when one is placed before each ear. 1 
The discord also remains quite perceptible in this experi- 
ment. Harmony and discord are, however, not determined 
by beats alone. 
In melodic as well as in harmonic combinations, notes 
whose rates of vibrations bear to one another some simple 
ratio, are distinguished (i) by their agreeableness, and (2) 
by a sensation characteristic of this ratio. As for the 
1 Cp. Fechner, Ueber einige Verhtiltnisse des binocularen Se/iens, 
Leipzig, 1860, p. 536. I have myself often tried such experiments. 
288 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
agreeable quality, there is no denying that this is partly 
explained by the coincidence of the overtones, and, in the 
case of harmonic combination, by the consequent efface- 
ment of the beats, resulting always where the ratios of the 
numbers representing the vibrations satisfy certain definite 
conditions. But the experienced and unprejudiced student 
of music is not entirely satisfied with this explanation. He 
is disturbed by the preponderant r61e accorded to the 
accident of acoustic color, and notices that tones further 
stand to each other in a positive relation of contrast, like 
colors, except that, in the case of colors, no such definite 
agreeable relations can be specified. 
The fact that a sort of contrast really does exist among 
tones almost forces itself upon our notice. A smooth, un- 
changing tone is something very unpleasing and colorless, 
like a single uniform color enveloping our entire surround- 
ings. A lively effect is produced only on the addition of 
a second tone, a second color. In like manner, if we 
cause a tone gradually to mount in pitch, as in experiments 
with the siren, all contrast is lost. Contrast exists, how- 
ever, between tones farther apart, and not merely between 
those immediately following one another, as the accompany- 
ing example will shew. Passage 2 sounds quite different 
after i from what it does alone, 3 sounds different 
from 2, and even 5 different from 4 immediately 
following 3. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 289 
16. 
Let us turn now to the second point, the characteristic 
sensation corresponding to each interval, and ask if this 
can be explained on our present theory. If a fundamental 
n be melodically or harmonically combined with its third 
m, the fifth harmonic of the first note (5^) will coincide 
i 
C c g c e g b-flat c 
n zn 3 4 5* 6n 7* 8n 
e b e g-sharp b d 
zm yn qm yn 6fft jtn 
t = = = 
F f c f a c e-flat f 
n 2 3 4 5 () 7 8 
t = = = = 
A a e a c-sharp e g a 
m -im yn ^m $m bnt -jm 8f 
with the fourth of the second note (40*). This, according 
to the theory of Helmholtz, is the common feature char- 
acterizing all third combinations. If I combine the 
notes Cand E, or F and A, representing their harmonics 
in the above table, then, as a fact, in the one case the 
harmonics marked ] and in the other those marked j 
coincide ; and in both cases the coincidence is between 
the fifth harmonic of the lower and the fourth harmonic of 
the higher note. Be it noted, however, that this common 
feature exists solely for the understanding, being the result 
2go THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
of a purely physical and intellectual analysis, and has 
nothing to do with sensation. For sensation the real 
coincidence in the first case is between the e's, and in the 
second between the a's, which are entirely different notes. 
on the assumption that there exists for every distinguish- 
able rate of vibration an appropriate specific energy, we 
are obliged, more than on any other theory, to ask where 
is the common component of sensation hidden that 
characterizes every third combination ? 
I must insist on this distinction of mine not being re- 
garded as a piece of pedantic hair-splitting. I propounded 
the question involving it about twenty years ago, at the same 
time with my question as to wherein physiological similarity 
of form, as distinguished from geometrical, consisted ; and 
the former is not a whit more unnecessary than was the latter, 
of which the superfluity, too, in the issue, was disproved. If 
we are to allow a physical or mathematical characteristic of 
the tierce-interval to stand as a mark of the tierce-sensation, 
then we should content ourselves, as Euler did, 1 with the 
coincidence of every fourth and fifth vibration a concep- 
tion which was, after all, not so bad, as long as it could be 
believed that sound continued its course in the nerve-tracts, 
also, as periodic motion, a view which even A. Seebeck 2 
1 Euler, Tentamen novce theories musicce^ Petropoli, 1739, p. 36. 
2 I cannot understand how any one can still maintain the theory of 
the temporal coincidence of impulses. At one time I replaced A. 
Seebeck's experiment by what I believe to be a better procedure 
(" Ueber einige der physiologischen Akustik angehorige Erscheinun- 
gen," Berichte der Wiener Akademie, 26th June 1864), but I never could 
detect any periodicity in the nerve-process connected with sensation. 
At that time it was not known that beats are never observed between 
a subjective tone and an adjacent objective tone, or between subjective 
ones ; but the fact cannot now be doubted. Cp. Stumpf's interesting 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 291 
(Pogg. Ann., Vol. LXVIII.) regarded as possible. With 
regard to this particular point, Helmholtz's coincidence of 
5 and $m is in no respect less symbolical and does not 
offer greater enlightenment. 
So far I have presented my arguments with the convic- 
tion that I should not find it necessary to make a single 
retrograde step of importance. This feeling does not accom- 
pany me in the same measure in the development of the 
following hypothesis, which, in all its essential features, 
was suggested to me a long time ago. Yet the hypothesis 
may at least serve to clear up and illustrate, from the 
positive side also, the requirement which I believe a more 
complete theory of tone-sensations is bound to meet. I 
will first expound my view in the form in which it appeared 
in the first edition of this book. 
Let us suppose that it is an extremely important vital 
condition for an animal of simple organization to perceive 
slight periodic motions of the medium in which it lives. 
If (owing to the relatively excessive size of its organs, and 
its consequent lack of receptivity for such rapid changes) 
paper on " Beobachtungen liber subjective Tone und tiber Doppelt- 
horen " (Zeitschrift fur Psychologic und Physiologic der Sinnesorgane, 
Vol. XXL, pp. 100-121). The subjective tones that arise in my ear 
generally last too short a time for me to experiment with them. Still 
I did succeed not long ago (1906) in getting to the piano with a very 
clear and constant c-sharp, and convincing myself that when a c-sharp 
a shade deeper was lightly struck on the piano, no beats were demon- 
strable. For me, indeed, this demonstration was superfluous, for I 
hold the opposite supposition to be physiologically inadmissible. But 
Stumpf s observations on the consonance and dissonance of subjective 
tones without beats are very important. 
292 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
change of attention is too sluggish, and the period of the 
oscillations is too short, or their amplitude too small, to 
permit the single phases of the excitation to enter con- 
sciousness, it may nevertheless be possible under certain 
conditions for the animal to perceive the accumulated sensa- 
tion-effects of the oscillatory stimulus. The organ of hear- 
ing will outstrip the organ of touch. 1 Now an end-organ 
capable of vibration (say an auditory cilium) responds, by 
virtue of its physical qualities, not to every rate of vibration, 
nor to one only, but ordinarily to several, at a considerable 
distance apart. 2 Therefore, as soon as the whole continuum 
of rates of vibration between certain limits becomes of 
importance for the animal, a small number of end organs 
no longer suffices, but the need of a whole series of such 
organs of graduated capacity arises. At first the organ of 
Corti and the basilar membrane were regarded by Helmholtz 
as such a system. 
It can hardly be expected, however, that a member of 
such a system will respond to only one rate of vibration. 
on the contrary, we should expect that it would respond 
with enfeebled but graduated intensity (perhaps from being 
divided by nodes) to the rates of vibration 2n, 3^, 4, etc., 
as also'^to the rates of vibration /2, /3, /4, etc. Inasmuch 
1 It is questionable therefore whether animals which have so small a 
measure of time that their voluntary movements produce a musical note 
hear in the ordinary sense, or whether with them it is not rather 
touch which makes on us the impression of hearing. Cp., for example, 
the admirable experiments and observations of V. Graber (" Die 
Chordotonalen Organe," Arch, fur Microskop. Anat., XX., p. 506). 
Cp. also my Beuoegungsempfindungen, p. 123. This conjecture has 
subsequently been confirmed in many ways. See Pop-ii lar-wis sen- 
se haft liche Vorlesitngen, 3rd ed., p. 401. 
2 As V. Hensen, for example, has observed. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 293 
as the assumption of a special energy for each rate of 
vibration has proved untenable, we may imagine, agreeably 
to what has been said above, that in the first place, only two 
sensation-energies, say, Dull (D) and Clear (C), are excited. 
The resultant sensation we will represent symbolically 
(somewhat as we do in mixed colors) by pD + qC ; or, 
making / + ^ = i and regarding q as a function f(n) of the 
rate of vibration, 1 by [T -f(n)} D+f(n) C. The sensation 
arising will now correspond to the number of the vibrations 
of the oscillatory stimulus, to whatever member of the series 
of end-organs the stimulus may be applied. And con- 
sequently our earlier view will not be materially disturbed 
by the new hypothesis. For, since the member n responds 
most powerfully to n, and only in a much more enfeebled 
degree to 2#, $n, or to n/2, n/$, R n vibrating with n even 
in case of an aperiodic impulse, therefore the sensation 
[i -/()] D+f(n) C will still be predominantly associated 
with . 
Well-attested cases of double hearing (cp. Stumpf, loc. 
tit., p. 266 et seq.) point forcibly to the conclusion that 
the ratios in which D and C are disengaged are dependent 
upon the end-organ, and not upon the rate of vibration 
a conclusion which would also not affect our theory. 
A member R n , accordingly, responds powerfully to #, 
and also, though more weakly, to 2, 3^, .... n/2, 
n/3 .... with the sensations belonging to these rates of 
vibration. It is, however, extremely improbable that exactly 
the same sensation is excited whether R n responds to n, or 
whether R n responds to . on the contrary, it is probable 
that every time the members of the series of organs respond 
1 Thus, to take a very simple example, we might make /() k. log. . 
294 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
to a partial tone, the sensation receives a weak supple- 
mentary coloring, which we will represent symbolically, for 
the fundamental tone by Z 1? for the overtones by Z 2 , Z 3 , 
. . . ., and for the undertones by Z^ Zi, . . . . on this 
supposition, sensations of tone would be somewhat richer in 
composition than would follow from the formula [i -f(n)] D 
+ f( n ) The sensations which the series of end-organs, 
as excited by the fundamentals, yields, constitute a province 
with the supplementary coloring Z v the excitation of the 
same series by the first overtone yields a special province 
of sensation with the supplementary coloring Z 2 , etc. The 
Z's may be either unchanging elements, or may themselves, 
again, consist of two components, U and F, and form series 
representable by [i -/()] U+f(n) F. But at present the 
decision on this last point is immaterial. 
It is true that the physiological elements Z 15 Z 2 , . . . . 
have yet to be found. Yet the very perception that they 
have to be sought seems to me of importance. Let us see 
what form the province of tone-sensations would take on 
if we regarded Zj, Z 2 , .... as given. 
We will take as example a melodic or harmonic major- 
third combination, whose rates of vibration are n = ^p 
and m = $p; the lowest of the overtones common to the 
two is 5 = 4m = 20^, the highest of the undertones common 
to the two is p. Then we obtain the table on the 
following page. 
Thus in the third combination, the supplementary sensa- 
tions Z 4 , Z 5 , and Z^ Zi, which are characteristic of the 
third, make their appearance even when the notes contain 
no overtones, while the former (Z 4 , Z 5 ) are strengthened 
when, either in the open air or at least in the ear, over- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 295 
tones do occur. The diagram may be easily generalized 
to include any interval. 1 
These supplementary colorings, though scarcely notice- 
able in single tones, or in running continuously through 
the scale, will accordingly become conspicuous in combina- 
tions of tones having certain ratios of rate of vibration, 
The members of 
the series of end- 
RP 
R$p 
R$p 
Rzop 
organs : 
-a c 
S| 
respond to the rates 
of vibration ; 
4A5/ 
4* 
5/ 
*a* 
1L 
4 
SS-5 4 
M 
with the supple- 
d w 
mentary sensa- 
Zi, Z & 
z\ 
z l 
Z!,Z, 
|- S 
tions : 
*i 
they also respond 
g 
to the rates of vi- 
20/> ~5(4/) 
20/ = 4(5^) 
| 
bration : 
*^rf 
with the supple- 
g" S 
mentary sensa- 
^ 5 
Zi 
gS, 
tions ; 
just as the contrasts of faintly colored, almost white lights 
become vivid when such lights are brought together. And, 
1 The above exposition will be found in a rather conciser and slightly 
different form in my note "Zur Analyse der Tonempfindungen " 
(Sitzungsberichte der Wiener Akademie, December 1885), where I 
have tried to analyse sensations of tone on the analogy of sensations 
of color, of which the analysis has been carried very much further. 
Every vibration-number disengages a few specific energies in a ratio 
which depends on the vibration-number in question, The excitability 
of these energies is different at different points on the retina. Analogous 
relations are assumed mutatis imitandis for sensations of tone. It 
296 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
furthermore, the same contrast-colorings always correspond 
to the same ratios of rate of vibration, no matter what the 
pitch. 
In this manner it is intelligible how tones may receive, 
by melodic and harmonic combination with others, the 
most varied colorings, which are wanting to them when 
singly sounded. 
The elements Z lt Z 2 . . . must not be conceived as 
unvarying and fixed in number. on the contrary, it is 
to be supposed that the number of perceptible Z's depends 
on the organization, on the training of the ear, and on the" 
attention. According to this conception, the ear does not 
directly cognize ratios of rate of vibration but only the 
supplementary colorings conditioned by these ratios. The 
tonal series symbolically represented by [i -f(n)]D +f(n} C 
is not infinite but limited. Since / (n) may vary between 
the values o and i, D and C, where they are the sensations 
corresponding to the lowest and highest tones, are the 
end-terms of the series. If the number of vibrations 
sinks considerably below or rises considerably above that 
of the fundamental of the extreme term of the series, a 
weak response only will take place, but no alteration of 
the quality of the sensation. Further, the sensation of 
the intervals must disappear in the neighborhood of the 
seemed originally that in both cases there must be an infinite variety 
of sensations corresponding to the infinite variety of the physical 
stimulus. But in both cases psychological analysis leads to the con- 
clusion that a smaller number of sensations is to be assumed, and that, 
on the principle of parallelism, we have to think of these sensations, 
not as immediately dependent on the complicated physical stimulus, 
but as immediately dependent on the psycho-physical process which is 
as simple as they are themselves. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 297 
two limits of hearing ; first, because, in general, differences 
between sensations of tone cease at this point, and, secondly, 
because at the upper limit the members of the series 
capable of being excited by the undertones are lacking, 
while at the lower limit those which react on the overtones 
are lacking. 
Passing in review again the position at which we have 
arrived, we see that with few exceptions the conclusions 
reached by Helmholtz may be all retained. Noises and 
composite sounds may be decomposed into musical tones. 
To every distinguishable rate of vibration there corre- 
sponds a particular nervous end-organ. In place of the 
numerous specific energies required by this theory, how- 
ever, we substitute two only, which render the relationship 
of all tonal sensations intelligible, and which, by the role 
which we assign to the attention, likewise enable us to 
keep perceptually distinct, several tones when sounded 
together. By the hypothesis of the multiple response of 
the members of the series of end-organs, and by that of 
supplementary acoustic colorings, the significance of 
accidental acoustic color is diminished, and we get a 
glimpse of the direction in which, notably on the ground 
of musical facts, the positive characteristics of intervals 
are to be further investigated. Finally, the latter con- 
ception supplies Von Oettingen's principle of duality 
with a foundation which might perhaps commend 
itself to this investigator himself as preferable to his 
assumption of "memory"; while at the same time it 
becomes manifest why the duality cannot be a perfect 
symmetry. 
298 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
18. 
I have expressly described the theory of the multiple 
response of the series of end-organs, as well as the theory 
of supplementary colorings, as a "hypothesis," and I have 
put forward this hypothesis merely with the object of 
illustrating the meaning of the postulates resulting from 
psychological analysis, and of perhaps stimulating others 
to a more successful attack on the problem. I am there- 
fore not surprised to find that other writers do not agree 
unreservedly with my attempt. But that this hypothesis is, 
as Stumpf says, 1 useless and quite unsuited to its purpose, 
I cannot admit. The coincidence of the supplementary 
colorings Z 4 , Z 5 , or Z t Zj, in one and the same nerve, is 
not merely a physical, but also a psycho-physical fact. It 
can scarcely be a matter of indifference that the sensation 
of a mixed coloring is determined by a single element. on 
the contrary, it seems to me that what I am looking for, 
namely an explanation of the definite coloring of the 
intervals, and also what Stumpf is looking for, namely 
an explanation of fusion, would actually be represented 
by the partial coincidence which I assume, even without 
overtones. - Stumpf s further assertion that, in the case of 
notes with overtones, there is no difficulty in understanding, 
on Helmholtz's theory, the similarity of like intervals, rests 
upon a misapprehension of my criticism of Helmholtz. 
It will satisfy no one to be told that overtones of equal 
strength coincide in the case of two tierces, since what is 
in question is the qualitative similarity of the sensations. 
1 C. Stumpf, Beitrage z^^r Akustik imd Musikwissenschaft^ Heft I, 
pp. 17, 18. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 299 
If the recognition of a melodic tierce-interval were imme- 
diately intelligible, it would of course be unnecessary to 
look for any special explanation of why we recognize the 
harmonic combination of tierces. But inasmuch as Stumpf 
himself holds that the melodic steps are characterized by 
the harmonic combination, this view would involve a vicious 
circle. on my theory also, the fact of melodic and harmonic 
selection of definite ratios of vibration-numbers leads to the 
same problem. My hypothesis inclines towards the theory 
of resonance, and according to Stumpf is to be rejected 
on that very account. I will presently deal more particu- 
larly with this last point. 
19. 
There has been much discussion of the physical pro- 
cesses involved in audition, and, in particular, of the 
function of the parts of the middle ear. In spite of this, 
it would seem that an unprejudiced revision of the physical 
theory of audition is urgently needed. The question has 
been raised whether the auditory ossicles vibrate as a 
whole, or whether the sound-waves pass through them. 
E. H. Weber decides in favor of the former view, which 
has been experimentally confirmed by Politzer, while I 
was probably the first to establish it on a theoretical basis. 1 
For if the dimensions of the ossicles in comparison with 
the length of the sound-waves in question are, as regards 
their material, very small (as is actually the case), there 
can be no doubt that practically the same phases of move- 
1 Mach, " Zur Theorie des Gehororgans," Sitzungsberichte der Wiener 
Akademie, Vol. LVIIL, July 1863. Also Helmholtz, Die Mechanik 
der Gehorknochelchen, 1869. 
300 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
ment occur throughout the whole extent of the ossicles, 
and that consequently they must move as a whole. It 
has occurred to some inquirers to transfer the movements 
of the ossicles to the fluid of the labyrinth. But patho- 
logical investigations teach us that, even without the 
co-operation of the ossicles and the membrana tympani, 
the hearing may remain quite good, provided that the 
labyrinth is in order. The ossicles and tympanum seem 
only to be important when what is in question is the trans- 
ference to the labyrinth of very faint movements of the 
air ; in that case the reduction of the pressure falling upon 
the whole surface of the membrana tympani to the small 
stirrup-footplate seems to be necessary. Otherwise, sound- 
waves can be carried to the labyrinth by way of the cranial 
bones also. If sounding bodies, such as tuning-forks, are 
placed on different parts of the head, it can be shewn that 
the direction of the sound-waves that penetrate into the 
labyrinth does not play any important part. Again, all 
dimensions of the sound-perceiving apparatus are so small 
in comparison with the audible soundwaves, and the 
velocity of sound in the bones and the labyrinthine fluid 
is so great, that the whole extent of the labyrinth only 
contains room for one perceptible wave-phase at any one 
moment. The result of all this is, that it is not the move- 
ments and the direction of movement, but the variations 
of pressure which arise in the labyrinth almost synchron- 
ously, that are to be regarded as the decisive stimulus that 
excites sensation. 
Nevertheless let us consider the movement which can be 
set up in the labyrinth by the movements of the stirrup- 
plate. We may first imagine all the soft parts to be taken 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 301 
out, and the whole space bounded by the osseous wall to 
contain nothing but fluid. The movement that can find 
room here is a periodical current passing from the oval to 
the round window and vice versa, the form of which, since 
the velocity of the disturbance vanishes in proportion to the 
velocity of the sound, will be almost entirely independent 
of the period. If the surfaces of the two windows are con- 
ceived as positive and negative electrodes, and as conducting 
the fluid, then the lines of the electric current will coincide 
with the lines of the periodic current. Now this state of 
things will not suffer any substantial change, if the difference 
between the specific weight of the soft parts and that of the 
fluid in which they are immersed is very small. It is the 
mass of the fluid that is of predominant importance. The 
fact that particular constructions can', according to the pitch, 
take on a special local state of vibration in spite of the fluid, 
need scarcely be discussed. The quantitative relations are 
here quite different from what they are in the case of strings 
or membranes in air. 
Consequently, Ewald's new theory of audition 1 is, in my 
opinion, no more tenable than the theory of Helmholtz as 
to the fibres of Corti and the elective vibrations of the 
basilar membrane. If in Ewald's experiments a membrane 
coated with oil shews, when the coat is comparatively thick, 
no clear divisions any longer, it would completely fail to 
shew any if it were immersed in a fluid, much more if the 
dimensions were proportionately reduced. We must, how- 
ever, insist that Ewald's theory is otherwise appropriate in 
many respects, and that it would offer many advantages. 
For instance, in the case of harmonic intervals, even when 
1 Ewald, Eine neue Hortheorie^ Bonn, 1899. 
302 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
overtones are absent, the membranes display coincidences 
of the node-lines. Thus this theory seems to fulfil a part 
of the above mentioned postulates. Unfortunately it is 
physically inadmissible, quite apart from further difficulties 
which it is also unable to solve. I need scarcely say that I 
do not presume to dismiss so admirable and laborious a 
piece of work in a few words, but at the same time I cannot 
refrain from stating my objections to it. 
Shortly after the publication of the fourth edition of this 
book, which contained the foregoing passages expressing my 
doubts as to the vibration of membranes in fluids, Ewald 
published his experiments with the camera acustica. 1 He 
immersed in water a delicate membrane, of about the 
dimensions of the basilar membrane, and succeeded in 
acoustically setting up in it continuous vibrations with clear 
nodal divisions corresponding to the pitch. This shewed 
that my conjecture was wrong, and gave me cause to reflect 
in what point I had been mistaken. I then remembered 
the very small nodal divisions which, years before, I had 
myself observed in fluid membranes. 2 I also recalled 
Friesach's experiments with strings immersed in water, 3 the 
result of which had been to shew that immersion in water 
acts as an enlargement of the string's mass, since the fluid 
in the immediate neighborhood of the string accompanies 
its vibrations, moving synchronously to and fro in extremely 
short paths. It is therefore quite conceivable that the 
labyrinthine fluid vibrates to and fro as a whole, and that 
1 Ewald, Pfliiger's Archiv, 1903, Vol. XCIII., p. 485. 
2 Optisch-akustische Versuche, Prague, 1872, p. 93, 
3 Friesach, Berichte der Wiener Akademie^ 1867, Vol. LVL, 2nd 
part, p. 316. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 303 
nevertheless the velocity of propagation in the membrane, 
which is very much smaller, appears in the labyrinthine 
fluid in the form of stable vibrations of the membrane. If 
the existence of such vibrations of the membrane is proved, 
Ewald's theories gain greatly in value. I should like, 
further, to refer here to two papers by Stohr which seem to 
me to contain the germs of ideas which would repay 
development. 1 
20. 
The difficulty of setting the theory of resonance on a 
sound physical basis has probably, as it seems to me, been 
felt by everyone who has studied it, and not least acutely 
by its originators. But at the same time it was recognized 
that, if it was given up, the key to the problem of the 
analysis of sounds and to a clear and simple doctrine of 
tone-sensations would be lost. Hence the frantic attempts 
to save the theory of resonance. L. Hermann 2 seems to 
me to speak very much to the point, when he says that 
we cannot do without some sort of theory of resonance, but 
that this need not necessarily be a physical theory, but may 
also be a physiological theory. We may make, with him, 
the plausible assumption that the nervous organs per se 
1 Stohr, " Ueber Unterbrechungstone," Deutsche Revile, July, 1904. 
Mach and Kessel some time ago pointed out the necessity of attacking 
the problems of acoustics from the point of view of asymmetry ; see 
"Die Funktion der Trommelhohle," Berichte der Wiener Akademie, 
Vol. LXVI., 3rd part, 1872; Stohr, " Klangfarbe oder Tonfarbe," 
SUdde^^tsche Monalshefte, Munich and Leipzig, July 1904. In this 
paper Stohr is aiming, though by a different route, at a goal not far 
removed from my own. 
2 Hermann, Pfliiger's Archiv, Vol. LVL, pp. 494 sqq., 1894. 
304 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
are peculiarly sensitive to stimuli with a definite period. 1 
It cannot exactly be elastic forces that impel the organ 
back to its position of equilibrium, but we may think of a 
state of equilibrium which is of an electrical or chemical 
nature, the deviations from it standing to one another in 
the relation of the positive to the negative sign. And 
further, there may be a connexion between these organs, 
by means of which one can act as a stimulus upon another. 
In this way a reasonable prospect seems to be opened up 
of making up for the loss of the physical theory. I cannot 
here attempt to reproduce Hermann's arguments com- 
pletely and accurately, but must content myself with 
referring the reader to his paper. 

one point, however, we may consider more closely. 
When two wave-shaped pendular vibrations with vibration- 
numbers , ', co-operate, there then arise beats which 
may be regarded as a rising and sinking of the tone, n or 
n' (n' ri) times a second. But it is never possible to 
regard the movement of the air as such a movement as 
could contain the wave-vibration, that is to say, the tone 
n' - n. Fven a physical resonator with the vibration- 
number n' - n can never be excited by such beats, whether 
they are fast or slow. Indeed, it is easy to see, when one 
imagines or draws the course of the beats, that in the long 
run precisely as many and as strong positive and negative 
impulses must take place as there are vibrations (#' - n) of 
the resonator. In the first half of the time, also, the 
impulses are equal to and of the same direction as the 
1 Perhaps this assumption would still remain valuable if it also suc- 
ceeded in providing a basis for a satisfactory physical theory of 
resonance. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 305 
impulses in the second half. An effectual summation is 
therefore excluded. It would only be possible if the 
resonator could be made more receptive of one kind of 
impulse than of the other, and more receptive in the first 
half of the duration of its vibration. We can easily see 
how this way of considering the matter involves the re- 
jection of Young's explanation of combination tones by 
means of rapid beats, and leads, on the other hand, to 
Helmholtz's theory of combination tones, while preserving 
the theory of resonance. It would seem, however, that 
the physical relations which Helmholtz had to assume do 
not exist in the circumstances under which combination 
tones are heard. But it is quite conceivable that a nervous 
organ should be unequally receptive of opposite impulses, 
and likewise should be receptive in different degrees at 
different stages of its excitation. For an organ does not 
simply follow the forces that act upon it, but contains a 
store of energy upon which those forces only act by liberat- 
ing the energy. In this way Young's mistake, and the 
presumably unsuccessful attempt of Helmholtz to improve 
on Young's theory, will have led to an important new point 
of view. 
21. 
The theory of Helmholtz as to tone-sensations seemed, 
when it was first promulgated, to be an admirably complete 
and classical achievement. Yet, on a fundamental exami- 
nation, it has not been able to stand against criticism. 
And this criticism was in no sense captious, as is suffi- 
ciently evident from the fact that the attacks of the different 
critics, in spite of all individual peculiarities, were directed 
306 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
against the same points and took the same direction. The 
result of all this criticism seems to be that the main problem 
has been put back almost to the point at which it stood 
before Helmholtz wrote. The effect of this might be 
tragic, if it were ever legitimate to look at the matter from 
the point of view of a single person. 
But the achievement of Helmholtz, open to attack 
though it may be on certain sides, must not be underrated. 
His work, apart from the positive increase of knowledge 
which we owe to it, has brought life and movement into 
the whole question ; it has encouraged inquirers to make 
new experiments, and has provided the stimulus for a mass 
of new investigations ; new prospects have been opened up, 
and possible ways of going wrong have been definitely 
closed for ever. New experiments and criticisms are 
made all the easier by the existence of some positive work 
from which to take their start. 
In thinking that a task, which provides ample work for 
psychologists and physiologists as well as for physicists, 
could be mastered, in all its main features, from physical 
points of view, Helmholtz was doubtless under a delusion. 
Even those friends and contemporaries of his who, about 
the middle of the last century, founded the physical school 
of physiology in co-operation with him, have had to recog- 
nize that the fragment of inorganic physics which we have 
conquered, is far from being the whole world. The 
"Doctrine of Tone-Sensations" is the speculation of a 
genius, the expression of an artistic intuition, which points 
the way though it be only by the symbolism of a physical 
analogy, and as in a picture along which further research 
will have to advance. We must therefore be careful not to 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 307 
throw overboard much that is valuable along with the 
deficiencies that have to be set aside. For what reasons 
Helmholtz himself took so little notice of criticism, I do 
not know. But in the last disposition which he made, 
according to which the text of the Tone- Sensations was 
to remain unaltered after his death, I think that he acted 
rightly. 
22. 
To a person accustomed to looking at things from the 
point of view of the theory of evolution, the high develop- 
ment of modern music and the spontaneous and sudden 
appearance of great musical talent seem, at first glance, a 
most singular and mysterious phenomenon. What can this 
remarkable development of the power of hearing have to do 
with the preservation of the species? Does it not far 
exceed the measure of the necessary or the merely useful ? 
What can possibly be the significance of a fine discrimina- 
tion of pitch ? Of what use to us is the sense of intervals, 
or of the acoustic colorings of orchestral music ? 
As a matter of fact, the same question may be proposed 
with reference to every art, no matter from what province 
of sense its material is derived. The question is pertinent, 
also, with regard to the intelligence of a Newton, an Euler, 
or their like, which apparently far transcends the necessary 
measure. But the question is most obvious with reference 
to music, which satisfies no practical need and for the most 
part depicts nothing. Music, however, is closely allied to 
the decorative arts. In order to be able to see, a person 
must have the power of distinguishing the directions of lines. 
If he has a fine power of distinction, such a person may 
308 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
acquire, as a sort of collateral product of his education, a 
feeling for agreeable combinations of lines. The case is the 
same with the sense of color-harmony following upon the 
development of the power of distinguishing colors, and so, 
too, it undoubtedly is with respect to music. 
We must bear in mind that what we call talent and 
genius, however gigantic their achievements may appear to 
us, constitute but a slight departure from normal endow- 
ment. Talent may be resolved into the possession of 
psychical power slightly above the average 'in a certain 
province. And as for genius, it is talent supplemented by 
a capacity of adaptation extending beyond the youthful 
period, and by the retention of freedom to overstep routine 
barriers. The naivety of the child delights us, and produces 
almost always the impression of genius. But this impres- 
sion as a rule quickly disappears, and we perceive that the 
very same utterances which, as adults, we are wont to 
ascribe to freedom, have their source, in the child, in a 
lack of fixed character. 
Talent and genius, as Weismann has aptly shown, 1 do 
not make their appearance slowly and by degrees in the 
course of generations ; nor can they be the result of ac- 
cumulated effort and practice on the part of ancestors ; but 
they manifest themselves spontaneously and suddenly. 
Taken in connexion with what has been said above, this, 
too, is intelligible, if we will but reflect that descendants are 
not exact reproductions of their immediate ancestors, but 
exhibit the qualities both of their immediate and of their 
more distant ancestors and relatives with some variations, 
1 Weismann, Ueber die Vererbung. Jena, 1883 (English translation, 
Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1889), p. 43. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 309 
now slightly diminished, now slightly augmented in amount. 
The comparison of several children of the same two parents 
is very instructive on this point. To deny the influence of 
pedigree on psychical dispositions would be as unreasonable 
as to reduce everything to it, as is done, whether from 
narrow-mindedness or dishonesty, by modern fanatics on 
the question of race. Surely everyone knows from his own 
experience what rich psychical acquisitions he owes to his 
cultural environment, to the influence of long vanished 
generations, and to his contemporaries. The factors of 
development do not suddenly become inoperative in post- 
embryonic life. 1 
1 Cf. the sound and sober view of R. Wallaschek, Anfdnge der 
Tonkunst) Leipzig, 1903, pp. 291-298. 
XIV. INFLUENCE OF THE PRECED- 
ING INVESTIGATIONS on OUR 
CONCEPTION OF PHYSICS. 1 
i. 
WHAT gain does physics derive from the preceding in- 
vestigations ? In the first place, a very widespread 
prejudice is removed, and with it, a barrier. There is no rift 
between the psychical and the physical, no inside and outside, 
no " sensation " to which an external " thing," different from 
sensation, corresponds. There is but one kind of elements, 
out of which this supposed inside and outside are formed 
elements which are themselves inside or outside, according 
to the aspect in which, for the time being, they are viewed. 
The world of sense belongs both to the physical and the 
psychical domain alike. As, in studying the behaviour of 
gases, by disregarding variations of temperature we reach 
Mariotte's law, but by expressly considering them, Gay 
1 I have partly discussed the questions considered in this chapter, 
before (see my History and Root of the Principle of the Conservation 
of Energy \ translated by P. E. B. Jourdain, Chicago, Open Court 
Publishing Co., 1911, and also the essay on "The Economical Nature 
of Physical Inquiry," first published in 1882, and now in my Popular 
Scientific Lectures, Chicago. 1894, and see my Mechanik and 
Warmelehre). With regard to the idea of concepts as labor-saving 
instruments, the late Prof. W. James directed in conversation my 
attention to points of agreement between my writings and his essay 
on "The Sentiment of Rationality" (Mind, Vol. IV., p. 317, July 
1879). This essay, written with refreshing vigor and impartiality, will 
be perused by everyone with pleasure and profit. 
310 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 311 
Lussac's, while throughout our object of investigation 
remains the same ; so, too, we are studying physics in its 
broadest signification when in searching into the connexions 
of the world of sense we leave our own body entirely out 
of account; whereas we are studying the psychology or 
physiology of the senses when we direct our main attention 
to the body and above all to our nervous system. Our 
body, like every other, is part of the world of sense ; the 
boundary-line between the physical and the psychical is 
solely practical and conventional. If, for the higher pur- 
poses of science, we erase this dividing-line, and consider all 
connexions as equivalent, new paths of investigation cannot 
fail to be opened up. 
We must regard it as an additional gain that the physicist 
is now no longer overawed by the traditional intellectual 
implements of physics. If ordinary "matter" must be 
regarded merely as a highly natural, unconsciously con- 
structed mental symbol for a relatively stable complex of 
sensational elements, much more must this be the case 
with the artificial hypothetical atoms and molecules of 
physics and chemistry. The value of these implements for 
their special, limited purposes is not one whit destroyed. 
As before, they remain economical ways of symbolizing 
experience. But we have as little right to expect from 
them, as from the symbols of algebra, more than we have 
put into them, and certainly not more enlightenment and 
revelation than from experience itself. We are on our 
guard now, even in the province of physics, against over- 
estimating the value of our symbols. Still less, therefore, will 
the monstrous idea of employing atoms to explain psychical 
processes ever get possession of us; seeing that atoms 
312 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
are but the symbols of those peculiar complexes of sensa- 
tional elements which we meet with in the narrow domains 
of physics and chemistry. 
2. 
The fundamental views of mankind are formed by a 
natural process of adaptation to a narrower or wider sphere 
of experience and thought. It may be that the physicist is 
still satisfied with the notion of a rigid matter, of which the 
only changes are movements, or changes of place. Of such 
a thing as this the physiologist or psychologist can make 
nothing at all. But any one who has in mind the gather- 
ing up of the sciences into a single whole, has to look for a 
conception to which he can hold in every department of 
science. Now if we resolve the whole material world into 
elements which at the same time are also elements of the 
psychical world and, as such, are commonly called sensa- 
tions ; if, further, we regard it as the sole task of science 
to inquire into the connexion and combination of these 
elements, which are of the same nature in all departments, 
and into their mutual dependence on one another ; we may 
then reasonably expect to build a unified monistic structure 
upon this conception, and thus to get rid of the distressing 
confusions of dualism. Indeed, it is by regarding matter as 
something absolutely stable and immutable that we actually 
destroy the connexion between physics and physiology. 
Epistemological criticism can indeed do no one any 
harm, but the specialist, the physicist, for instance, has 
no reason to allow himself to be troubled overmuch by 
such speculations. Acuteness of observation and a felicitous 
instinct are very safe guides fcr him. His conceptions, in 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 313 
so far as they prove to be inadequate, will be best and most 
quickly corrected by the facts. But when it is a question 
of bringing into connexion two adjacent departments, each 
of which has been developed in its special and peculiar way, 
the connexion cannot be effected by means of the limited 
conceptions of a narrow special department. By means of 
more general considerations, conceptions have to be created 
which shall be adequate for the wider domain. Every 
physicist is not an epistemologist, nor ought every physicist 
to be one, even if it were possible. Special research 
demands a man's full energies ; but so does epistemology. 
Not long after the first edition of this book was published, 
I was lectured by a physicist on the misguided way in which 
I had conceived my task. In his opinion, it was impossible 
to analyse the sensations as long as the paths of the atoms 
in the brain were unknown; and when they were known 
everything else would follow of itself. Of course I had not 
much use for utterances such as these, which, had I been a 
young man of the period of Laplace, might have fallen upon 
fertile ground and have developed into a psychological 
theory based on " concealed movements." The effect 
which they had was, however, to make me offer a silent 
apology to Dubois-Reymond with his Ignorabimus^ a 
dictum which up to that moment I had regarded as the 
greatest mistake. After all, Dubois-Reymond's recognition 
of the insolubility of his problem was an immense step in 
advance ; this recognition removed a weight from many 
men's minds, as is shewn by the success of his work, a 
success which is otherwise scarcely intelligible. 1 He did 
1 Dubois-Reymond, Ueber die Grenzen des Naturerkennens, 1872, 
4th. ed. 
314 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
not, indeed, take the further important step of seeing that 
the recognition of a problem as insoluble in principle, must 
depend on a mistaken way of stating the question. For he 
too, like countless others, took the instruments of a special 
science to be the actual world. 
The sciences may be distinguished according to the 
matter of which they treat, as also by their manner of treat- 
ing it. But all science has for its aim the representation of 
facts in thought, either for practical ends, or for removing 
intellectual discomfort. Resuming the terminology of 
the "Introductory Remarks," science, we may say, arises 
when the combination of the other elements is imitated by 
the elements a (3 7. . . . For example, physics (in its 
broadest signification) arises by the representative repro- 
duction of the elements A B C in their relations to one 
another; the physiology or psychology of the senses, through 
reproducing in like manner the relations of A B C . . . to 
K L M . . . ; physiology, through reproducing the relations 
of K L M ... to one another and to A B C . . . ; while 
the reproducing of the a /5 7 ... themselves by other 
a /3 7 . . . leads to the psychological sciences proper. 
Now one might be of the opinion, say, with respect to 
physics, that the portrayal of the sense-given facts is of less 
importance than the atoms, forces, and laws which form, so 
to speak, the nucleus of the sense-given facts. But un- 
biassed reflexion discloses that every practical and intel- 
lectual need is satisfied the moment our thoughts have 
acquired the power to represent the facts of the senses 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 315 
completely. Such representation, consequently, is the end 
and aim of physics ; while atoms, forces, and laws are 
merely means facilitating the representation. Their value 
extends as far, and as far only, as the help they afford. 
Our knowledge of a natural phenomenon, say of -an 
earthquake, is as complete as possible when our thoughts 
so marshal before the eye of the mind all the relevant sense- 
given facts of the case that they may be regarded almost as 
a substitute for the phenomenon itself, and the facts appear 
to us as old familiar figures, having no power to occasion 
surprise. When, in imagination, we hear the subterranean 
thunders, feel the oscillation of the earth, figure to ourselves 
the sensation produced by the rising and sinking of the 
ground, the cracking of the walls, the falling of the plaster, 
the movement of the furniture and the pictures, the stopping 
of the clocks, the rattling and smashing of windows, the 
wrenching of the door-posts, the jamming of the doors; 
when we see in mind the oncoming undulation passing over 
a forest as lightly as a gust of wind over a field of grain, 
breaking the branches of the trees ; when we see the town 
enveloped in a cloud of dust, hear the bells begin to ring 
in the towers ; further, when the subterranean processes, 
which are at present unknown to us, shall stand out in full 
sensational reality before our eyes, so that we shall see the 
earthquake advancing as we see a waggon approaching in 
the distance till finally we hear the earth shaking beneath 
our feet, then more insight than this we cannot have, and 
more we do not require. If we cannot combine the partial 
316 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
facts in their right proportions without the aid of certain 
auxiliary mathematical conceptions or geometrical construc- 
tions, it yet remains true that these constructions merely 
enable our thoughts to grasp gradually and piecemeal what 
they are unable to grasp all at once. But these auxiliary 
conceptions would be devoid of value, could we not reach, 
by their help, the graphic representation of the sense-given 
facts. 
When I see in thought a white beam of light which falls 
upon a prism issue forth in a fan-shaped band of colors 
having certain angles which I can specify beforehand ; when 
1 see the real spectrum-image, obtained upon a screen by 
interposing a lens, with Fraunhofer's lines occurring in it at 
points determinable in advance ; when I see, in my mind, 
how these lines alter their position on the prism being 
turned, on its substance being changed, or on the ther- 
mometer in contact with it altering its register, then I know 
all that I can require. All auxiliary conceptions, laws, and 
formulae, are but quantitative norms, regulating my sensory 
representation of the facts. The latter is the end, the 
former are the means. 
The adaptation of thoughts to facts, accordingly, is the 
aim of all scientific research. In this, science only deliber- 
ately and consciously pursues what in daily life goes on 
unnoticed and of its own accord. As soon as we become 
capable of self-observation, we find our thoughts, in large 
measure, already adjusted to the facts. Our thoughts 
marshal the elements before us in groups copying the order 
of the sense-given facts. But the limited supply of thoughts 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 317 
cannot keep pace with the constantly augmenting sweep of 
experience. Almost every new fact necessitates a new 
adaptation, which finds its expression in the operation of 
judgment. 
This process is easily followed in children. A child, on 
its first visit from the town to the country, strays, for 
instance, into a large meadow, looks about, and says 
wonderingly : "We are in a ball. The world is a blue 
ball." l Here we have two judgments. What is the process 
accompanying their formation? In the first instance, the 
already existing sensational representation "we" (himself 
and his companions) is filled out into a single image by 
means of the representation of a ball, which also already 
existed. Similarly, in the second judgment, the image of 
the " world " (/.*., all the objects of the environment) is 
supplemented by combination with the image of an envelop 
ing blue ball (the representation of which must also have 
been present, since otherwise the name for it would have 
been wanting). A judgment is thus always a supplement- 
ing of a sensational presentation in order to represent more 
completely a sensational fact. If the judgment can be 
expressed in words, then the new presentation is never 
more than a combination of formerly established memory- 
images, which can also be elicited in a person addressed 
by words. 
The process of judgment, therefore, in the present case, 
consists in the enrichment, extension, and supplementation 
1 This example is not fictitious, but was observed in the case of my 
three-year-old child. In this case what is actually attested is a physio- 
logical fact, but this has only been recognized at a late stage. Scientific 
astronomy begins in antiquity with similar naif assertions, which it 
thinks are physical. 
3i8 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
of sensational presentations by other sensational presenta- 
tions under the guidance of sense-given facts. If the pro- 
cess is over, and the image has assumed a familiar shape, 
making its appearance in consciousness as a completed 
presentation, then we have no longer to do with a judgment 
but merely with a simple memory. 1 It is to the formation 
of such intuitive knowledge, as Locke calls it, that natural 
science and mathematics mainly owe their growth. Con- 
sider, for example, the following statements : (i) the tree 
has a root ; (2) the frog has no claws ; (3) the caterpillar is 
transformed into a butterfly ; (4) weak sulphuric acid dis- 
solves zinc ; (5) friction electrifies glass ; (6) an electric 
current deflects a magnetic needle ; (?) a cube has six 
surfaces, eight corners, twelve edges. The first statement 
contains a spatial extension of the presentation " tree " ; 
the second a correction of a presentation too hastily 
generalized from habit ; the third, fourth, fifth, and sixth 
contain temporal extensions of their respective presentations. 
1 I cannot here enter upon an examination of the process of judgment 
as such. But among recent works on the subject I should like to draw 
special attention to W. Jerusalem's Die Urteilsfiinktion (Vienna, 1895). 
Though my own position is not that of the author's, I nevertheless have 
been greatly stimulated and instructed by many of the investigations of 
special points contained in his book. The physiological aspects, and 
in particular the biological function of judgment, are set forth in a very 
lively way. His conception of the subject in judgment as a centre of 
force can scarcely be called felicitous. on the other hand, it will 
certainly be readily admitted that in the early stages of culture and of 
the formation of language anthropomorphic conceptions exerted much 
influence. Other questions of a different kind are discussed by A. 
Stohrin 7heorieder Namen (1889), Die Vieldeutigkeit des (7rtet/s(i&9$), 
and Algebra der Grammatik (1898). Of these works, those concerned 
with the relation between logic and grammar seem to me the most 
interesting. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 319 
The seventh proposition is an example of geometrical 
intuitive knowledge. 
6. 
Intuitive knowledge of the sort just described impresses 
itself upon the memory, and makes its appearance in the 
form of recollections which spontaneously supplement every 
fact presented by the senses. The various facts are not 
exactly alike. But the component parts of the sensational 
presentation which are common to different cases are 
emphasized, and so we reach a principle which holds a 
paramount place in memory the principle of broadest 
possible generalization or continuity. on the other hand, if 
memory is to do justice to the complexity of facts, and be 
of real practical use, it must conform to the principle of 
sufficient differentiation. Even the animal is reminded, by 
soft, bright red and yellow fruits (seen without exertion on 
the tree), of their sweet taste, and by green hard fruits 
(which are seen with difficulty), of their sour taste. The 
insect-hunting monkey snatches at everything that buzzes 
and flies, but avoids the yellow and black fly, the wasp. 
Here we have expressed, distinctly enough, the combined 
effort for the greatest possible generalization and continuity 
and lot practically sufficient differentiation of memory. And 
both ends are attained by the same means, the selection and 
emphasis of those particular elements of the sensational pre- 
sentations which are determinative of the direction which 
the thought must pursue to suit the experience. The 
physicist proceeds in quite an analogous manner, when he 
says (generalizing) : All transparent solids refract incident 
light towards the perpendicular, and when he adds (differ- 
320 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
entiating) : amorphous bodies and isomeric crystals simply, 
the rest doubly. 
A great part of our mental adaptation takes place un- 
consciously and involuntarily, under the guidance of the 
facts presented to the senses. If this adaptation has 
become sufficiently comprehensive to embrace the vast 
majority of the occurring facts, and subsequently we come 
upon a fact which runs violently counter to the customary 
course of our thought without our being able to discover at 
once the determinative factor likely to lead to a new differ- 
entiation, then a problem arises. The new, unusual, and 
marvellous acts as a stimulus, which irresistibly attracts the 
attention. Practical considerations, or even bare intellectual 
discomfort, may engender the will to remove the contradic- 
tion or to adapt our thoughts to the new fact. Thus arises 
purposive thought-adaptation, or investigation. 
For example, we have all, at some time or another, quite 
contrary to the common run of our experience, observed a 
lever or pulley lifting a large weight by means of a small 
one. We seek the differentiating factor, which cannot be 
immediately disclosed to us by the fact itself as given to 
the senses. It is only when, comparing various similar 
facts, we have noted the influence of the weights, and of 
the arms of the lever, and by our own exertions have reached 
the abstract concepts of "moment" or "work," that the 
problem is solved. " Moment " or " work " is the differen- 
tiating element. When it has become a habit of thought to 
pay attention to "moment" or "work," the problem no 
longer exists. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 321 
8. 
What do we do when we abstract ? What is an abstrac- 
tion ? What is a concept ? Is there a sensational presentation- 
image corresponding to the concept ? I cannot represent 
to myself a man in general. I can at most represent to 
myself a particular man, or perhaps one combining such 
accidental peculiarities of different men as are not exclusive 
of each other. A universal triangle, which is at once right- 
angled and equilateral, cannot be imagined. Further, the 
image thus rising into consciousness at the name of the con- 
cept, and accompanying the conceptual process, is not the 
concept. In fact, generally, words, being designations which 
from necessity must be used to describe many particular 
presentations, are far from corresponding completely to any 
concept. A child who has seen for the first time a black 
dog and heard it named, soon afterward calls a large and 
swiftly-running black beetle, "dog"; or a pig or a sheep, 
"dog." 1 Any similarity whatever reminding him of the 
presentation to which the name was first given naturally 
leads to the use of the same name. The point of similarity 
need not be at all the same in the successive cases. It may 
reside, for instance, at one time, in the color, at another 
in the motion, at another in the form, at another in the 
external covering ; and so on. Thus there is no question 
of a concept. Thus a child calls the feathers of a bird 
"hairs"; the horns of a cow " feelers ;; ; a shaving-brush, 
1 Thus the Marcomanni called the lions sent across the Danube by 
the Romans "dogs," and the lonians called the xd-pfa 1 f tne Nile 
"crocodiles " from their likeness to the lizards (KpoK65ei\oi) which, in 
Ionia, live in the walls. (Herodotos, II., 69.) 
X 
322 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
its father's beard, and the down of a dandelion, without dis- 
tinction, "shaving-brush"; and so on. 1 Most adults treat 
words in the same manner, only less noticeably so, because 
they have a larger vocabulary at their disposal. The illiterate 
man calls a rectangle a " square " ; occasionally he also calls 
a cube a " square," because of its rectangular boundaries. 
The science of language, and a number of authenticated 
historical examples, shew that even nations do not act 
differently. 2 
A concept is never simply a completed presentation. 
In using a word denoting a concept, there is nothing in- 
volved in the word but a simple impulse to perform some 
familiar sensory operation, as the result of which a definite 
sensational element (the mark of the concept) is obtained. 
For example, when I think of the concept "heptagon," I 
enumerate the angles of a figure visibly before me or of 
its image in my consciousness; and when in so doing I 
reach seven, in which case the sound, the numeral, or my 
finger may announce the sensational mark of the number, 
then by this very act the given presentation falls under 
the given concept. In speaking of a "square number," 
I seek to resolve the number given into components 
typified by the operation 5x5, 6x6, etc., the sensational 
characteristic of which, namely, the equality of the two 
factors multiplied, is patent. The same holds good of 
every concept. The activity excited by the word may be 
made up of a number of operations, one of which may 
contain the other. But the result is always a sensational 
element which was not present before. 
1 All these examples are taken from actual experience. 
2 See W. D. Whitney, Life and Growth of Language, 1875. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 323 
In looking at or in imagining a heptagon, the fact of 
its having seven angles need not be present to my mind. 
This fact is distinctly cognized only on counting. Fre- 
quently, the new sensational element may be so obvious 
(as it is, for instance, in the case of the triangle) that the 
operation of counting seems unnecessary. Such cases, 
however, are exceptional, and constitute the main source 
of misunderstandings concerning the nature of concepts. 
In the case of conic sections (the ellipse, parabola, 
hyperbola) I do not directly see that these curves all 
fall under the same concept ; but I can discover the fact 
by cutting a cone, and by constructing the equation for 
conies. 
When, therefore, we apply abstract concepts to a fact, 
the fact merely acts upon us as an impulse to a sensa- 
tional activity, which introduces new sensational elements, 
which in their turn may determine the subsequent course 
of our thought in harmony with the fact. By this 
activity we enrich and extend the fact, which before 
was too meagre for us. We do what the chemist does 
with his colorless solution of salts, when by a definite 
operation he elicits from it a yellow or brown precipi- 
tate, which has the power to differentiate the course of 
his thought. The concept of the physicist is a definite 
reaction-activity, which enriches a fact with new^sensational 
elements. 
A small measure of sensational endowment and a very 
low degree of mobility are sufficient for the formation of 
concepts, as is shewn by the history of the mental develop- 
ment of the blind, deaf and dumb Laura Bridgman, which 
has been made generally accessible by Jerusalem's interest- 
324 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
ing little book. 1 In Laura Bridgman the sense of smell 
wa*s almost entirely lacking ; her only channel for the per- 
ception of disturbances and sound-vibrations was the soles 
of her feet and her finger-tips her skin, in short; yet 
she succeeded in forming simple concepts. By walking 
about and by moving her hands she discovers the tactual 
signs (the class-characteristics) of a door, a chair, a knife, 
and so forth. The power of abstraction does not, indeed, 
go very far. The most abstract concepts to which she 
was able to attain seem to have been the numbers. on 
the whole her mental processes remained, naturally enough, 
attached to specific presentations. Evidence of this is 
afforded by her taking the sums in a school-book to be 
specially intended for her (op. tit., p. 25), and her idea 
that heaven, or the world beyond, was a school (op. tit., 
P- 3)- 
To revert to an earlier example, when we see a lever, 
we are impelled to measure the length of its arms, to weigh 
its weights, and to multiply the numbers representing the 
lengths of its arms by the numbers representing the values 
of its weights. If the same sensational numerical symbol 
corresponds to both products, we expect equilibrium. We 
have thus gained a new sensational element which was 
not antecedently given in the bare fact itself, but which 
now differentiates the course of our thought. If we will 
keep well in mind the fact that conceptual thought is a re- 
1 W. Jerusalem, Laura Bridgman, Vienna, Pichler, 1891. Cp. 
also L. W. Stern, Helen Keller, Berlin, 1905; Jerusalem, "Marie 
Heurtin," Oesterreichische ftundsckau, Vol. III., pp. 292, 426 (1905). 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 325 
action-activity which must be thoroughly practised, we shall 
understand the well-known fact that no one can familiarize 
himself with mathematics or physics or with any natural 
science by mere reading without practical exercise. Under- 
standing here depends entirely on action. In fact, it is 
impossible in any province to grasp the higher abstractions 
without a practical working knowledge of its details. 
Facts, then, are extended and enriched, and ultimately 
again simplified, by conceptual handling. For when the 
new determinative sensational element is found (say, the 
number representing the virtual moments of the lever), 
then the attention is directed to this alone, and the most 
diverse groups of facts are found to resemble and not to 
resemble each other solely in virtue of this element. Thus 
here also, as in the case of intuitive knowledge, everything 
is reducible to the discovery, selection, and emphasis of 
the determinative sensational elements. Investigation here 
only reaches by a roundabout way what is immediately 
presented to intuitive cognition. 
The chemist with his re-agents, the physicist with his mea- 
suring-rod, scales, and galvanometer, and the mathematician 
all treat facts in precisely the same way \ the only difference 
being that the latter needs to go least outside the elements 
a j8 7 . . . KL M in his extension of facts. The aids of 
the mathematician are always conveniently at hand. The 
investigator and all his thought are a fragment only of 
nature, like everything else. There is no real chasm between 
him and*he t/other fragments. All elements are equivalent. 

on the preceding theory, the essence of abstraction is 
not exhausted by terming it (with Kant) negative attention. 
It is true that, in abstracting, the attention is turned away 
326 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
from many sensational elements, but on the other hand, it 
is turned towards other new sensational elements ; and 
precisely this latter fact is the essential feature. Every 
abstraction is founded on the prominence given to certain 
sensational elements. 
10. 
In the foregoing exposition of my views I have left what 
I wrote in 1886 unaltered; but at the same time I should 
like to refer the reader to the further explanations contained 
in a later work of mine. 1 In the second edition of the 
Prinzipien der Wdrmekhre (1900), I have also mentioned 
the works of H. Gomperz and Ribot, which have appeared 
since 1897 ; these works contain investigations which in 
many respects have a certain affinity to my own. Both 
Gomperz and Ribot exclude scientific concepts from the 
scope of their inquiry, and treat only of such vulgar con- 
cepts as have been fixed in the words of the common 
speech of everyday intercourse. I, on the contrary, am of 
the opinion that the nature of concepts is necessarily much 
more clearly displayed in scientific concepts, which have 
been consciously formed and applied, than in vulgar 
concepts. The latter are so vague that they can scarcely 
be reckoned as proper concepts at all. The words of 
ordinary speech are simply familiar signs which occasion 
equally familiar habits of thought. The conceptual content 
of such words, in so far as it has any definite form at all, 
is scarcely present to consciousness, as Ribot also found 
by his statistical experiments. I have no doubt that, if 
1 Prinzipien der WtLrmekhre> 1896 ; 2nd ed., 1900, pp. 415, 422. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 327 
Ribot and Gomperz had framed their inquiry so as to 
include scientific concepts also, my agreement with them 
would be even more far-reaching than it actually is. 
We have chosen statical moment as a simple example of 
a concept. Complicated concepts will require a complicated 
system of reactions, drawing upon more or less large parts 
of the central nervous system, and helping to create a 
correspondingly complicated system of sensational elements 
characterizing the concept. Probably the difficulties pointed 
out by J. von Kries are not insuperable on this theory. 1 
(Cf. pp. 69, 70 above.) 
ii. 
The facts given by the senses, therefore, are alike the 
starting-point and the goal of all the mental adaptations of 
the physicist. The thoughts which follow the sense-given 
fact immediately are the most familiar, the strongest, and 
the most intuitive. Where we cannot at once follow a new 
fact, the strongest and most familiar thoughts press forward 
to mould it into a richer and more definite shape. This 
process is the source of all the hypotheses and speculations 
of science, which all find their justification in the mental 
adaptation that develops them and ultimately gives them 
birth. Thus we think of the planets as projectiles, we figure 
to ourselves an electric body as covered with a fluid that 
acts at a distance, we think of heat as a substance that passes 
from one body to another, until finally the new facts become 
as familiar and as intuitive as the older ones, which we have 
used as mental helps. Even where immediate intuition is 
*J. von Kries, Die materiellen Gmndlagen der Bewusstseinser- 
scheinungeti) Freiburg im Breisgau, 1898. 
328 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
out of the question, the thoughts of the physicist, by care- 
fully observing the principle of continuity and of sufficient 
differentiation, become ordered in an economically assorted 
system of conceptual reactions, which lead, at least by the 
shortest path, to intuitive knowledge. All calculations, 
constructions, etc., are merely intermediate means, pro- 
ceeding step by step, and always using sense-perception as 
a support, to the attainment of this kind of intuition in 
cases where it cannot be attained immediately. 
12. 
Let us now consider the results of mental adaptation. 
Thoughts can adapt themselves only to what is constant 
in the facts ; it is only the mental reconstruction of constant 
elements that can yield advantage in point of economy. 
Herein is contained the ultimate ground of our effort for 
continuity in thought, that is, for the preservation of the 
greatest possible constancy, and in this way, too, the results 
of the adaptation are rendered intelligible. 1 Continuity, 
economy, and constancy mutually condition one another 
they are really only different aspects of one and the same 
property of all sound thinking. 
The unconditionally constant we term substance. I see 
a body upon turning my eyes in its direction. I can see 
it without touching it, I can touch it without seeing it. 
Although the actual appearance of the component elements 
1 Cp. my The Science of Mechanics, translated by T. J. M'Cormack, 
Chicago, Open Court Publishing Co., 1893, P- 5 O 4- 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 329 
of the complex is determined in this way by certain conditions, 
I yet have these conditions too absolutely in my power to 
appreciate or notice them markedly. I regard the body, or 
the complex of elements, or the nucleus of this complex, 
as always present, whether, for the moment, it is the object 
of my senses or not. Having always ready the thought of 
this complex, or, symbolically, the thought of its nucleus, 
I gain the advantage of being able to predict, and avoid 
the disadvantage of being surprised. My behaviour is the 
same with regard to the chemical elements, which also 
appear to me unconditionally constant. Although here my 
mere willing it is not sufficient to make of the complexes in 
question sensational facts, and although in the present case 
external aids (for instance, bodies exterior to my own body) 
also are necessary, I yet leave these aids out of account 
as soon as they have become familiar to me, and look upon 
the chemical elements as simply constant. The man who 
believes in atoms treats them in an analogous way. 
In the same manner as with the complex of elements 
corresponding to a body, we may also proceed, on a higher 
plane of thought-adaptation, with entire provinces of facts. 
In speaking of electricity, magnetism, light, and heat, even 
when not associating special substances with these names, 
we yet ascribe constancy to these provinces of facts, leaving 
entirely out of account the familiar conditions under which 
they appear ; and we hold the ideas which reproduce them 
always in readiness, thereby gaining an advantage similar 
to that explained above. When I say a body is "electric," 
far more memories arise in my mind, and my expectations 
are associated with far more definite groups of facts, than 
if I had emphasized, for instance, the attractions displayed 
330 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
in the single cases. Yet this hypostasizing may have its 
disadvantages, also. In the first place, in proceeding thus, 
we always follow the same historical paths. It may be 
important, however, to recognize that there is no such 
thing as a specific electrical fact, that every such fact can 
just as well be regarded, for example, as a chemical one, or 
as a thermal one, or rather that all physical facts are made 
up, ultimately, of the same sensational elements (colors, 
pressures, spaces, times), and that we are merely reminded 
by the term " electric " of that particular form in which we 
first became acquainted with the fact. 
If we have once accustomed ourselves to regard the body, 
to and from which we can, at pleasure, turn our glance or 
our hand, as constant, then it is easy for us to do the same 
in cases in which the conditions of sensational manifesta- 
tion lie entirely beyond our power for example, in the 
case of the sun and moon, which we cannot touch, or of 
parts of the world which we have seen but once and shall 
perhaps never see again, or that we know only by descrip- 
tion. Such a method of procedure may have high import- 
ance for an undisturbed and economical conception of the 
world, but it is certainly not the only legitimate method. 
It would be merely a consistent additional step, if we were 
to regard the whole past, which is, indeed, still present in 
its vestiges (since, for instance, we see the stars where they 
were thousands of years ago), and the whole future, which 
is present in germ (since, for example, our solar system will 
be seen where it now is, thousands of years hence), as con 
stant. The entire passage of time, in fact, is dependent 
solely on conditions of our sensibility. Were a special 
purpose given, even this step might be hazarded 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 331 
14. 
Really unconditioned constancy does not exist, as will 
be evident from the preceding considerations. We attain 
to the idea of absolute constancy only as we overlook or 
underrate conditions, or as we regard them as always given, 
or as we deliberately disregard them. There is only one 
sort of constancy, which embraces all the cases that occur, 
namely, constancy of connexion or of relation. Substance, 
again, or matter, is not anything unconditionally constant. 
What we call matter is a combination of the elements or 
sensations according to certain laws. The sensations con- 
nected with the different sense-organs of a particular man 
are dependent on one another according to laws, as are 
the sensations of different men. It is in this that matter 
consists. The older generation, especially the physicists 
and chemists, will be alarmed by this proposal not to treat 
matter as something absolutely constant, but to take as 
constant, instead, a fixed law of connexion among elements 
which in themselves seem extremely unstable. Even 
younger minds may find this conception difficult ; but the 
view is inevitable, though I myself at one time went through 
a great struggle in order to arrive at it. We shall have to make 
up our minds to some such radical change in the method of 
our thought, if we want to escape the alternative of perpetu- 
ally recurring helplessness in the face of these questions. 
There can be no question of abolishing from ordinary 
everyday use the vulgar conception of matter which has 
been instinctively developed for this purpose. Moreover, 
all our concepts of physical measurement can be maintained, 
332 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 

only receiving such critical elucidation as I have tried to 
carry out for mechanics, heat, electricity, etc. Purely 
empirical concepts here take the place of metaphysical. 
But science suffers no loss when a " matter," which is a 
rigid, sterile, constant, unknown Something, is replaced by 
a constant law, of which the details are still capable of 
further explanation by means of physico-physiological re- 
search. In doing this our object is not to create a new 
philosophy or metaphysics, but to promote the efforts, 
which the positive sciences are at this moment making, 
towards mutual accommodation. 
*$ 
The propositions of natural science express only such 
constancies of connexion as : " The tadpole turns into a 
frog. Chlorate of sodium makes its appearance in the form 
of cubes. Rays of light are rectilinear. Bodies fall with an 
acceleration of 9*81 (m/sec 2 )." When these constancies are 
expressed in concepts, we call them laws. Force (in the 
mechanical sense) is likewise merely a constancy of con- 
nexion. When I say that a body A exerts a force on a body 
B, I mean that B, on coming into contraposition with A, is 
immediately affected by a certain acceleration with respect 
to A. 
The singular illusion, that the substance A is the abso- 
lutely constant vehicle of a force which takes effect immedi- 
ately on j#'s being contraposed to A t is easily removed. If 
we, or more exactly speaking, our sense-organs, be put in 
the place of B, here a condition intervenes, which, seeing 
that it is possible at any time to fulfil it, is invariably 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 333 
disregarded, and thus A appears to us absolutely constant. 
Similarly, a magnet, which we see as often as we care to 
look in its direction, appears to us the constant vehicle of a 
magnetic force, which becomes operative only upon being 
brought near to a particle of iron, which we cannot, with- 
out noticing the fact, disregard as easily as we can ourselves. 1 
The phrases, " No matter without force, no force without 
matter," which are but abortive attempts to remove a self- 
incurred contradiction, become superfluous when we re- 
cognize only constancies of connexion. 
1 6. 
Given a sufficient constancy of environment, there is 
developed a corresponding constancy of thought. By virtue 
of this constancy our thoughts are spontaneously impelled 
to complete the half-observed facts. This impulse towards 
completion is not prompted by the individual facts as 
observed at the time ; nor is it intentionally created ; but 
we find it operative in ourselves entirely without our personal 
intervention. It confronts us like a power from without, 
yet as a power which continually accompanies and assists 
us, as a thing of which we stand in need, in order to 
1 To the child everything appears substantial, for the perception of 
which only his senses are necessary. The child asks where the shadow, 
where the extinguished light goes to. He will not allow the electrical 
machine to be turned any great length of time for fear of exhausting 
the supply of sparks, etc. A boy of less than a year old wanted, when 
his father whistled a tune, to catch the notes from his lips. Even with 
older children we find the attempt to snatch at coloured after-images, 
etc. only upon noting conditions of a fact that are outside ourselves 
does the impression of substantiality disappear. The history of the 
theory of heat is very instructive in this connexion. 
334 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
supplement the facts. Although it is developed by experi- 
ence, it contains more than is contained in the single 
experience. The impulse in a certain measure enriches the 
single fact. Through it the fact is more to us. With this 
impulse we have always a larger portion of nature in our 
field of vision, than the inexperienced man has with the 
single fact alone. For the human being, with his thoughts 
and his impulses, is himself merely a piece of nature, which 
is added to the single fact. This impulse, however, can lay 
no claim to infallibility, and there exists no necessity com- 
pelling the facts to correspond to it. Our confidence in it 
rests entirely upon the supposition, which has been sub- 
stantiated by numerous trials, of the sufficiency of our 
mental adaptation, a supposition, however, which must be 
prepared to be contradicted at any moment. 
Not all our ideas representing facts have the same 
constancy. Whenever we have a special interest in the 
representation of facts, we endeavour to support and cor- 
roborate ideas of lesser constancy by ideas of greater 
constancy, or to replace them by the latter. Thus Newton 
conceived the planets as projectiles, although Kepler's laws 
were already well known, and the tides as attracted by the 
moon, although the facts of their movement had long been 
ascertained. We do not think that we understand the 
suction of a pump, or the flowing of a siphon, until we have 
mentally added the pressure of the air as holding the chain 
of particles together. Similarly we seek to conceive electrical, 
optical, and thermal processes as mechanical processes. 
This need of the support of weaker thoughts by stronger 
thoughts is also called the need of causality, and is the 
moving spring of all scientific explanations. We naturally 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 335 
prefer, as the foundation of this process, the strongest and 
most thoroughly tested thoughts, and these are given us by 
our much exercised mechanical functions, which we may 
test anew at any moment without many or cumbersome 
appliances. Hence the authority of mechanical explanations, 
especially those by pressure and impact. A corresponding 
and still higher authority attaches to mathematical thoughts, 
for in their development we stand in need of no extraneous 
means whatever, but, on the contrary, invariably carry most 
of the material for experimenting about with us. But if we 
are once apprised of this, the need of mechanical explana- 
tions is appreciably weakened. 1 
I have already often pointed out that a so-called " causal " 
explanation, also, is nothing more than the statement or 
description of an actual fact or of a connexion between facts, 
and I might here simply refer to the detailed discussions 
in my Theory of Heat and my Popular Lectures. But, as 
people who have not made a special study of physics always 
believe that they broaden the basis and increase the 
profundity of their thought if they assume a fundamental 
difference between a scientific description (for instance, of 
the development of an embryo) and a physical explanation, 
1 Physical experiences other than mechanical may approach to the 
value of mechanical experiences as they become more familiar. In my 
opinion Strieker has advanced a correct and important view in bringing 
causality into connexion with the will (Studien tiber die Assoziation der 
Vorstellungen.) Vienna, 1883). When I was a young lecturer in 1861, 1 
myself advocated with great warmth and one-sidedness (in the exposition 
of Mill's method of difference) the view subsequently expressed by 
Strieker. And the idea has never quite left me (cp., for example, my 
Science of Mechanics, English trans., pp. 84, 304, 485.) However, I 
am at present of the opinion, as the above discussion shews, that this 
question is not so simple, and must be looked at from several sides, 
(Cp. Warmelehre, 2nd ed., 1900, p. 432.) 
336 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
I may perhaps be allowed to add a few more words on the 
subject. When we describe the growth of a plant, we 
notice that there comes into play such an immense variety 
of circumstances varying from one case to another, that it 
is only in the broader features at most that our description 
can hope to apply universally, while as regards the minuter 
details it can only be accurate for the individual case. 
This is exactly what happens in physics when the circum- 
stances are at all complicated; the only difference being 
that the circumstances are generally simpler and better 
known. That is why it is easier for us in physics to 
separate out the circumstances experimentally, and intel- 
lectually too, by means of abstraction. Schematization is 
easier. For the astronomers of antiquity, to describe the 
motion of the planets was a task analogous to what the 
description of a plant's development is for a modern 
botanist. The discovery of Kepler's laws depends upon 
a fortunate and fairly crude schematization. The more 
closely we consider a planet, the more individual does its 
movement become, and the less exactly does it follow 
Kepler's laws. Speaking strictly, all the planets move 
differently, and the same planet moves differently at 
different times. Now, when Newton gives a " causal 
explanation " of the planetary motions by shewing that one 
particle of mass m acquires through another particle m f the 
acceleration <p = -^, and that the accelerations deter- 
mined in the first particle by different particles are summed 
geometrically, he is only pointing out or describing facts, 
which, although by a roundabout path, yet have been 
reached by observation. Let us consider what the process 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 337 
is. The circumstances determining the planetary motions 
are first of all isolated from one another, that is to say, the 
individual particles of mass and their distances from one 
another. The relation between two particles of mass is 
very simple, and we think that we know all the circum- 
stances, mass and distance, that determine this relation. 
If we have a description which has been found to be 
correct for a few cases, we extend it beyond the limits of 
experience and assume it to be universally correct, at the 
same time disregarding the possibility of any disturbance 
from an unknown and alien cause ; in this, indeed, we may 
be mistaken, as we should be, for instance, if gravity were 
to turn out to be transferred through a medium and to 
require time for its transference. The modification of the 
relation is equally simple, as was pointed out, when to two 
particles a third is added, and to these a fourth, and so on. 
Thus Newton's description is not, in fact, the description of 
an individual case ; it is a description in terms of elements. 
Newton, in describing the way in which the elements of 
mass are related to one another in the elements of time, 
indicates to us how we can describe in terms of the elements 
any individual case we like, according to his pattern. It is 
just the same with all the other cases that theoretical physics 
has mastered. But this does not mean that the essence of 
the description is changed in any way. What we have to do 
with, is a general description in terms of elements. If we may 
remain satisfied with a representation of the phenomena by 
means of differential equations, a view which I long ago 
recommended (Mechanik, 1883, 4 tn e d, I 9 OI > P- 53)) an d 
which seems to be coming more and more into favor, 
this actually amounts to the recognition that explanation 
338 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
is nothing more than a description in terms of elements. 
Every particular case can then be put together out of spatial 
and temporal elements, the relations between which are 
described by equations. 
It was said above that man himself is a fragment of 
nature. Let me illustrate this by an example. For the 
chemist a substance may be sufficiently characterized merely 
by his sensations. In this case the chemist himself sup- 
plies, by inner means, the whole wealth of fact necessary 
to the determination of his course of thought. But, in 
other cases, recourse to reaction by the help of external 
means may be necessary. When an electric current flows 
round a magnetic needle situated in its plane, the north 
pole of the needle is deflected to my left, if I imagine 
myself as Ampere's swimmer in the current. I enrich the 
fact (current and needle) which is insufficient in itself to 
define the direction of my thought, by introducing myself 
into the experiment by an inner reaction. I may likewise 
lay my watch in the plane of the circuit, so that the hand 
moves in the direction of the current. Then the south 
pole falls in front of, the north pole behind the dial. Or 
I may make ^of the circuit traversed by the current a sun- 
dial (on the plan of which the watch in fact was modelled 1 ), 
so arranging it that the shadow follows the current. 
In this case the north pole will move towards the 
shadowed side of the plane of the current. The two 
last-mentioned reactions are outward reactions. The 
1 By the direction in which its hands move the watch proclaims its 
descent from the sun-dial and its discovery in the northern hemisphere. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 339 
two species of reactions could not be made use of indis- 
criminately if a chasm existed between myself and the 
world. Nature is a single whole. The fact that the two 
species of reaction are not known in all cases, and that 
frequently the observer appears to be entirely without in- 
fluence, proves nothing against the view advanced. 
Right and left appear to us to be similar, in contrast to 
before and behind, and to above and below. Yet it is 
certain that they are only different sensations, overwhelmed 
by stronger similar sensations. The space of sensation thus 
has three strongly marked and essentially different directions. 
From a metrical point of view all directions of geometrical 
space are identical. Our immediate sensation represents 
symmetrical shapes as equivalent ; but in physical respects 
they are by no means equivalent. Physical space also has 
three essentially different directions, which are most clearly 
manifested in a triclinal medium, in the behaviour of an 
electro-magnetic element. The same physical properties 
appear also in our own body, which is the reason why our 
bodies can be used as reagents in physical problems. If 
we had an exact physiological knowledge of an element of 
our bodies, we should thereby have laid, in all essentials, 
the foundation of our understanding of the physical 
universe. (Cp. p. 100.) 
[8. 
I have repeatedly emphasized the unity of the physical 
and the psychical, but it is worth while to consider this 
unity once more in one of its special aspects. Our psychical 
life, in so far as we mean by that term our presentations, 
seems to be perfectly independent of physical processes ; 
340 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
it seems to be a world in itself, with freer laws of its own, 
laws that are of a different order. But it is certain that 
this is a mere illusion, caused by the fact that only a very 
minute part of the traces of physical processes ever comes 
to life in our presentations. The circumstances determining 
this fragment are much too complicated to grasp, so that 
it is impossible to lay down any precise rule for its occur- 
rence. In order to determine what thoughts a physicist, 
for instance, will connect with the observation of a particular 
optical fact, we should have to know the previous events 
of his life, the force of the impressions which they have 
left behind them, and the facts of the development of 
general and technical culture by which he has been influ- 
enced ; and finally we should have to be in a position to 
take into account his mental disposition at the moment. 
To do all this, it would be necessary to enlist as an auxiliary 
the whole of physics, in its widest sense, and at an un- 
attainably high stage of development. 1 
Let us now consider the other side of the picture. A 
physical fact, which we experience for the first time, is 
strange to us. If it happened in some quite different way 
from that in which it actually happens, it would not thereby 
be any more puzzling. The way in which it occurs appears 
to us not to be determined by anything, least of all to be 
uniquely determined. What it is that invests the way in 
which a physical fact occurs with the character of deter- 
minateness, can only be understood from our psychical 
1 Thus, although my ideal of psychology is that it should be purely 
physiological, I should nevertheless think it a great mistake to reject 
so-called "introspective" psychology entirely. For self-observation 
is not only an important means, but in many cases is the only means 
of obtaining information as to fundamental facts. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 341 
development. The presentational part of our mental life 
is the agent which first draws the fact forth from its isola- 
tion, brings it into contact with an abundance of other 
facts, and then invests it with determinateness, in virtue of 
the necessity for agreement with those other facts and for 
he exclusion of contradiction. The science of psychology is 
auxiliary to physics. The two mutually support one another, 
and it is only when they are united that a complete science is 
formed. From our standpoint, the antithesis of subject and 
object, in the ordinary sense, does not exist. The question 
as to the greater or less degree of precision with which pre- 
sentations copy the facts, is, like every other question, a 
problem of natural science. 
19. 
Whenever it happens, in a complexus of elements, that 
some of the elements are replaced by others, then a con- 
stancy of connexion of one kind becomes a different kind. 
In such cases it is desirable to discover a constancy which 
survives this change. J. R. Mayer was the first to feel this 
need, and satisfied it by enunciating his concept of "force," 
which corresponds to the technical mechanical concept of 
"work" (Poncelet), or more exactly to the more general 
concept of " energy " (Young). Mayer conceives this force 
(or energy) as something absolutely constant (as a store of 
something, as a material), thus harking back to the most 
stubborn intuitive notions. We perceive, from Mayer's 
struggle with expressions, and with general philosophical 
phrases (noticeable in the first and second of his treatises), 
that he at first felt instinctively and intuitively the urgent 
need of such a concept. But his great achievement was 
342 H THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
accomplished only by his adapting the existing physical 
concepts to the requirements of the facts as well as to his 
needs. 1 
20. 
When the adaptation is adequate, the facts are spon- 
taneously reproduced by the thoughts, and incompletely 
given facts are completed. Physics can act only as a 
quantitative norm regulating and giving a more precise 
conformation to the spontaneously flowing thoughts, 
suitably to practical or scientific needs. When I see a 
body thrown horizontally, the intuitive picture of a pro- 
jectile in motion may rise before my mind. But the 
artilleryman or the physicist requires more. He must know, 
for example, that if on applying the measuring-rod M to the 
horizontal abscissae of the projectile's path, he can count to 
i, 2, 3, 4 . . . ., he must, on applying the measure M' to 
the vertical ordinates, also count to i, 4, 9, 16 . . . . in 
order to reach a point of the path. The function of physics 
consists, therefore, in teaching that a fact which, on a 
definite reaction R yields a sensory mark JE, also yields, on 
the giving of a different reaction J?', a second sensory mark 
E '. By this means it is possible to supply more exactly 
the deficiencies of incompletely given facts. 
The introduction into physics of the universally compar- 
able, or so-called " absolute " measurements, the reduction 
of all physical measurements to such units as the centimetre, 
the gramme, and the second (length, mass and time), has 
one peculiar result. There exists in any case a tendency to 
1 Cp. Prinzipien der Warmelehre, 2nd ed., 1900. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 343 
regard anything that can be physically grasped and measured, 
anything that can be stated in such a way as to become 
common property, as "objective" and "real," in contrast to 
the subjective sensations ; and the absolute measures appear 
to give some support to this opinion, and to supply it with a 
psychological, if not with a logical, motive. It looks as if what 
we call "sensations" in the familiar sense, were something 
quite superfluous in physics. Indeed, if we look closer, the 
system of units of measurement can be still further simplified. 
For the numerical measurement of mass is given by a ratio 
of accelerations, and measurement of time can be reduced 
to measurement of angles or lengths of arcs. Consequently 
measurement of lengths is the foundation of all measure- 
ments. But we do not measure mere space; we require 
a material standard of measurement, and with this the 
whole system of manifold sensations is brought back 
again. It is only intuitional sense-presentations that can 
lead to the formulation of the equations of physics, and it is 
precisely in such presentations that the interpretation of 
these equations consists. Thus, though the equations only 
contain spatial numerical measurements, these measure- 
ments, also, are merely the ordering principle which tells us 
out of what members of the series of sensational elements 
we have to construct our picture of the world. 
21. 
I have elsewhere 1 shewn that quantitative enunciations 
are only distinguished from qualitative by the fact that the 
former have reference to a continuum of homogeneous 
1 See Prinzipien der Wdrmelehre, pp. 438, 459. 
344 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
cases. on this view, the advantageous employment of 
equations for purposes of description would only be possible 
within a very limited field. There is, however, some pros- 
pect of enlarging this field by successive steps without any 
limit. This would be done in the following way. All 
possible optical sensations, though they cannot be 
measured, can be characterized and catalogued by means 
of numbers on psycho-physical methods. Thus any optical 
experience can be described by representing, by means of 
equations, the values of these numerical characteristics as 
dependent on the spatial and temporal co-ordinates, and on 
one another. And we shall have to hold that a result the 
same in principle can be obtained in the fields of the other 
senses also. Thus it is possible to assign a perfectly precise 
meaning to the expression used on p. 45 above. 
22. 
The ascertainment of the dependence of the elements 
A B C on one another, K L M being disregarded, is the task 
of natural science, or of physics in its broadest sense. But, 
in reality, the A B C's are always also dependent on K L M. 
There are always equations of the form f(A B C . . . 
KL M t . . .)= O. Now since many different observers 
K L M . . . , K' L r M' . . . , K" L" M" . . . are in- 
volved, we succeed in eliminating the accidental influence 
of the variation of K L M, etc., and we thus obtain only the 
element that can be stated as common property, namely the 
pure dependence of the A B C's on one another. In this 
process the KL M . . ., K f L' M' . . ., are treated like 
physical instruments, each with its peculiarities, its special 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 345 
constants, and so forth, from which the results, as finally in- 
dicated, have to be set free. But if it is a question merely 
of the temporal connexion of one quantitative reaction with 
other quantitative reactions, as in the above dynamical 
example, the matter is then still simpler. Everything then 
turns on the ascertainment of equality or identity of the 
A B C's under like circumstances, that is to say, under like 
K L M\ which comes to saying that everything turns 
merely on the ascertainment of spatial identities. The 
kind of quality of the sensations is now indifferent ; it is 
their equality that is alone decisive. And now a single 
individual suffices to fix relations of dependence which are 
valid for all individuals. Thus from this point onwards we 
have obtained a safe basis for the whole field of scientific 
research, a fact which inures to the advantage of psycho- 
physiology as well. 
23- 
The space of the geometrician is by no means merely the 
system of space-sensations (the senses of sight and touch), 
but consists rather of a body of conceptually idealized and 
formulated physical experiences, having the space-sensations 
as their point of departure. In the very fact of the geome- 
trician's regarding his space as being of the same nature 
at all points and in all directions, he goes far beyond the 
space given to sight and touch, which by no means possesses 
this simple property (pp. 1 68, 1 8 1 , sqq.). Without experience 
in physics the geometrician would never have reached this 
conception. The fundamental propositions of geometry 
have, as a fact, been acquired wholly by means of physical 
experiences, by the superposition of measures of length 
346 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
and of angles, by the application of rigid bodies to one 
another. Without propositions of congruence, no geometry. 
Apart from the fact that spatial images would not be pro- 
duced in us without physical experience, we should, even 
granting their existence, never be able to apply them to one 
another and to test their congruence. When we feel com- 
pelled to imagine an isosceles triangle as having equal angles 
at its base, our compulsion is due to the remembrance of 
powerful past experiences. If the proposition had its 
source in "pure intuition," there would be no necessity for 
learning it. That discoveries may be made by sheer power 
of geometrical imagination, and are so made daily, merely 
proves that the memory of a given experience can reveal to 
the mind features which in the original observation escaped 
unnoticed ; just as in the after-image of a bright lamp, new 
and previously unseen details may be discovered. Even the 
theory of numbers must be looked at in some such manner ; 
its fundamental propositions can hardly be viewed as en- 
tirely independent of physical experience. 
The cogency of geometry (and of all mathematics) is due, not 
to the fact that its theories are arrived at by some peculiar kind 
of knowledge, but only to the fact that its empirical material, 
which is particularly convenient and handy, has been put to 
the test very often, and can be put to the test again at any 
moment. Moreover, the province of space-experience is far 
more limited than that of the whole of experience. The con- 
viction of having in all essentials exhausted this limited pro- 
vince soon arises and produces the necessary self-confidence. 1 
1 Cp- Wdrmelehre, p. 455 ; Meinong, Hume-Studien, Vienna, 1877 ; 
Zindler, Beitr&ge ztir Theorie der mathematischen Erkenntnis y 
Vienna, 1889. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 347 
24. 
A self-confidence similar to that of the geometrician is 
doubtless also possessed by the composer and the decora- 
tive painter, who have both gained, the former in the 
domain of sensations of tone, the latter in that of sensations 
of color, a broad and rich experience. To the one no 
space-figure will occur the elements of which are not well 
known to him, and the two others will meet with no new 
combinations of tone or of color that are unfamiliar to 
them. But the inexperienced beginner in geometry will be 
no less surprised and disappointed by the results of his 
activity than the young musician or decorator. 
The mathematician, the composer, the decorator, and 
the student of natural science, when indulging in specula- 
tion, pursue quite analogous modes of procedure, despite 
the differences of their materials and aims. The mathe- 
matician, it is true, owing to his more limited material, has 
the advantage of the others as regards the certainty of his 
procedure ; while the latter for the opposite reason is at a 
disadvantage as compared with the others. 
25- 
The distinction between physiological and geometrical 
space has proved to be unavoidable. But while geome- 
trical insight is obtained by the spatial comparison of bodies 
with one another, time also cannot be left out of considera- 
tion, since it is impossible, in making such comparisons, to 
disregard the translation of bodies. Space and time stand 
348 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
in intimate connexion, thereby shewing themselves to be 
relatively independent of the other physical elements. This 
is expressed in the fact that when bodies move their other 
properties remain relatively constant. It is precisely owing 
to this fact that pure geometry and mechanics are possible. 
Space and time, closely considered, stand, as regards 
physiology, for special kinds of sensations ; but, as regards 
physics, they stand for functional dependencies upon one 
another of the elements characterized by the sensations. 
When the spatial and temporal physiological indices, 
conditioned by the parts and processes of our body, are 
compared with one another in like physiological circum- 
stances, we obtain relations of dependence of the physical 
elements on one another, that is, dependence of the 
elements of one body on those of another, and dependence 
of the elements of one process on those of another. on the 
basis of this result we can take the temporal and spatial 
determinations in a purely physical sense. Whatever 
coincides with the smaller part of a process which takes 
place continuously in one direction, is earlier in time. In 
a homogeneously filled space the position B is nearer than 
another position to the position A, when B is reached by 
the process starting from A earlier than the other position 
is reached. The straight line is the class-concept of the 
positions uniquely determined by the physical relations 
between two points, or infinitely small bodies. The 
position C is situated at the point of bisection of the 
straight line AB^ when, in homogeneous space, processes 
starting from A and B reach that position in equal times, 
and reach it in a shorter time than any other position with 
which it shares the first property. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 349 
26. 
The time of the physicist does not coincide with the 
system of time-sensations. When the physicist wishes to 
determine a period of time, he applies, as his standards of 
measurement, identical processes or processes assumed to 
be identical, such as vibrations of a pendulum, the rotations 
of the earth, etc. The fact connected with the time-sensa- 
tion is in this manner made the subject of a reaction, and 
the result of this reaction, the number which is obtained, 
serves, in place of the time-sensation, to determine more 
exactly the subsequent movement of the thought. In like 
manner, we regulate our thoughts concerning thermal pro- 
cesses not according to the sensation of warmth which 
bodies yield us, but according to the much more definite 
sensation which is obtained from thermometrical reactions 
by simply noting the height of the mercury. Usually a 
space-sensation (a rotation-angle of the earth, or the path 
of the hand on the dial of a clock) is substituted for the 
sensation of time, and for this, again, a number is put. 
For example, if we represent the excess of the temperature of 
a cooling body over that of its surroundings by S = T~**, 
then t is this number. 
The relation in which the quantities of an equation stand, 
is usually (analytically) a more general one than that which is 
meant to be represented by the equation. Thus in the equa- 
tion (x/a) 2 + ( yjb) 2 = i all possible values of x have an analyti- 
cal meaning, and yield corresponding values of y. But if the 
equation be used to represent an ellipse, then only the values 
of x < a and y < b have a geometrical (or real) significance. 
350 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Similarly, it would have to be expressly added, if this 
were not obvious, that the equation S = ** represents 
the real process only for increasing values of t. 
If we imagine the natural course of different events, say 
the cooling of one body and the free descent of a second, 
represented by equations involving time, then time may be 
eliminated from these equations, and we may express, for 
example, the excess of temperature by means of the space 
traversed by the falling body. Thus viewed, the elements 
appear simply as dependent on one another. But the 
meaning of such an equation would have to be more 
exactly denned by adding that only increasing distances of 
descent or decreasing temperatures are to be inserted 
successively therein. 
When we thus think of excess of temperature as deter- 
mined by the space traversed by a falling body, the 
dependence is not an immediate one. on this point I 
agree with Petzoldt. 1 But the dependence is no more 
immediate when we assume excess of temperature to be 
determined by the angle of rotation of the earth. For no 
one will believe that the same temperature- values would 
continue to correspond to the same angular values, if the 
earth were to alter its velocity of rotation in consequence of 
some shock. But it seems to me to follow from such con- 
siderations that our postulates are merely provisional, and 
depend upon partial ignorance of the decisive part played by 
certain independent variables which are inaccessible to us. 
It is only in this sense that I would wish the reference which 
I once made to a certain absence of determination, to be under- 
1 Petzoldt, " Das Gesetz der Eindeutigkeit," Vierteljahrcsschrift fur 
TV is sense ha ft lie he Philosophic. Vol. XIX., pp. 146 sqq. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 351 
stood. 1 This view, moreover, is perfectly compatible with the 
postulation of unique determinations, since such postulates 
are always laid down on the assumption of given circumstances, 
and with abstraction from unusual and unexpected changes. 
This way of looking at the matter is, as it seems to me, in- 
evitable, when we reflect that the distinction emphasized by 
Petzoldt between simultaneous and successive dependencies, 
holds for intuitional presentation, but not for the equations 
which are the norms regulating presentation quantitatively. 
The equations can only be of one kind, and can only express 
simultaneous dependencies. Towards indeterminism in the 
ordinary sense, the assumption, for instance, of .freedom 
of the will in the sense used by many philosophers and 
theologians, I have not the slightest inclination. 
Time is not reversible. A warm body set in cool sur- 
roundings merely cools, and does not grow warm again. 
With larger, or later, time-sensations only smaller decreasing 
excesses of temperature are connected. A house in flames 
burns down but never builds itself up again. A plant does 
not decrease in size and creep into the earth, but grows out 
of it, increasing in size. The irreversibility of time reduces 
itself to the fact that the alterations in the values of physical 
quantities always take place in definite directions. Of the 
two analytical possibilities one only is actual. We do not 
need to see in this fact a metaphysical problem. 
Changes can only be determined by differences. Where 
there are no distinctions there is no determination. The 
supervening change may increase the distinctions or it may 
1 Mach, History and Root of the Principle of the Conservation of 
Energy, translated by P. E. B. Jourdain, Chicago, Open Court Publish- 
ing Co., 1911. 
352 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
diminish them. But if the differences had a tendency to 
increase, change would go on endlessly and aimlessly. 
The only assumption compatible with a general representa- 
tion of the universe, or rather with the representation of 
our own limited environment, is that of a tendency, on the 
whole, to a diminution of differences. But if circumstances 
that set up differences did not make themselves felt by 
forcing their way into our environment, a time would soon 
come when nothing more would happen at all. 
Again, we can conclude, with Petzoldt, from our own 
existence and from our bodily and spiritual stability, to 
the stability and to the uniqueness, as regards determina- 
tion and direction, of the processes of nature. For not 
only are we ourselves a fragment of nature (p. 338 above), 
but it is the presence of these very properties in our en- 
vironment that determines our existence and our thought 
(see Popular Scientific Lectures, 3rd edition, p. 250). But it 
will not do to build too confidently on this foundation, for 
organisms are peculiar fragments of nature, of very limited 
and moderate stability, which in point of fact are liable to de- 
struction, and for the preservation of which a proportionately 
moderate amount of stability in the environment is sufficient. 
The most convenient course will therefore be to recognize the 
limits which are everywhere manifestly set to our knowledge, 
and to regard the effort towards unique determination as an 
ideal, which, so far as may be, we actualize in our thought. 
I do not, of course, regard the statements which I wrote 
down at the time of my greatest intellectual ferment (1871), 
as secure against all attack, particularly as regards their 
form ; nor do I by any means consider that Petzoldt's 
objections are dictated by a spirit of captiousness. I hope, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 353 
however, that when I deal with the subject again at greater 
length, for I have only been able to touch upon it briefly 
here, I shall be able to bring about a full understanding, 
without at the same time giving up any essential part of 
my view. 1 
1 My recently published book, Erkenntnis undlrrtum (1905), contains 
further discussions of the question. See, in particular, pp. 426-440. 
XV. 
HOW MY VIEWS HAVE BEEN 
RECEIVED. 
i. 
WHEN the first edition of this book was published, 
opinions about it were greatly divided. But in 
the great majority of cases, it was points of detail that 
found acceptance, in so far as the reception was favorable, 
-while the fundamental views which had led to the details 
were for the most part rejected. All the public criticism 
that I have seen has preserved a tone of moderation, even 
when it has been hostile, and, in its outspokenness, has 
been extremely instructive to me. 1 
There is no mistaking the favorable influence which 
the later publications of Richard Avenarius have exercised 
on the estimation of my book. It surely gives much food 
for thought, when we find a professional philosopher 
1 That private judgments had been equally moderate I should not 
have believed, even if certain small indiscretions had not given me 
evidence to the contrary. A more than contemptuous judgment of a 
German colleague was communicated to me by a curiously roundabout 
path let us say more or less by way of the Antipodes with the un- 
mistakable intention of giving me pain. This object, to be sure, was 
not attained. For it would certainly be very unfair if I were to refuse 
to others the right, which I exercise often enough myself, of neglecting 
work that I consider unprofitable. To be sure, I have never felt it 
necessary to insult people whose opinions differ from my own. 
354 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 355 
establishing in an elaborate systematic treatise a position 
which, when taken up by a scientist, there has been a 
disposition to explain away as the aberration of a dilettante. 
To-day Avenarius' pupils, and many younger inquirers who 
have drawn near to my position by paths of their own, 
are standing at my side as allies. Nevertheless, all the 
critics, with few exceptions, including those who reproduce 
my fundamental ideas quite correctly and have certainly 
understood them, cannot help feeling serious objections to 
them. There is nothing surprising in this ; for I make 
great demands on the plasticity of my readers. It is one 
thing to understand an idea logically, and another to take 
it up in a sympathetic spirit. The ordering and simplifying 
function of logic can, indeed, only begin when psychical 
life is in an advanced stage of development and can 
already boast a rich store of instinctive acquisitions. Now 
it is scarcely possible to attain to this instinctive pre-logical 
nucleus of acquisitions by logical means. It is much more 
a question of a process of psychical transformation, which, 
as I found in my own case, is difficult enough even in 
youth. It would therefore be too much to count on 
immediate agreement here. on the contrary, I am satisfied 
to be merely allowed a hearing at all, and to be listened to 
without prepossessions. I will now, following the impres- 
sions I have received from my critics, once more bring out 
and illustrate those points of which the reception has been 
most strenuously opposed. In doing this, I shall treat the 
objections that have been urged as typical objections, with 
nothing captious or personal about them, and I shall there- 
fore not mention any names. 
356 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Unless we subject ourselves to a certain compulsion, we 
see the earth as standing still, and the sun and the fixed 
stars in motion. This way of looking at the matter is not 
merely sufficient for ordinary practical purposes, but is also 
the simplest and most advantageous. But the opposite 
view has established itself as the more convenient for certain 
intellectual purposes. Although both are equally correct 
and equally well-adapted to their special purpose, the 
second view only succeeded in gaining acceptance after a 
severe combat with a power hostile to science, a power 
which in this case was in alliance with the instinctive 
conceptions of ordinary people. But to ask that the 
observer should imagine himself as standing upon the sun 
instead of upon the earth, is a mere trifle in comparison 
with the demand that he should consider the Ego to be 
nothing at all, and should resolve it into a transitory 
connexion of changing elements. It is true that on various 
sides, the way has long been prepared for this conception. 1 
We see such unities as we call " I " produced by generation 
and vanishing in death. Unless we indulge ourselves in 
the fiction, so fantastic nowadays, that these unities existed 
before birth in a latent state, and will similarly continue to 
exist after death, we can only suppose that they are just 
temporary unities. Psychology and psycho-pathology teach 
1 Cp. the standpoint of Hume and Lichtenberg. For thousands of 
years past Buddhism has been approaching this conception from the 
practical side. Cp. Paul Carus, The, Gospel of Buddha, Chicago, 1894. 
Cp. also the wonderful story unfolded by the same writer in Karma, A 
Story of Early Buddhism^ Chicago, 1894. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 357 
us that the Ego can grow and be enriched, can be 
impoverished and shrink, can become alien to itself, and 
can split up, in a word, can change in important respects 
in the course of its life. In spite of all this, the Ego is 
what is most important and most constant for my instinctive 
conceptions. It is the bond that holds all my experiences 
together, and the source of all my activity. In just the 
same way, again, a rigid body is something very constant 
for our crude instinctive conceptions. If it is divided, 
dissolved, or chemically combined with another body, the 
number of these constancies increases and diminishes. 
Then, in order to hold fast at any price to the notion that 
has become so dear to us, we assume latent constancies, 
and take refuge in atomism. Inasmuch as we are often 
able to restore again the body which has disappeared or 
changed, this procedure rests upon somewhat better 
grounds than in the case of the Ego. 
Now in practice we can as little do without the Ego- 
presentation when we act, as we can do without the 
presentation of a body when we grasp at a thing. Physio' 
logically we remain egoists and materialists, just as we 
always see the sun rise again. But theoretically this way 
of looking at the matter cannot be maintained. Let us 
change it by way of experiment. If in doing so we obtain 
a glimpse of the truth, it will in the long run bear practical 
fruits as well. 
Anyone who has at some time or another been influenced 
by Kant, anyone who has adopted an idealistic standpoint, 
and has been unable to get rid of the last traces of the 
358 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
notion of the "thing in itself," retains a certain inclination 
towards solipsism, which will appear more or less clearly. 
Having been through it in my early youth, I know this 
condition of mind well, and can easily understand it. The 
philosophical thinker proceeds to make the single problem 
of the Ego, a problem which is in principle insoluble, 
the starting-point for everything else. The Ego is some- 
thing given to us, we cannot transcend it and get away from 
it. When, therefore, speculative philosophers say " Solipsism 
is the only logically consistent standpoint," their utterance 
is quite intelligible in view of their struggle to reach a 
closed, all-inclusive, complete system of the universe. To 
be sure, we ought to add that materialism also is equally 
consistent for anyone who believes that matter is the only 
thing that is immediately given, and that cannot be further 
explained. This, indeed, is true of all systems. But when 
a man of science tells me that solipsism is the only con- 
sistent standpoint, he excites my astonishment. I will not 
emphasize the fact that this standpoint is better suited 
to a fakir who dreams his life away in contemplation, 
than to a serious, thoughtful and active man. But what I 
do believe is that the man of science who inclines this way 
is making a confusion between philosophical and scientific 
methods. The man of science is not looking for a com- 
pleted vision of the universe ; he knows beforehand that all 
his labor can only go to broaden and deepen his insight. 
For him there is no problem of which the solution would 
not still require to be carried deeper; but there is also 
no problem which he can regard as absolutely insoluble. 
If it is impossible for the time being to make any 
impression on a problem, he solves in the meanwhile 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 359 
others that are more accessible. If he then returns to 
the original problem, it has generally lost much of its 
terrifying appearance. 
No doubt the Ego is not exhausted, if we say, quite 
provisionally, that it consists in a peculiar connexion of the 
elements, as long as the nature of this connexion is not 
investigated in detail. But the special problems that are 
relevant here will not be solved by speculation j their solu- 
tion will be found by the psychologists, physiologists, and 
psychiatrists, to whom we already owe many important 
elucidations of such problems. The physical substratum 
of the Ego, the body, 1 will afford many points of reference 
which introspective psychology can only handle in a very im- 
perfect manner. A man of science who should be a solipsist 
would be like a physicist for whom the thermometer was 
the fundamental problem of the universe, because on any 
particular day he did not happen to have a perfectly clear 
understanding of the influence of temperature on expansion. 
on the other hand, the philosopher who is a solipsist seems 
to me to be like the man who gave up turning round 
because whatever he saw was always in front of him. As 
to the instinctive, but untenable, splitting up of the Ego 
into an object experienced and an active or observing 
subject, a problem which has tormented everybody long 
enough, anyone who wishes to think out these questions 
may compare pp. 25-29 above. 
1 But what is in question here is not a transcendental, unknowable 
Ego, which many philosophers perhaps still think it impossible to 
eliminate as a last remnant of the thing-in-itself, although, generally 
speaking, they have risen superior to that notion by now. 
360 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
Whoever cannot get rid of the conception of the Ego as 
a reality which underlies everything, will also not be able 
to avoid drawing a fundamental distinction between my 
sensations and your sensations. In the same way, whoever 
believes in the absolute constancy of a body, thinks of this 
body as the single vehicle of all its properties. But when 
this silvery-white piece of sodium is melted, and dissolves 
in steam which looks absolutely different from the original 
thing ; when the sodium is divided into different parts and 
transferred to different chemical combinations, so that 
more, or even fewer, bodies are present than before ; then 
our habitual manner of thought can only be preserved by 
extremely artificial devices. It then becomes more advan- 
tageous to regard the particular properties as belonging 
sometimes to one and sometimes to another complex, or 
body, and to substitute, for the bodies that are not constant, 
the law which is constant and which survives the change of 
the properties and of their connexions. Here again, it is 
making no small demand, to ask that this new habit of 
thought should be adopted. How the thinkers of antiquity 
would have protested, if someone had said to them, " Earth, 
water and air are not constant bodies at all; what are 
constant are the modern chemical elements of which they 
are composed, many of which elements cannot be seen, 
while others can only be isolated or fixed with great diffi- 
culty. Fire is not a body at all, but a process," and so on. 
We are scarcely able to estimate correctly nowadays the 
magnitude of the change which lies in this step. Yet in 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 361 
modern chemistry a further transformation in this direction 
is being prepared, and the same methods of abstraction 
lead in due course to the standpoint which is adopted here. 
From the standpoint which I here take up for purposes of 
general orientation, I no more draw an essential distinction 
between my sensations and the sensations of another person, 
than I regard red or green as belonging to an individual 
body. The same elements are connected at different points 
of attachment, namely the Ego's. But these points of 
attachment are not anything constant. They arise, they 
perish, and are incessantly being modified. But where 
there is no connexion at a given moment, there is also no 
perceptible reciprocal influence. Whether it may or may not 
prove possible to transfer someone else's sensations to me by 
means of nervous connexions, my view is not affected one 
way or the other. The most familiar facts provide a sufficient 
basis for this view. 
Perhaps even more than in my fundamental ideas, many 
readers have found a stumbling-block in what they took, 
erroneously indeed, to be the general character of my 
conception of the universe. And, to begin with, I must 
say that anyone who, in spite of repeated protests from 
myself and from other quarters, identifies my view with 
that of Berkeley, is undoubtedly very far removed from a 
proper appreciation of my position. 1 This misconception 
1 Shall once again state the difference in a word ? Berkeley regards 
the ' ' elements " as conditioned by an unknown cause external to 
them (God) ; accordingly Kant, in order to appear as a sober realist, 
invents the " thing-in-itself " ; whereas, on the view which I advocate, 
a dependence of the "elements" on one another is theoretically and 
362 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
is no doubt partly due to the fact that my view was de- 
veloped from an earlier idealistic phase, which has left on 
my language traces which are probably not even yet entirely 
obliterated. For, of all the approaches to my standpoint, 
the one by way of idealism seems to me the easiest and 
most natural. And connected with this is the fear of 
pan-psychism, which at the same time seizes my readers. 
Many are the victims that fall a prey to pan-psychism, in the 
desperate struggle between a monistic conception of the uni- 
verse and instinctive dualistic prejudices. In my early youth 
I had to work through these tendencies myself, and Avenarius 
was still labouring at them in his book of 1876. As regards 
these two points, I feel it to be a piece of particularly good 
fortune that Avenarius has developed the same conception of 
the relation between the physical and psychical on an entirely 
realistic, or, if the phrase be preferred, a materialistic founda- 
tion, so that I need do no more than refer to his discussions. 
6. 
My world of elements, or sensations, strikes not only men 
of science, but also professional philosophers, as too un- 
practically all that is required. It seems to me that, in the interpreta- 
tion of Kant, his very natural and psychologically intelligible fear of 
being considered fantastic, has not been sufficiently taken into account. 
It is only from this point of view that we can understand how, while 
holding that only those concepts had meaning and value which were 
applicable to a possible experience, he could posit a thing in itself, of 
which no experience is conceivable. Over against the particular sensation, 
the plain man and the man of science both set the thing as a presentational 
complex of all the experiences, whether remembered or still expected, 
which are connected with the sensation in question ; and this procedure 
is extremely shrewd. But for anyone who has assimilated Kant's way 
of thinking, it becomes meaningless at the limits of experience. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 363 
substantial. When I treat matter as a mental symbol 
standing for a relatively stable complex of sensational 
elements, this is described as a conception which does not 
make enough of the material world. The external world, 
it is felt, is not adequately expressed as a sum of sensa- 
tions ; in addition to the actual sensations, we ought at 
least to bring in Mill's possibilities of sensation. In reply 
to this, I must observe that for me also the world is not 
a mere sum of sensations. Indeed, I speak expressly of 
functional relations of the elements. But this conception 
not only makes Mill's "possibilities" superfluous, but re- 
places them by something much more solid, namely the 
mathematical concept of function. Had I ever dreamt 
that a short, precise expression would be so easily over- 
looked, and that a popular exposition on broad lines 
would have been more useful, some such exposition as 
that which H. Cornelius 1 has so admirably given " on the 
concept of objective existence," would have served my 
purpose. In any case, even here I should have avoided 
the expression "possibility," and should have substituted 
for it the concept of function. 
From expressions used in other quarters, it would appear 
that the true explanation of my position is to be sought in 
an exaggerated sensationalism, and in a correspondingly 
inadequate understanding of the value of abstraction and 
conceptual thought. Now, without a fairly well-marked 
sensationalism a man of science cannot accomplish much. 
But this does not prevent him from forming clear and pre- 
cise concepts. on the contrary. The concepts of modern 
1 Psychologic als Erfahrungswissenschaft, Leipzig, 1897, p. 99, and 
particularly pp. noand in. 
364 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
physics will stand comparison, in point of precision and 
height of abstraction, with those of any other science ; 
but they offer at the same time the advantage that they 
can always be traced back with ease and certainty to the 
sensational elements on which they are built up. For 
science the gulf between intuitional presentation and con- 
ceptual thought is not so great, and is not unbridgeable. 
I may remark in passing that I am far from thinking 
meanly of the concepts of physics ; for nearly forty years 
I have been occupied with the criticism of them in various 
ways, and with greater thoroughness than they have re- 
ceived before. And since my results are gradually, after 
long resistance, finding acceptance with physicists, it will 
perhaps be allowed that this is no cheap and facile agree- 
ment. When the physicist, whose training has accustomed 
him to having a kilogram weight pressed into his hand 
with every definition, gradually expresses himself as 
satisfied with definitions which reduce everything to a 
functional relation of sensational elements, the philosopher 
will surely not want to be even more of a physicist than 
the physicist. Naturally, however, there is no room for 
the necessary working out of details in this sketch, which 
is intended to be merely a programme for the closer 
connexion of the exact sciences with one another; for 
further information the reader must be referred to my 
works on physics. It would, indeed, be highly pre- 
sumptuous of me to assume even that all physicists are 
acquainted with these works, much more that they are 
familiar to people who are not professional physicists ; yet 
it is partly want of familiarity with my works which has 
made it possible for me to be accused, for instance, 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 365 
of having entirely overlooked the " spontaneity " and 
"autonomy" of thought. Even towards bare sensations 
our attitude is not one of mere passivity; for sensations 
disengage a biological reaction, of which the natural con- 
tinuation is precisely the adaptation of thought to facts. 
If this adaptation were immediately and perfectly success- 
ful, the process would ipso facto come to an end. But 
since different imperfectly adapted thoughts come into 
conflict with one another, the biological process continues. 
What I have called the adaptation of thoughts to one 
another takes place. Now I should really like to know 
what process of scientific development, the logical process 
included, is not covered by this statement ? Here I may 
be permitted to break off for the present these controversial 
remarks, in which I have only been forced to repeat what 
I have frequently said and have long been saying. 
To many readers the universe, as conceived by me, 
seems to be a chaos, a hopelessly tangled web of elements, 
They feel the want of leading and unifying points of view. 
But this depends on a misinterpretation of the task that I 
have set myself. All points of view, which are of value 
for the special sciences and for the philosophical considera- 
tion of the world, remain capable of further application, 
and indeed, are^ so applied by me. The apparently 
destructive tendency of the work is merely directed against 
superfluous, and therefore misleading, additions to our 
concepts. Thus I believe that the contrasts between the 
psychical and the physical, and between subjective and 
366 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
objective, have been correctly reduced by me to what 
is essential in them, and at the same time have been 
purged of traditional and superstitious conceptions. And 
this has been done in such a way that scientifically es- 
tablished points of view are not altered, and at the same 
time, room is made for new points of view. I have no 
desire to set up, in the place of the lamentations of 
a piously whining " Ignorabimus," an obstinately self- 
sufficient attitude of rejection of everything that is worth 
knowing and that can be known. For to refuse to attempt 
answers to questions that have been recognized as meaning- 
less, is in no sense an act of resignation ; in view of the 
mass of material that can really be investigated, it is the 
only reasonable course open to a man of science. The 
physicist who refrains from seeking for the secret of per- 
petual motion, need not nowadays regard this as an act of 
resignation, any more than the mathematician, who no 
longer troubles himself about the squaring of the circle, 
or the solution of equations of the fifth degree in closed 
algebraical form. So, too, with more general philosophical 
questions : the problems are either'solved, or are recognized 
as pointless. 
" In what exactly does the fallacy, or the bias, of Mach's 
philosophical views consist ? " This question, which one of 
my critics asks, strikes me as very harmless. For I am 
convinced that my exposition is full of defects in more 
than one direction. This, indeed, can scarcely be avoided 
when a writer's views are undergoing a radical process of 
revolution, for even a single head cannot work out such 
a process completely to its conclusion. Hence, though I 
can feel these faults, I cannot put my finger on them. If 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 367 
I could, I should be a long way further advanced towards 
my goal. But neither have I been able to obtain a clear 
view of my faults from the writings of my critics. Let us, 
therefore, wait a little longer. 
Arguments have been brought against my views, which 
have been fully discussed both in this book and in other 
writings of mine ; but I do not state this fact with a desire 
to reproach anybody. It must be a real torture to have to 
read everything that is published, and, what is more, to 
have to pass judgment conscientiously and deliberately in 
a brief allotted time. I have never discovered in myself 
any taste for this important vocation, and consequently I 
have only written three reviews, all told, in a period of forty 
years. So I do not grudge it to the reviewers, that they 
should have saved themselves a certain amount of trouble, 
even though it has been partly at my expense. I hope they 
will not take it ill on my part, if I do not re-act to every sally 
and to every sarcasm which they fancy has hit its mark. 
Honigswald, however, has subsequently devoted a book 
to my standpoint (Zur Kritik der Machschen Philosophic, 
Berlin, 1903). I must admit that he has taken the trouble 
to read my books ; nor have I the least objection to make 
to a criticism which decides that my position is incom- 
patible with Kant's. Not all philosophers will draw the 
inference that my position must therefore be untenable. 
My relations to Kant have been peculiar. His critical 
idealism was, as I recognize with the greatest gratitude, 
the starting-point of all my critical thought; but it was 
impossible for me to retain my allegiance to it. I very 
soon began to gravitate again towards the views of Berkeley, 
which are contained, in a more or less latent form, in Kant's 
368 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
writings. By studying the physiology of the senses, and 
by reading Herbart, I then arrived at views akin to those 
of Hume, though at that time I was still unacquainted 
with Hume himself. To this very day I cannot help 
regarding Berkeley and Hume as far more logically con- 
sistent thinkers than Kant. It is not the business of a 
man of science to criticize or refute a philosopher like 
Kant, though it may be observed in passing that it would 
no longer be a particularly heroic achievement to shew the 
inadequacy of Kant's philosophy as a guide to modern 
scientific research. This has long since been effected by 
the progress that has been made in all departments, in- 
cluding philosophy itself. When Honigswald enunciates a 
number of general points of view, and proceeds to elicit 
from them a closed philosophical system, he completely 
misapprehends the cautiously tentative methods of ap- 
proximation employed by science. The constants of the 
man of science are not absolutely constant, nor, on the 
other hand, do the changes which he investigates correspond 
to the limitless flux of Herakleitos. I call biological aims 
11 practical," when they are not directed to pure knowledge 
as an end in itself. only consider what the position of 
the man of science would be, if, before he began to think, 
he had to refute all the philosophical systems one by one. 
once more, there is no such thing as "the philosophy of 
Mach." 1 
8. L/ 
Whether I shall ever succeed in making my fundamental 
ideas plausible to the philosophers, I must leave to time to 
1 Cf. Erkenntnis und It rtum, 1905, Preface. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 369 
decide. I do not attach much importance to this at 
present, though I have a deep reverence for the gigantic 
intellectual labors of the great philosophers of all ages. But 
I have an honest and lively desire for an understanding with 
the natural scientists, and I consider that such an under- 
standing is attainable. I should like the scientists to 
realize that my view eliminates all metaphysical questions 
indifferently, whether they be only regarded as insoluble 
at the present moment, or whether they be regarded as 
meaningless for all time. I should like them, further, to 
reflect that everything that we can know about the world is 
necessarily expressed in the sensations, which can be set 
free from the individual influence of the observer in a 
precisely definable manner (p. 344 above). Everything that 
we can want to know is given by the solution of a problem 
in mathematical form, by the ascertainment of the functional 
dependence of the sensational elements on one another. 
This knowledge exhausts the knowledge of "reality." The 
bridge between physics, in the widest sense, and scientific 
psychology, is formed of these very elements, which are 
physical and psychical objects according to the kind of 
combination that is being investigated. 
A 7 SI 
Probably a good many physiologists have taken objection 
to a point of detail in my position, as to which I should 
like to say something more. I have a great value for re- 
searches such as those of S. Exner, 1 and I believe that 
1 Entwurf zu einer physiologischen Erkldrung der psychischen 
Erscheinungen, Vienna, 1894. 
370 THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 
many important problems as to psychical phenomena can 
be solved merely by the investigation of the nervous con- 
nexions of the central organs, 1 and by observation of the 
way in which stimuli are arranged in a quantitative scale. 2 
Indeed Exner's book itself is evidence of this. But I feel 
that the main problems still remain unsolved. For, from 
my point of view, I cannot conceive, any more than I could 
nearly forty years ago, how the qualitative variety of sensa- 
tions can arise from the variation of the connexions and 
from mere quantitative differences. Fechner's psycho- 
physics, which have had so important an influence, did 
not fail to stimulate me exceedingly at the time. Inspired 
by Fechner's book, I delivered some very bad lectures on 
the subject, the value of my lectures being still further 
diminished by the fact that I soon came to see that Fechner's 
theory of formulae of measurement was erroneous. In this 
connexion, after explaining Helmholtz's " telegraph-wire " 
theory of sensation, I said : " But will the electric processes 
in the nerves prove to be too simple to explain adequately 
the difference of quality in sensations ? Will it be necessary 
to thrust the explanation further back into regions that are 
still unknown ? What if, after investigating the whole brain, 
we find everywhere nothing but electric currents? My 
personal opinion is this. The electrical researches that 
have been made on the nerves are no doubt of a very 
delicate nature, but in one respect they are very rough. 
An electric current of given intensity tells us nothing, 
except that a definite quantity of living force passes in the 
time-unit through a cross-section of the current. By what 
1 Entiuurf zu einer physiologischen Erklarwng der psychischen Erschei- 
nungen, p. 4, Vienna, 1894. 2 Op. cit.> p. 3. 
THE ANALYSIS OF SENSATIONS 371 
processes and by what molecular movements that living 
force is assisted, we do not know. It is possible that the 
most diverse processes underlie one and the same intensity 
of current." 1 Even to-day I have not succeeded in getting 
rid of this idea, and I cannot refrain from bringing forward 
evidence that confirms it in essentially the same form, as 
for instance by referring to the presence of an identical 
current in different electrolytes. 2 The progress of physio- 
logical chemistry, 3 and the experiments that have been made 
in the transplantation of different organs, 4 seem to me to-day 
to be still more decisively in favor of my view. Rollett 5 
has brought into connexion with one another, and discussed 
in a very instructive manner, with reference both to his own 
work and to that of others, a number of important questions 
closely related to the discussions of this book. 
1 " Vorlesungen iiber Psychophysik," Zeitschrijt fiir praktische 
Heilkunde, pp. 335, 336, Vienna, 1863. 
2 See the preface to the preceding English edition of this book, 
Chicago, 1897, pp. v, vi. 
3 Huppert, Ueber die Erhaltung der Arteigenschaften, Prague, 1896. 
4 Ribbert, " Ueber Transplantation von Ovarium, Hoden, und 
Mamma," Archivfur Entioicklungsmechanik, 1898, Vol. VII. 
5 " Entwicklungslehre und spezifische Energie," Mittcihtngen des 
Vereins der Aerzte in Steiermark^ 1902, No. 8. 
INDEX 
I 
INDEX OF SUBJECTS 
Abstraction, what is it ? 325 
Adaptation, mental, 328, 365 
Acceleration, sensation of, 133, 
139 sqq. 
organ reacting on, 165 
Accommodation of the eye, 
how effected, 228 sqq. 
After-images, 131, 252 
Animals, asymmetry in, 113 
intelligence of exaggerated, 
196 
reflex movements in, 171 
sqq., 196, 198 
measurement of time by, 250 
Animism, 97 
Anthropomorphism, 97 
Ants, 78 n. 
Apoplectic stroke, effect of, on 
author, 175 
Art, symmetry in, 117 sqq. 
Association, 100, 174, 235-244, 
264 
inertia of, 253 
Astronomers, personal equation 
of, 251 
Asymmetry, 112 
Attention, 178 sqq. 
Atoms, 311 
Biology, connexion of, with 
physics, 84 sqq. 
Blind, the, space-sensations of, 
118, 135, 139, 180, 187 
Bodies, permanency and 
rigidity of, 191 
" Body," what is it ? 13, 32, 
329, 330 
| Cats, experiments on, 159 
Causal explanations, meaning 
of, 335-338 
Causality, 85 sqq. 
\ Change, 351 
Chick, the, 126, 171, 179, 188 
Color-adaptation, 95 
Color-sensations, 64-69, 103 
sqq. 
connexion of, with space- 
sensations, 105 
" Concealed movements," 313 
Concepts, what are they ? 321- 
327 
physical, 364 
Congruence, 346 
geometrical and optical, 107 
Consciousness, organ of, 257 
Conservation of energy, 55 n. 
Consonance, 272 sqq. 
Consumption, organic, con- 
nexion of, with time- 
sensation, 256 
Continuity, principle of, 57, 
319 
Crustacea, experiments on, 157 
Cyclostat, 149 
2 A 
373 
374 
INDEX 
D Frog, reflex movements in the, 
97, 158, 183, 241 
Deaf-mutes, vertigo in, 159 Function, notion of, in physics 
sqq. and biology, 93 
Doves, experiments on, 158 i mathematical concept of, 
Dreams, u, 253-255, 281 363 
anachronisms in, 253 Functional relations, 35 
Ear, middle, function of, in 
hearing, 299 sqq. 
Echidna, 164 
Economy of thought, 49, 328 
Ego, the, apparent permanency 
self -inspection of, 20 
-- not primary, 23 
-- impermanence of, 357 
sqq. 
Egyptian drawings, 232 
Electricity, 93 
Elements (sensations), 8 sqq., 
1 3*??., 35 
-- dependence of, on one 
another, 344 
Embryology, experimental, 95 
Emotions, 21 
influence of, on time-sensa- 
tion, 261 
Energy, 341 
Equilibrium, function of laby- 
rinth of the ear in, 162 
sqa, 
Evolution, bearing of, on 
physiology, 71 sqq. 
theory of, as scientific 
hypothesis, 79 
Eye, motor apparatus of, no 
sqq. 
experiments with the, 128 
reflex movements of the, 
132 sqq. 
Force, 341 
Freedom of the will, 351 
Galvanotropic reaction, 159 
Genius, definition of, 308 
I Geometrical space, 120, 168, 
181, 345 
Geometry, Greek and Indian, 
1 20 
i Ghosts, fear of, 75 
i Guinea-pigs, behaviour of, when 
deprived of labyrinths, 161 
sqq. 
H 
Harmony, function of contrast 
in, 288 
Hawk-moth, 85 
; Hearing, Helmholtz' theory of, 
266 sqq. 
i author's suggested theory of, 
291 sqq. 
| Ewald's theory of, 301 
i Heredity, 72, 77, 308 
Heterodromous processes, 68, 
253 
Homodromous processes, 68 
Horopter, Miiller's, 125 
i Horses, deficiency of, in sense 
of time, 260 
Idealism, 357, 362, 367 
Illusions, explanation of, 1 1 
visual, 202-208, 220-231, 
2343 255 
auditory, 255 
; Images, mental, 200 
INDEX 
375 
Images, mental, how deter- 
mined, 201 sqq. 
Immortality, 25 
Impulses, innate, 239 
Innervation, 173-176 sqq. 
and the will, 165-167 
of muscles of the eye, 169 
Insects, retina of, 228 
Intellect, definition of, 196 
Intervals, musical, 285-287 
sensations connected with, 
289 sqq. 
I ntr ejection, 28, 51 sqq. 
Intuitive knowledge, 319, 327, 
328 
Inversion, optical, 223 sqq. 
Judgment, process of, 317 sq. 
Labyrinth of the ear, function 
of, 154 sqq. 
Light, electro-magnetic theory 
of, 104 
distribution of, on the retina, 
217 
M 
Matter, not immutable, 312 
= combination of sen- 
sations, 331 
Measurement, standards of, 192 
absolute, 342 
Mechanical systems, 90 
Membranes, vibration of, in 
fluids, 299 sqq. 
Memory, 235-244 
Hering's theory of, 72 
Memory-images, 172 
Memory-traces, analogy of, to 
physical traces, 236 
Mice, Japanese, deafness in, 160 
Millipede, 188 
Mole, equilibrium and hearing 
in the, 162 sq. 
Moment, 320 
Motor sensations, 139 sqq., 146, 
!73 
Mouse, blind, equilibrium and 
hearing in, 162 
Music, physiological origin of, 
263 
relation of speech to, 280 sq. 
modern development of, 307 
Musical tones, Helmholtz' 
analysis of, 265 sqq. 
N 
Nervous system, interaction of 
parts of, 241 
Numbers, theory of, dependent 

on physics, 346 
Nystagmus, 158 
Optical space, 168 
Organisms, peculiar charac- 
teristics of, 98 sqq. 
plasticity of, 238 
Otolithic apparatus, the, 153 
sqq. 
Painting, 347 
Italian, 233 
Pompeian, 232 
Pan-psychism, 362 
Perspectives, optical pheno- 
mena connected with, 212 
sqq., 220 sqq., 232 
Physical and psychical, the, 
connexion between, 17, 22 
the, view of relation be- 
tween, identical in Mach 
and Avenarius, 51 sqq. 
the, parallelism of, 60 
the, dualism of, 141 sqq. 
376 
INDEX 
Physics, bearing of physiology 
and psychology on, Bio- 
Physics and biology, connexion 
between, 84 sqq. 
Pigeons, reflex movements in, 
73 
Planetary motions, the, 336 
Pleasure and pain, 21 
Plethysmography, 257 
Pseudoscopy, 225 
Puzzle-pictures, 212 
R 
Reflex movements in animals, 1 
7.3 sqq. 
Relative motion, sensations of, : 
142 sqq. 
Representation, 257 
sensations supplemented by, ! 
199 
Resonance-theory of hearing, 
269 sqq., 303 
Retina, the, 122 sqq. 
movement of images on, 144 
Retinas, " synergy " of, 123 
Rhythm, no symmetry in, 256 \ 
Rhythms, identity of, 258 sqq. \ 
Right and left, distinction of, j 
ii2, 339 
Rotation, phenomena of, 134, ! 
138 sq., 140 sqq., 149 sqq., 
158 
Semicircular canals, the, 149 
sqq. 
Sensations, direction of, 109 
specific, 184 
lower limit of, 243 
sexual, 263 
Sheep, experiments on, 154 
Sight-sensations, 195-234 
Silk- worms, 76 
Similarity, optical and geo- 
metrical, 108 sqq., 115 
Solipsism, 36, 37, 358, 359 
Sound-color, 269 
Sounds, analysis of, 262-309 
Space, 339 
physiological and geometri- 
cal properties of, 120 
visual and conceptual, 124 
optical and geometrical, 168 
geometrical, contrasted with 
physiological, 181 sqq. 
Euclidean, 182 
tactual, 1 86 
tactual and optical homo- 
geneous, 187 
analogy of, to tone-sensa- 
tion, 278, 282 sqq. 
geometrical, 345 
and time, functional inter- 
dependence of, 348 
Sparrow, 74, 171, 196 
Species, preservation of, 81 
Specific energies, 122 sqq., 275 
Specific sense - energies, prin- 
ciple of, 165 
Subject and object, 341, 365 
Substance, what is it ? 328, 333 
Sufficient differentiation, prin- 
ciple of, 58, 319 
Symmetry, 106, 108, in, 114, 
H5 sq. 
in music, 272 n. 
sense of, 170 
Teleology, 80, 83-101 
Temperature, how determined, 
35 
" Thing-in-itself," 6, 361 n. 
" Thought-experiment," 194 
Time, perspectival contraction 
of, 258 
dependent on our sensibility, 
330 
physical, 349 
irreversibility of, 351 
Time-sensation, 244-261 
INDEX 
377 
Tones, fusion of, 274 
Tone-sensations, 262-309 
Touch, sensations of, 135 sqq. 
Tropisms, 241 
U 
Unity of consciousness, 27-29 
Unity of the physical and 
psychical, 339 
Vertigo, optical, 138 
in deaf-mutes, 148 sqq. 
Vertigo, galvanic, 159 sqq. 
rotatory,* 5 9 sqq. 
Vestibular apparatus, the, 154 
Vision, binocular, 125 
W 
Will, the, 23, 100, 171-180 
connexion of, with inner- 
vations, 129 
to move, sensations con- 
nected with, 139 
connexion of, with music, 
262 
freedom of, 351 
II 
INDEX OF NAMES 
Abraham, 268 n. 
Ach, 158 
Allen, Grant, 103 n. 
Alexander, 160-163 
Aristotle, 84, 87, 136 n. 
Aubert, 66 
Auerbach, 268 n. 
Autenrieth, 85 
Avenarius, 27 n., 30 n., 46-56, 
261, 354. 362. 
Bain, 173 
Benndorf, 103 n. 
Beer, 197 n., 230 
Berg, 263 
Berkeley, 48, 135 ., 361, 367 
Bernoulli, J., 121 
Bethe, 196, 197 n. 
Biehl, 154 
Boyle, 174 
Breuer, 131, 132, 137, 140, 153, 
X 54 155. 159, 162, 163, 164 
Brewster, 63, 64 n., 174 n 
Bridgman, Laura, 323, 324 
Brown, Crum, 133, 144, 148 
Briicke, 123, 268 n. 
Briihl, 268 n. 
Buttel-Reepen, 197 
Carus, Paul, 356 n. 
Chesselden, 136 n. 
Comte, 46 
Cornelius, H., 48, 363 
Cornelius, P., 286 
Cossmann, 89 n. 
Cyon, 164 
D 
D'Alembert, 272 n. 
Darwin, 49, 71, 74, 76, 79, 81, 
104 n., 241,. 263 
Delage, 155 
Descartes, 118, 122, 197 
Diderot, 135 n. 
Dove, 123 
378 
INDEX 
Dreyfuss, 161 
Driesch, 80, 98 
Dubois-Reymond, 313 
Du Prel, 255 
Dvorak, 251, 252, 268 n. 
Emch, 119 
Euclid, 168, 181, 190, 191 n. 
Euler, 272 n., 273 n., 290, 307 
Ewald, 149, 153, 158, 164, 241, 
301, 302, 303 
Exner, 145, 228 n., 230, 268 n,, 
369 
Fechner, 61, 81 n., 101 n., 210, 
251 n,, 264 n. 
Fischer, 265 n. 
Forel, 197 
Fourier, 269 
Fraunhofer, 7, 65 n. t 316 
Friesach, 302 
Gay-Lussac, 310 
Geissler, 252 
Goethe, i 
Goltz, 74, 197, 241 
Gomperz, 326, 327 
Govi, 122 n., 149 
Graber, 292 n. 
Grimaldi, 219 
Groth, 67 
Gruithuisen, 4 n. 
Guldberg, 112, 113 
Guye, 148 
H 
Haddon, 117 
Haga, 219 n. 
Hammerschlag, 160 
Hankel, 120 
Harvey, 86 
Hauptmann, C., 48, 61 n., 89 n. 
Hauptmann, M., 272 n. 
Heidenhain, in 
Heller, 136 n., 137 n. 
Helmholtz, 63, 64 n., 117, 126, 
173, 191 n., 263, 265-275, 
291, 292, 297, 298, 299 ., 
301, 305, 306, 370 
Hensen, 88 n., 292 n. 
Herakleitos, 368 
i Herbart, 368 
i Hering, 27 n., 30 n., 50, 65-69, 
72, 80 n., 99 n., 100 n., 109, 
122 n., 124, 125, 139, 168- 
170, 172, 177, 178, 181 n., 
183, 197 n., 225, 277 n. 
\ Hermann, 245 n., 269, 270, 271, 
303 
1 Hero, 87 
Herodotos, 321 n. 
\ Herzfeld, 67 n. 
| Heymans, 61 n., 226, 252 n. 
I Hillebrand, 125 n., 177 n. t 
221 n. 
Hirth, 99 n., 136 n. 
Hofler, 55 n., 226 
Honigswald, 367 
Holtz, 96 n., 131 
Hume, 4 n., 46, 356 n., 368 
Huppert, 371 n. 
James, 21, 129, 144, 148, 159, 
163, 168 n., 173, 175 n. t 
176, 179, 181 n., 257, 310 . 
Jerusalem, 318 n., 323, 324 n. 
Jones, 116 
K 
Kant, 30 n., 194. 325. 357' 3 61 
n., 367 
Kepler, 86, 334, 336 
Kessel, 279 n. 
King, 174 n. 
Kirchhoff, 49 
Kohlrausch, 268 n. 
Konig, 269, 270 
Kornfeld, 257 n. 
Krause, E., 103 n. 
Krause, C. F., 20 n. 
INDEX 
379 
Kreidl, 132, 153, 157, 159, 160, 
162, 163 
Kries, von, 61 n., 69 n., 327 
Kiilke, 286 
Kiilpe, 61 n., 89 n. 
Laplace, 313 
Leibniz, 191 n., 273 n. 
Leonardo da Vinci, 66, 67, 206, 
287 
Lichtenberg, 28, 356 n. 
Lipps, 131 n., 262 n., 273 n. 
Lissajous, 232 
Locke, 135 n., 318 
Loeb, 86, 98, 113, 137 n , 153, 
196, 221, 224, 226, 241, 
247 n. 
Loewy, 135 n. 
Lubbock, 149 
Ludwig, 66 
M 
Magnus, 103 n. 
Manacei'ne, 255 
Mariotte, 39, 310 
Marty, 103 n. 
Maxwell, 247 n. 
Mayer, A., 64 
Mayer, J. R., 341 
Meinong, 346 n. 
Menger, 98 
Meumann, 245 n. 
Meyer, 270 .' 
Meynert, 261 
Mill, 92, 335 n., 363 
Moliere, 37, 119 
Molyneux, 135 n. 
Morgan, 76, 77 
Moser, 237 
Mosso, 257 
Munk, 135 n. 
Miiller, 27, 59, 122, 125, 126, 
202, 203 
Miinsterberg, 168 n., 173, 176, 
Mygin 
245 n., 252 
d, 159 
N 
Nagel, 132, 153, 155, 165 
Newton, 49, 64, 92, 121, 174, 
307, 334. 336, 337 
Nichols, 245 n. 
Nietzsche, 25 
Obermayer, von, 219 n. 
Oettingen, von, 271, 272, 275, 
297 
Ohm, 265 
Oppel, 144, 273 n. 
Ostwald, 99 n., 239 n. 
Panum, 123, 126, 217, 229 
Pauli, 68, 69, 83 n., 112 n., 253 
Petzold, 36 n., 48, 350, 351, 352 
Pfaundler, 268 n. 
Pfeffer, 94 
Plateau, 134, 144, 223 
Plato, ii 
Polak, 273 n. 
Politzer, 299 
Pollak, 153, 159 
Polle, 103 n. 
Poncelet, 341 
Popper, 20 n., 30 n. 
Poulton, 96 n. 
Prentiss, 157 
Preyer, 31 n. 
Ptolemy, 122 
Purkinje, 133, 186, 252 
R 
Rameau, 265 
Reimarus, 85 
Reinke, 98 
Ribbert, 371 n. 
Ribot, 4, 21, 326, 327 
Riehl, 31 n., 139 
Riemann, 181 
Robert, 254 
3 8o 
Rollett, 73, 371 
Roux, 95, 99 n. 
INDEX 
Sachs, 86 
Sandford, 252 
Saunderson, 136 n. 
Sauveur, 265 
Schafer, 153, 158 
Schaik, van, 88 n. 
Scheffler, 228 
Schlodtmann, 126 n. 
Schmidt, 6 n. 
Schnabel, 135 n. 
Schneider, 77 
Schopenhauer, i, 82 ., 262 
Schultz, 104 n. 
Schumann, 245 n. 
Schuppe, 6 n., 36 n., 46 
Schuster, 71 
Scripture, 206, 245 n. 
Seebeck, 290 
Seeliger, 219 n. 
Semon, 72 w. 
Smith, Adam, 49 
Smith, R., 265 
Soret, 117, 118, 122, 136 n. 
Spencer, 71, 77 
Spinoza, 46 
Staudt, von, 200 
Steiner, 200 
Stern, 324 n. 
Steinhauser, 265 . 
Stohr, 227, 228, 229, 230, 303, 
318 w. 
Strauss, 75 
Strehl, 1 60 
Strieker, 280, 335 n. 
Stumpf, 61 n., 126 n., 262 n. t 
270 w., 272, 273, 274, 290 
n., 293, 298, 299 
Suess, 236 
Szily, von, 146 n. 
Tolstoi, 112 
Tschermak, 126 n. 
Tylor, 52 n., 56 
U 
Uexkiill, 197 w. 
Vergil, 104 n. 
Vierordt, 145 
Volkmann, 49 
W 
Wahle, 31 n. 
Wallaschek, 246 n.. 255 n., 
260, 261, 309 w. 
Wasmann, 199 
Weber, 81 n., 299 
Weismann, 24, 72, 73, 77, 78, 
308 
Wheatstone, 123 
Whitney, 322 n. 
Wilner/95 
Wind, 219 n. 
Witasek, 226 w. 
Wlassak, 50, 56, 181 n., 261 
Wollaston, 65 
Wundt, 173 
Young, 64, 265, 269, 305, 341 
Zell, 96 n., 197 
Ziegler, 240 . 
Zindler, 346 n. 
Zollner, 225, 226 
TURNBULL AND SPEARS, PRINTERS, EDINBURGH